The psychology of Nations by G.E. Partridge - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

CHAPTER VII

POLITICAL EDUCATION IN A DEMOCRACY

One of the results of the war has been to raise in the minds of all

peoples, to an extraordinary degree, the most earnest questions about

the nature and validity of government. The political sense of all

peoples has been stimulated. We see on every hand new conceptions of

government and demands for more and better government, but also the

most radical criticism and the denial of all government.

The

determination in very fundamental ways of what government is, and must

be, what ideas must prevail, what must be suppressed, what an ideal

government is, if such an ideal can be formed, the question of evils

inherent in the idea of government itself (if such evils there be),

the laws of development of government in all their practical

aspects--all these questions now come up for examination, and will not

be repressed. If we do not take them at one level we must upon

another. Naively or scientifically, philosophically or radically, the

nature of government must be dealt with.

Government is now being examined, we all see, from points of view not

hitherto taken. The conscientious objector raises the question of the

ultimate basis of the right of the many to control the lives of

individuals, and he asks especially whether there is any ground for

the assumption that in this sphere, more than in any other, might

makes right. Conscription, in fact, has driven us to consider the

meaning of liberty and the foundations upon which the right to it

rests. This stern fact of conscription, the realization that in a

moment the most democratic governments in the world are capable of

bringing to bear, quite constitutionally, absolute control over the

most basic possessions of the individual, has led many to ask

seriously whether government is after all a good in itself, or is

merely a necessity having many attendant evils. They wish to know

whether there is in the principle of government something that takes

precedence over all the assumed rights of the individual. Does

government, they inquire, have a _right_ to the individual; or is it

only in _serving_ the individual that it is entitled to exercise

authority that limits the individual?

These are questions, manifestly, that involve the whole foundation of

sociology, but we need not be unduly dismayed at that.

This is a time

when naïve thinking and exact science must make compromises with one

another. For better or for worse we must find some working hypothesis

upon which a fair adjustment may be made in the practical life of the

present moment. This _working hypothesis_ must also serve--and perhaps

that is after all its main function--as something to guide us,

something having solidity upon which we can stand, in performing our

work as educators.

What we need, what we believe all feel now the need of, is a

conception of government satisfying to the multitude of common people.

We wish to know whether we live for the state, we say, or whether the

state lives for us. We wish to understand what the basic rights and

duties of the individual are. As average individuals, willing to give

service in any cause that seems good, we do not ask so much to have

determined for us precisely what type of government best satisfies the

requirements of science or philosophy, but what the best working basis

for harmonious adjustment in the social life of the future is to be.

These enquiring moods on the part of the people are a part of the

temperament that has issued from the war. We shall make a mistake if

we regard it as a mere passing effect, however; _it means a deep

stirring of the political consciousness of people throughout the

world_.

Significant differences may be observed in the general attitude toward

government among the people in the great nations of the world. Each

nation appears to have its own political temperament, and this quite

apart from the views represented especially by political parties and

the like, and quite independently of the scientific and philosophical

conceptions of government and its functions of which there are a great

number, and among them certainly no agreement upon the main issues and

values.

Taking public opinion as a whole, Germany, England, France and America

seem to represent distinctly different attitudes toward government. The

State in the German philosophy of life, as every one is now aware, is

all; the individual derives his reality and his value, so to speak,

from the idea of the supreme state. Individuality and freedom in this

philosophy of life do not refer to _political_

individuality and

freedom at all. In England, and perhaps to some extent in all

democratic countries, the prevailing thought seems to be that the

government that governs the least is, on the whole, the best

government. The English government is supposed to be the servant of the

people, and the individual has been in the habit of looking to the

government for many services. The individual, free and self-determined,

is the unit of value and of society, and the regulation of his conduct

by government is at best a necessary evil. It came as a surprise to the

Englishman when he realized that the state could command the most

personal service and the most complete surrender of the property rights

of the individual.

Le Bon says that the Frenchman, too, thinks of the state as something

to be kept at a minimum and to a certain extent to be opposed.

Opposition to the government is a part of the Frenchman's plan of

life. Boutroux says the same--that in France the habit of thinking of

the government and of society as two rivals has not been overcome.

Our own idea of government is certainly somewhat different from these.

We are watchful of individual right, but we do not tend to think of

government either as opponent or as servant. We do not ask the

government to take care of us as individuals, and we do not feel in

the public attitude the resistance to government that the French

writers observe in France. The American expects on the whole to look

out for his own interests and he has never felt the pressure and

over-powering force of government--until perhaps now.

Mabie says that

the American has conceived of his government as existing to keep the

house in order while the family lived its life freely, every

individual following the bent of his own genius.

These temperamental attitudes toward government, we said, seem quite

apart from scientific and philosophic conceptions of state. We see,

however, something of the temperament reflected in the philosophies.

Philosophers do not wholly detach themselves from the mores of their

race. The monarchy of Germany, Munsterberg says, appeals to the _moral

personality and the æsthetic imagination_. Its main function, however,

is to safeguard the German people. Its faults are the faults of its

virtues. Other German writers praise the German government especially

for its efficiency, for its incomparable body of officials--indeed for

its very clock-work perfection that Bergson hates in Prussian life.

Lehmann goes so far as to say that the German state had reached the

_perfect balance_ between individualism and communism.

These writers

see plenty of self-realization in German society, and quite enough of

participation, on the part of the individual, in the government.

Schmoller (51) denies that Germany ever lacked the spirit of free

institutions, and even compares Germany with ancient Attica, which he

thinks was great not because of the rule of the _demos_, but because

the people followed their aristocratic leaders.

Troeltsch tries to

show that the German idea of freedom is different from, and indeed

superior to, that of all other peoples. The French, he says, rest

their idea of freedom upon the doctrine of the equality of all

citizens, but in reality lawyers and plutocrats prevail.

The English

idea of freedom comes from Puritanic ideas; the individual's

independence of the state is based upon the idea of natural rights,

and upon the theory of the creation of the state by the individual.

But German freedom is something entirely different. Here freedom is in

education, and in the spiritual content of individuality. German

freedom is the freedom that comes from the spontaneous recognition of

rights and duties. Parliaments are good in their place, but after all

they are not the essence of freedom.

Totally different conceptions of state are easily found.

Consider, for

example, the views of Russell. Through every page of his book there

shines the determined belief in the inalienable rights of the

individual. Self-expression of the individual through creative

activity is the basic value, or at least the fundamental means of

realizing values. Russell sees nothing sacred or final in any form of

existing government. He would like to see government expanded in some

directions and contracted in others, for the functions of government

cannot all be vested in one body or organization. For defense the

nation is _not large enough_. For all civic government the nation is

_too large_. In its internal control it treats the individual too

ruthlessly. Wasteful and in large part even unnecessary, it

antagonizes the free development of the individual.

Government should

cease its oppression, it should no longer support unnatural property

rights, or interfere with the personal affairs of individuals. At the

present time, however, we should not expect a radical cure for all the

evils of government. If only we can find the right direction in which

to make advance, we should be satisfied with something less perfect

than an ideal.

The state in Russell's view, instead of being an ideal institution, is

even harmful in many ways and terribly destructive. It promotes war.

It makes the individual helpless, and crushes him with a sense of his

unimportance. It abets the injustice of capitalism. It excludes

citizens from any participation in foreign affairs. We must indeed not

let this incubus of state overwhelm us. We must keep it in its proper

place, even in performing its necessary functions, such as preserving

public health. It is better to take some risk, even in such matters,

than to override too much the individual's personal rights. All the

functions of the state must be made to center more about the welfare

of the individual, and in doing this the state must plainly regard as

fundamental the right of the individual to free growth and the

development of all his powers. We must learn to think more in terms of

individual welfare and less in terms of national pride.

In syndicalism in some form Russell sees the most promise for reform

of government. Some type of government at least which does not make

the geographical unit the basis of everything must be the government

of the future. This would lead in the end to a higher state than that

based primarily upon law, for it would be a government in which free

organization would be the first principle.

Plainly we are to-day in a time of flux in which ideas and

institutions are unsettled, and there is a great variety of political

theories of all kinds. We can hope to find no agreement among

theorists and certainly no common ground for the reconciliation of

conflicting parties. Still, even for the most practical daily life we

must find some guiding principles. We must look for some means of

bringing order out of the present diversity and conflict. Some

valuation of government, some idea of the ultimate purpose of

government ought to be agreed upon, if for no other reason that we may

have some principle which will give us continuity in our educational

work.

Consider the varieties of political creed now offered us, and there

can be little doubt both of the difficulty and the necessity of

finding guiding principles for the practical life and to preserve

sanity of mind. The monarchical idea still lingers; there is a variety

of conceptions of democracy, differing widely; there are socialists--state socialists, Marxian socialists of the old line,

Bolshevists, regionalists, syndicalists, and others--and anarchists of

pure blood. Of internal and party differences, policies, and plans

there is no end. Through all these we have to thread our way, and

reach what conclusions we can.

No American can of course be expected to see the question of

government otherwise than through American eyes. He is to some extent

prejudiced and bound to the ideas of liberty, individualism, and

democracy, whatever his variety of party politics be.

Democracy he may

regard as an assumption, but it will seem now even more than ever a

necessary assumption upon which to build a working conception of

government.

We have to look somewhere in actual life for the elements and

principles of government. Why should we not look for them in American

life, where government has grown up comparatively free from traditions

and prejudices and where it has been by all the ordinary tests

_successful_? There has been something both ideal and generic in

American life. Whatever personal equation may be involved in saying

this, the point of view has some objective justification. It is a

genetic method, at least. In early American life society was simple,

and life was earnest, and we see government and the individual in

their essential relations to one another.

In this primitive and yet modern society we see the individual as a

collection of functions, so to speak, existing in a group. The

individual also has various desires, which do not appear to be wholly

in agreement with his social functions. Some of these desires of

individuals are strongly antagonistic to society. In this society,

government is plainly the means of protecting the individual or the

group, by the suggestion or the exertion of lawful force, from the

threat of lawless force. Law is a means of enabling and also

compelling the individual _to perform the various functions which_

belong to him as an individual or as a member of the group. To some

extent the law also _aids_ the individual in performing his functions.

But this simple social order already shows certain basic disharmonies.

It is an experimental regulation of the individual.

Every restriction

the individual helps to put upon other individuals by participating in

or acquiescing in the establishment of government and law reacts to

limit his own freedom, in ways which he cannot wholly predict. Freedom

of the individual, even in the simplest social order, becomes greatly

limited, if not necessarily, at least naturally--and indeed

necessarily, since the only choice appears to be between lawful and

lawless limitation of freedom. From the beginning, therefore, there

can be no perfect satisfaction of individual desires or of either

general or individual needs, in the ordered social life.

Society as a

whole regulates the conduct of the individual both by aiding and by

inhibiting his activities, and must do so. In doing this, it is plain,

it promotes all or most of the functions of the individual. Ordered

society widens the total sphere of action of the individual. The

individual left to himself tends to become an end-in-himself. Law

makes him to a greater extent a means. In doing this it serves him and

it also uses him, and there can never be any guarantee, in any

individual case, of what the sum of these services and restraints

shall be. Society uses the individual in part, but not exclusively, in

his own service. The good and the evil, the necessity and the dilemma

of all government are outgrowths of this primitive service of the

social organization and this original disharmony among the wills of

individuals and the will of the group to serve the individual and also

at the same time certain general purposes which may not in any given

case coincide with either the desire or the need of the individual.

For this reason we conclude that there can be no _perfect_ government.

All government is experimental and exists by compromise.

What, then, in the most general way, can we say is the legitimate

function or purpose of government? Hocking says that government is the

means of assuring the individual that his achievements will be

permanent. To this end it puts order into the structure of society. In

our view something similar, but not identical with this, is true. We

can say that in its complex forms it is in principle only what we

found it to be in its primitive or simple forms.

_Government is

ideally a means of aiding all the functions of every individual._

_Functions_, let us observe and not primarily desires are served.

These functions are such functions as the individual has as a member

of every group to which he naturally belongs.

Government, then, so to

speak, has no standing of its own. Its proper function is to

facilitate all other functions. Neither individuals nor governments

have any rights as abstracted from the sum of functions which they

essentially are.

If this be true, we can certainly define no one best and eternal type

of government, any more than a fixed and perfect plan of life for an

individual can be defined. Government might be supposed properly to

change according to the functions which from time to time were most

important for the society in question. Social life, under government,

differs from a free and unorganized social life mainly in that a

certain _objectivity_ is acquired in regard to the functions of the

individual. The individual becomes a creature of functions rather than

of desires and needs. Common interests, or the interests of the group

are served, we say; in doing this the individual is made to serve his

own interests, perhaps, but the most outstanding fact is that in this

organized life the _immediate desires of the individual are likely to

be thwarted_. Regularity is put into conduct, and conduct is made to

serve multiple and distant ends. The functions of the individual, left

to the desire of the individual, will seldom be harmoniously

performed. They will lack precisely objective consideration. But in

the organized social life there will also be no perfect order and

harmony, no final balance of functions. Everything is still relative

and experimental. Government is a system in which any one individual

at any moment may gain or may lose. But _on the whole_, under the good

government, both more freedom for the individual and better conditions

and better life for the individual will presumably be obtained than in

any possible disordered or unorganized society. But government will

really add nothing that does not already belong to the functions that

naturally develop in any social group.

The actual functions of governments are, therefore, highly complex,

because it is in some way involved in all the functions of the

individuals themselves. Governments will be judged good or bad in two

particulars: according to the completeness with which they include all

the social functions, and as regards their efficiency in facilitating

these functions. We must not make the mistake of judging a government

merely by its form. Under the same constitution and holding the same

ideals, there is room for widely different forms of activity on the

part of the government, and great differences in efficiency and in the

functions performed. The same functions may be performed and the same

degree of efficiency reached apparently with different organizations.

Cleveland shows, for example, how our own government might become much

more efficient and make radical changes in the mechanism of the

legislative and executive functions without sacrificing any principle

we hold to, and perhaps without any change in our constitution.

It is this idea of the proper functions of government and the relative

adequacy of existing governments to perform them that seems to be

deeply questioned. Life has suddenly grown more complex.

The

individual is brought face to face with new demands upon him. He

becomes, it may be, a member of new groups, having new functions.

Government also, and correspondingly, expands. The question is not now

of the efficiency of government in doing what it has hitherto

undertaken; we wish to feel sure that government is adequate to meet

the requirements of a rapidly changing social order.

That just now is

indeed a very vital question. Governments, we say, may be obliged to

adapt themselves to entirely new tasks. Society assumes new external

relations, and therefore we should expect that new organs would be

needed for performing these new functions.

In all this we have been making _objective_ valuations of government.

An ideal or a definition of government in terms of its functions and

the degree of efficiency in the performance of them might still, we

ought to observe, leave a wide scope for preference in regard to

forms, and other subjective valuations. Even between aristocratic and

democratic forms, there may be still room for valid appreciations on

æsthetic or moral grounds. Our objective valuations of government must

in fact in various ways impinge upon fundamental questions in which no

purely scientific considerations will be wholly decisive.

We can certainly find no precise way of valuing in detail or in their

totality existing or proposed forms of government. Our most valid

method, however, appears to be to refer at every step the functions of

government back to the functions of the individuals who make up

society. Every phase of legitimate government must thus go back to the

individual, and his desires and functions. If we do this we shall see

again why in national life we have the same kind of experimental

problem that we have in the life of the individual.

There can be no

perfect adjustment among the acts of an individual, and no final

valuation of them. There is no perfect balance between present use and

future good, between individual and social values, between desires or

needs and functions. The reason for this, we say, is that life is so

complicated and made up of so many functions and of so many

conflicting desires that it cannot be conducted according to any

single principle or combination of principles. If we think of

government as only a phase of the widest social living, and so as

being through and through of the nature of the life of the individual,

we ought to have the right point of view for all practical

consideration of it. We must not expect consistency or perfection in

government, and we can have no hope of passing absolute and final

judgments upon it. Radical politics, in our present situation, must be

regarded as one of our greatest dangers.

Democracy has become the "great idea of the age." It is our own

fundamental principle, so we of all people ought to be able to

understand and to defend it--and to _define it_. Yet many writers

complain and more imply that the idea of democracy has never been very

clear, and perhaps not even ver