Constitutional History of England by Henry Hallam - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

CHAPTER VII

ON THE ENGLISH CONSTITUTION FROM THE ACCESSION OF

CHARLES I. TO THE DISSOLUTION OF HIS THIRD PARLIAMENT

1625-1629

Charles the First had much in his character very suitable to the times

in which he lived, and to the spirit of the people he was to rule; a

stern and serious deportment, a disinclination to all licentiousness,

and a sense of religion that seemed more real than in his father.[629]

These qualities we might suppose to have raised some expectation of

him, and to have procured at his accession some of that popularity,

which is rarely withheld from untried princes. Yet it does not appear

that he enjoyed even this first transient sunshine of his subjects'

affection. Solely intent on retrenching the excesses of prerogative,

and well aware that no sovereign would voluntarily recede from the

possession of power, they seem to have dreaded to admit into their

bosoms any sentiments of personal loyalty, which might enervate

their resolution. And Charles took speedy means to convince them

that they had not erred in withholding their confidence.

Elizabeth in her systematic parsimony, James in his averseness to

war, had been alike influenced by a consciousness that want of

money alone could render a parliament formidable to their power.

None of the irregular modes of supply were ever productive enough

to compensate for the clamour they occasioned; after impositions and

benevolences were exhausted, it had always been found necessary,

in the most arbitrary times of the Tudors, to fall back on the

representatives of the people. But Charles succeeded to a war, at

least to the preparation of a war, rashly undertaken through his own

weak compliance, the arrogance of his favourite, and the generous or

fanatical zeal of

348

the last parliament. He would have perceived it to be manifestly

impossible, if he had been capable of understanding his own position,

to continue this war without the constant assistance of the House of

Commons, or to obtain that assistance without very costly sacrifices

of his royal power. It was not the least of this monarch's imprudences,

or rather of his blind compliances with Buckingham, to have not only

commenced hostilities against Spain which he might easily have

avoided,[630] and persisted in them for four years, but entered on a fresh war with France, though he had abundant experience to

demonstrate the impossibility of defraying its charges.

Parliament of 1625. —The first parliament of this reign has been

severely censured on account of the penurious supply it doled out for

the exigencies of a war, in which its predecessors had involved the

king. I will not say that this reproach is wholly unfounded. A more

liberal proceeding, if it did not obtain a reciprocal concession from the

king, would have put him more in the wrong. But, according to the

common practice and character of all such assemblies, it was

preposterous to expect subsidies equal to the occasion, until a

foundation of confidence should be laid between the Crown and

parliament. The Commons had begun probably to repent of their

hastiness in the preceding year, and to discover that Buckingham and

his pupil, or master (which shall we say?), had conspired to deceive

them.[631] They were not to forget that none of the chief grievances of the last reign were yet redressed, and that supplies must be voted

slowly and conditionally if they would hope for reformation. Hence

they made their grant of tonnage and poundage to last but for a year

instead of the king's life, as had for two centuries been the practice;

on which account the upper house rejected the bill.[632] Nor would they have refused a further supply, beyond the two subsidies (about

£140,000) which they had granted, had some tender of redress been

made

349

by the Crown; and were actually in debate upon the matter, when

interrupted by a sudden dissolution.[633]

Nothing could be more evident, by the experience of the late reign as

well as by observing the state of public spirit, than that hasty and

premature dissolutions or prorogations of parliament served but to

aggravate the Crown's embarrassments. Every successive House of

Commons inherited the feelings of its predecessor, without which it

would have ill represented the prevalent humour of the nation. The

same men, for the most part, came again to parliament more irritated

and desperate of reconciliation with the sovereign than before. Even

the politic measure, as it was fancied to be, of excluding some of the

most active members from seats in the new assembly, by nominating

them sheriffs for the year, failed altogether of the expected success;

as it naturally must in an age when all ranks partook in a common

enthusiasm.[634] Hence the prosecution against Buckingham, to avert which Charles had dissolved his first parliament, was commenced

with redoubled vigour in the second. It was too late, after the

precedents of Bacon and Middlesex, to dispute the right of the

Commons to impeach a minister of state. The king, however,

anticipating their resolutions, after some sharp speeches only had

been uttered against his favourite, sent a message that he would not

allow any of his servants to be questioned among them, much less

such as were of eminent place and near unto him. He saw, he said,

that some of them aimed at the Duke of Buckingham, whom, in the

last parliament of his father, all had combined to honour and respect,

nor did he know what had happened since to alter their affections; but

he assured them that the duke had done nothing without his own

special direction and appointment. This haughty message so

provoked the Commons that, having no express testimony against

Buckingham, they came to a vote that common fame is a good

ground of proceeding either by inquiry, or presenting the complaint to

the king or Lords; nor

350

did a speech from the lord keeper, severely rating their presumption,

and requiring on the king's behalf that they should punish two of their

members who had given him offence by insolent discourses in the

house, lest he should be compelled to use his royal authority against

them; nor one from the king himself, bidding them remember that

parliaments were altogether in his power for their calling, sitting, and

dissolution; therefore, as he found the fruits of them good or evil, they

were to continue to be or not to be, tend to pacify or to intimidate the

assembly. They addressed the king in very decorous language, but

asserting "the ancient, constant, and undoubted right and usage of

parliaments to question and complain of all persons, of what degree

soever, found grievous to the commonwealth, in abusing the power

and trust committed to them by their sovereign."[635] The duke was accordingly impeached at the bar of the house of peers on eight

articles, many of them probably well-founded; yet as the Commons

heard no evidence in support of them, it was rather unreasonable in

them to request that he might be committed to the Tower.

In the conduct of this impeachment, two of the managers, Sir John

Eliot and Sir Dudley Digges, one the most illustrious confessor in the

cause of liberty, whom that time produced, the other, a man of much

ability and a useful supporter of the popular party, though not exempt

from some oblique views towards promotion, gave such offence by

words spoken, or alleged to be spoken, in derogation of his majesty's

honour, that they were committed to the Tower. The Commons, of

course, resented this new outrage. They resolved to do no more

business till they were righted in their privileges. They denied the

words imputed to Digges; and, thirty-six peers

351

asserting that he had not spoken them, the king admitted that he was

mistaken, and released both their members.[636] He had already broken in upon the privileges of the House of Lords, by committing

the Earl of Arundel to the Tower during the session; not upon any

political charge, but, as was commonly surmised, on account of a

marriage which his son had made with a lady of royal blood. Such

private offences were sufficient in those arbitrary reigns to expose the

subject to indefinite imprisonment, if not to an actual sentence in the

star-chamber. The Lords took up this detention of one of their body,

and after formal examination of precedents by a committee, came to

a resolution, "that no lord of parliament, the parliament sitting, or

within the usual times of privilege of parliament, is to be imprisoned or

restrained without sentence or order of the house, unless it be for

treason or felony, or for refusing to give surety for the peace." This

assertion of privilege was manifestly warranted by the co-extensive

liberties of the Commons. After various messages between the king

and Lords, Arundel was ultimately set at liberty.[637]

This infringement of the rights of the peerage was accompanied by

another not less injurious, the refusal of a writ of summons to the Earl

of Bristol. The Lords were justly tenacious of this unquestionable

privilege of their order, without which its constitutional dignity and

independence could never be maintained. Whatever irregularities or

uncertainty of legal principle might be found in earlier times as to

persons summoned only by writ without patents of creation,

concerning whose hereditary peerage there is much reason to doubt;

it was beyond all controversy that an Earl of Bristol holding his dignity

by patent was entitled of right to attend parliament. The house

necessarily insisted upon Bristol's receiving his summons, which was

sent him with an injunction not to comply with it by taking his place.

But the spirited earl knew that the king's constitutional will expressed

in the writ ought to outweigh his private

352

command, and laid the secretary's letter before the House of Lords.

The king prevented any further interference in his behalf by causing

articles of charge to be exhibited against him by the attorney-general,

whereon he was committed to the Tower. These assaults on the pride

and consequence of an aristocratic assembly, from whom alone the

king could expect effectual support, display his unfitness not only for

the government of England, but of any other nation. Nor was his

conduct towards Bristol less oppressive than impolitic. If we look at

the harsh and indecent employment of his own authority and even

testimony, to influence a criminal process against a man of approved

and untainted worth,[638] and his sanction of charges which, if Bristol's defence be as true as it is now generally admitted to be, he must

have known to be unfounded; we shall hardly concur with those

candid persons who believe that Charles would have been an

excellent prince in a more absolute monarchy. Nothing in truth can be

more preposterous than to maintain, like Clarendon and Hume, the

integrity and innocence of Lord Bristol, together with the sincerity and

humanity of Charles I. Such inconsistencies betray a determination in

the historian to speak of men according to his preconceived affection

or prejudice, without so much as attempting to reconcile these

sentiments to the facts which he can neither deny nor excuse.[639]

353

Though the Lords petitioned against a dissolution, the king was

determined to protect his favourite, and rescue himself from the

importunities of so refractory a House of Commons.[640] Perhaps he had already taken the resolution of governing without the

concurrence of parliaments, though he was induced to break it the

ensuing year. For the Commons having delayed to pass a bill for the

five subsidies they had voted in this session till they should obtain

some satisfaction for their complaints, he was left without any regular

supply. This was not wholly unacceptable to some of his counsellors,

and probably to himself; as affording a pretext for those unauthorised

demands which the advocates of arbitrary prerogative deemed more

consonant to the monarch's honour. He had issued letters of privy

seal, after the former parliament, to those in every county, whose

names had been returned by the lord lieutenant as most capable,

mentioning the sum they were required to lend, with a promise of

repayment in eighteen months.[641] This specification of a particular sum was reckoned an unusual encroachment, and a manifest breach

of the statute against arbitrary benevolences; especially as the name

of those who refused compliance were to be returned to the council.

But the government now ventured on a still more outrageous stretch

of power. They first attempted to persuade the people that, as

subsidies had been voted in the House of Commons, they should not

refuse to pay them, though no bill had been passed for that purpose.

But a tumultuous cry was raised in Westminster Hall from those who

had been convened, that they would pay no subsidy but by authority

of parliament.[642] This course, therefore, was 354

abandoned for one hardly less unconstitutional. A general loan was

demanded from every subject, according to the rate at which he was

assessed in the last subsidy. The commissioners appointed for the

collection of this loan received private instructions to require not less

than a certain proportion of each man's property in lands or goods, to

treat separately with every one, to examine on oath such as should

refuse, to certify the names of refractory persons to the privy council,

and to admit of no excuse for abatement of the sum required.[643]

Arbitrary taxation. —This arbitrary taxation (for the name of loan could

not disguise the extreme improbability that the money would be

repaid), so general and systematic as well as so weighty, could not

be endured without establishing a precedent that must have shortly

put an end to the existence of parliaments. For, if those assemblies

were to meet only for the sake of pouring out stupid flatteries at the

foot of the throne, of humbly tendering such supplies as the ministry

should suggest, or even of hinting at a few subordinate grievances

which touched not the king's prerogative and absolute control in

matters of state—functions which the Tudors and Stuarts were well

pleased that they should exercise—if every remonstrance was to be

checked by a dissolution, and chastised by imprisonment of its

promoters, every denial of subsidy to furnish a justification for

extorted loans, our free-born high-minded gentry would not long have

brooked to give their attendance in such an ignominious assembly,

and an English parliament would have

355

become as idle a mockery of national representation as the cortes of

Castile. But this kingdom was not in a temper to put up with tyranny.

The king's advisers were as little disposed to recede from their

attempt. They prepared to enforce it by the arm of power.[644] The common people who refused to contribute were impressed to serve in

the navy. The gentry were bound by recognisance to appear at the

council-table, where many of them were committed to prison.[645]

Among these were five knights, Darnel, Carbet, Earl, Heveningham,

and Hampden, who sued the court of king's bench for their writ of

habeas corpus. The writ was granted; but the warden of the Fleet

made return that they were detained by a warrant from the privy

council, informing him of no particular cause of imprisonment, but that

they were committed by the special command of his majesty. This

gave rise to a most important question, whether such a return was

sufficient in law to justify the court in remitting the parties to custody.

The fundamental immunity of English subjects from arbitrary

detention had never before been so fully canvassed; and it is to the

discussion which arose out of the case of these five gentlemen that

we owe its continual assertion by parliament, and its ultimate

establishment in full practical efficacy by the statute of Charles II. It

was argued with great ability by Noy, Selden, and other eminent

356

lawyers, on behalf of the claimants, and by the attorney-general

Heath for the Crown.

The counsel for the prisoners grounded their demand of liberty on the

original basis of Magna Charta; the twenty-ninth section of which, as

is well known, provides that "no free man shall be taken or

imprisoned unless by lawful judgment of his peers, or the law of the

land." This principle having been frequently transgressed by the

king's privy council in earlier times, statutes had been repeatedly

enacted, independently of the general confirmations of the charter, to

redress this material grievance. Thus in the 25th of Edward III. it is

provided that "no one shall be taken by petition or suggestion to the

king or his counsel, unless it be ( i.e. but only) by indictment or

presentment, or by writ original at the common law." And this is again

enacted three years afterwards, with little variation, and once again in

the course of the same reign. It was never understood, whatever the

loose language of these old statutes might suggest, that no man

could be kept in custody upon a criminal charge before indictment,

which would have afforded too great security to offenders. But it was

the regular practice that every warrant of commitment, and every

return by a gaoler to the writ of habeas corpus, must express the

nature of the charge, so that it might appear whether it were no legal

offence; in which case the party must be instantly set at liberty; or one

for which bail ought to be taken, or one for which he must be

remanded to prison. It appears also to have been admitted without

controversy, though not perhaps according to the strict letter of law,

that the privy council might commit to prison on a criminal charge,

since it seemed preposterous to deny that power to those intrusted

with the care of the commonwealth, which every petty magistrate

enjoyed. But it was contended that they were as much bound as

every petty magistrate to assign such a cause for their commitments

as might enable the court of king's bench to determine whether it

should release or remand the prisoners brought before them by

habeas corpus.

The advocates for this principal alleged several precedents, from the

reign of Henry VII. to that of James, where persons committed by the

council generally, or even by the special command of the king, had

been admitted to bail on their habeas corpus. "But I conceive," said

one of these, "that our case will not stand upon precedent, but upon

the fundamental laws and statutes of this realm; and though the

precedents look one way or the other, they are to be brought back

357

unto the laws by which the kingdom is governed." He was aware that

a pretext might be found to elude most of his precedents. The warrant

had commonly declared the party to be charged on suspicion of

treason or of felony; in which case he would of course be bailed by

the court. Yet in some of these instances the words "by the king's

special command," were inserted in the commitment; so that they

served to repel the pretension of an arbitrary right to supersede the

law by his personal authority. Ample proof was brought from the old

law books that the king's command could not excuse an illegal act. "If

the king command me," said one of the judges under Henry VI., "to

arrest a man, and I arrest him, he shall have an action of false

imprisonment against me, though it were done in the king's

presence." "The king," said Chief Justice Markham to Edward IV.,

"cannot arrest a man upon suspicion of felony or treason, as any of

his subjects may; because if he should wrong a man by such arrest,

he can have no remedy against him." No verbal order of the king, nor

any under his sign manual or privy signet, was a command, it was

contended by Selden, which the law would recognise as sufficient to

arrest or detain any of his subjects; a writ duly issued under the seal

of a court being the only language in which he could signify his will.

They urged further that, even if the first commitment by the king's

command were lawful, yet when a party had continued in prison for a

reasonable time, he should be brought to answer, and not be

indefinitely detained; liberty being a thing so favoured by the law that

it will not suffer any man to remain in confinement for any longer time

than of necessity it must.

To these pleadings for liberty, Heath, the attorney-general, replied in

a speech of considerable ability, full of those high principles of

prerogative which, trampling as it were on all statute and precedent,

seemed to tell the judges that they were placed there to obey rather

than to determine. "This commitment," he says, "is not in a legal and

ordinary way, but by the special command of our lord the king, which

implies not only the fact done, but so extraordinarily done, that it is

notoriously his majesty's immediate act and will that it should be so."

He alludes afterwards, though somewhat obscurely, to the king's

absolute power, as contra-distinguished from that according to law; a

favourite distinction, as I have already observed, with the supporters

of despotism. "Shall we make inquiries," he says, "whether his

commands are lawful?—who shall call in

358

question the justice of the king's actions, who is not to give account

for them?" He argues from the legal maxim that the king can do no

wrong, that a cause must be presumed to exist for the commitment,

though it be not set forth. He adverts with more success to the

number of papists and other state prisoners, detained for years in

custody for mere political jealousy. "Some there were," he says, "in

the Tower who were put in it when very young; should they bring a

habeas corpus, would the court deliver them?" Passing next to the

precedents of the other side, and condescending to admit their

validity, however contrary to the tenor of his former argument, he

evades their application by such distinctions as I have already

mentioned.

The judges behaved during this great cause with apparent

moderation and sense of its importance to the subject's freedom.

Their decision, however, was in favour of the Crown; and the

prisoners were remanded to custody. In pronouncing this judgment,

the chief justice, Sir Nicholas Hyde, avoiding the more extravagant

tenets of absolute monarchy, took the narrower line of denying the

application of