The psychology of Nations by G.E. Partridge - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

CHAPTER XI

HUMANISM

There has much been said during the war to the effect that the great

struggle was essentially a conflict between the spirit of humanism and

some principle or other which was conceived to be the opposite of

humanism. Humanism is said to be opposed to rationalism, or to

nationalism, or specialization, or paganism, or Germanism as a whole,

humanism often being thought of as the spirit of Greek or Christian

thought and philosophy.

There is truth, we should say, in these views. Humanism in a broad

sense emerged from all the purposes of the war as the principle of the

greater part of the world, as opposed to the idea of Germanism. This

spirit of humanism, however, is no single motive or feeling. It is a

complex mood, so to speak, and it is not to be regarded as strange

that it has been felt and described in various ways, and that it is

not yet clearly understood. _Humanism appears to be most deeply felt

as the appreciation of the common and fundamental things in human

nature._ It inclines toward the employment of feeling, or at least to

subjective rather than to purely objective principles in the

determination of fundamental values in life. Humanism includes an

interest in personality, which is of course the most basic of the

common possessions of man, and it is therefore interested in justice

and in freedom. Humanism as thus an appreciation of fundamental values

in life by feeling rather than by principle, belongs to the deeper

currents of life, those that flow in the subconscious--

it is close to

instinct, to moods, and the religious and the aesthetic experiences.

The later German philosophy of life we might mention as a denial of

much that humanism asserts. Here we see a doctrine of force, an ideal

of life based upon the elevation of conscious will to its first

principle. If we seek concrete contrasts to this anti-humanism we

might mention our own national life, governed by an idea of free

living, which has made possible the assimilation of many stocks, in a

life in which common human nature is regarded as the supreme value.

Extreme specialization, rational principles, objective standards are

watchwords of the plan of life that is most opposed to humanism. In

this life instincts and values determined by feelings are brought out

into the clear light of consciousness and are there judged with

reference to their fitness to serve ends determined by reason. It is

all noon-day glare in this rational consciousness.

Collectivism is

based upon coercion and upon calculation of the value of order in

serving practical purposes, themselves determined by a theory of

society, instead of upon social feeling or upon a natural process of

assimilation of the different and the individual into a common life.

Specialization also, in this philosophy, is a result of calculation

rather than of a belief in the value of the individual, and is gained

by the sacrifice of those experiences which, if we hold to the

humanistic ideal, we regard as essential to the life of the individual

and to society. This calculus of values extends, of course, into the

field of international life. Here too conduct is based upon estimation

of effects, freedom is relative to and subordinate to economic values.

A theory of the state takes precedence over all subjective ethical

principles, and there must be a disavowal of all native sentiments and

judgments as regards justice which issue from an appreciation of the

worth of personality and other fundamental human values and

possessions; and all common human sentiments which would stand in the

way of carrying out the decisions of reason and state-theory or any

political policy must of course also be denied.

This contrast, however inadequate our analysis of the spirit of

humanism and its opposite may be, will at least show that the idea of

justice, which in the humanistic ideal grows directly out of the

appreciation of the value of personality is the central practical

principle of humanism, and it is exactly as an opponent of the idea of

justice on the ground of its alleged weakness, that the rationalistic

or the nationalistic philosophy is best conceived.

It is upon this question of justice that we must take our stand for or

against humanism. If we are humanists we believe in the rights of

individuals, whether men or nations, to their own life and

independence, which they are entitled to preserve through all forms of

social processes. Justice means recognition of the right of

individuals to perform all their functions as individuals, and

humanism is precisely an appreciation of the values of the individual

as such a functioning whole. If we are humanists we believe that this

principle of justice, and this feeling of justice ought to be

cultivated and made world-wide. This is the ideal of equal rights to

all human values. Hence it is the mortal enemy of all philosophies of

life which place any principle above that of justice and its moral

implications, Whether in the narrower or the wider social life. This

is humanism.

There are various ways of interpreting humanism as a practical

philosophy or principle of education. Burnet says, perhaps not very

completely expressing what he means, that the humanistic ideal of

education, as contrasted with the merely formal, is that the pupils

should above all be led to feel the meaning and worth of what they are

studying. We should say that the meaning of humanism in education is

that _the child should understand and appreciate the meaning and worth

of all human life_. This requires that education should so be

conducted that the child may learn to see--rather to feel and

appreciate--the inner rather than the merely external nature of all

life that is presented to him, and in which he participates. Not

language, but thought; not history, but experience, is his field.

Justice depends wholly upon an ability to come upon reality in the

realm of human nature. This implies not only intellectual penetration,

but a form of sympathy which consists of putting oneself as completely

as possible into the life of that which is studied.

All this means, it is plain, a power in the educational process, a

spirit and a mood in all education which we have not yet in any very

large measure attained. What is required is indeed that children

should live more intimately with reality, so to speak, and that we

should not be satisfied when they have merely learned about it. We

shall not be content, however, with an educational process which, in

fulfilling these requirements for more life, becomes merely _active_.

Life must also be dramatic and intense and abundant. All the mental

processes--the feelings, the intellectual functions and not the will

alone must participate in this active life.

We shall soon see, no doubt, and in fact we are beginning already to

see a renewed interest in all the arguments for and against a

humanistic as opposed to a scientific culture and curriculum for our

schools. It is the humanistic side from which, it is likely, we shall

now hear the most pleas, for the war has ended, they say, in victory

for humanity and for humanism--hence for the humanities.

It is the

Christian and the Græco-Roman civilization that has prevailed.

Victorious France, whose culture is founded upon that of the Greek and

the Roman, has vindicated the supreme value of that culture. On the

other hand we hear that our present age has become an age of science.

If science has been a factor in causing the war, science has also won

it. If industrialism involved the world in disaster, the world will be

saved by more and better work, more practical living, wider

organization for the production of goods and of wealth.

Therefore our

curriculum must become more practical. We must have more of business

and industry, more vocational training, more training that sharpens

the intelligence.

There is a truth which cannot be overlooked in the claim of the

humanists, but the acceptance of it as it stands as a philosophy of

education is not without its serious dangers. What we may well

apprehend is a reactionary philosophy of education, and of all

culture. We begin to hear very strong pleas, for example, for a school

in which language, literature, and perhaps history become the center.

West[1] asks for a wider recognition of the humanities after the war.

Moore[2] says that the war is a victory of the civilization finally

established by the Romans on the basis of law, over the barbaric ideas

of power. Seeing this he is led to plead for a closer union now

between Latin and modern studies, binding civilization of to-day with

the thought and feeling of old Rome. Butler[3] says that we are surely

coming back to the classical languages and literature.

Such conclusions as these raise many questions and perhaps doubts and

apprehension. The ideal they express of penetrating the heart of

civilization and experiencing in the educational process the inner

life rather than the outer form of life, must indeed appeal to all,

and we should all as humanists agree that this ideal expresses what

humanism means and is the center of a true philosophy of education--but whether this ideal can be realized by any school that

clings to the old classical learning, even in spirit, is quite another

matter. To-day, if ever, we need to go forward in education. Our

spirit must be that of the searcher for new truth, and for a better

life. The old will not satisfy us either as a model and ideal or as a

method. No already accumulated culture material will be adequate for

our new school.

_Our schools of to-morrow, we should conclude, must still be inspired

by the scientific spirit, but what we need is science humanised, and

science in the service of moral principles._ One may well ask whether

it is not now the most opportune time to leave our classical learning

behind, and try to find a more adequate culture in which to convey the

spirit of our new humanism. If we have won a victory for humanity, as

we think, and have kept alive the Christian spirit by means of a

meager culture, we need not still cling to that culture if we can find

something better. Even if modern Germany has misused science and

brought it to reproach, we need not be prejudiced against science. We

need more science but we need to bring science into closer relation to

the whole of human life. We need more of all the psychological

sciences as an aid to our appreciation of history as the story and a

revelation of the meaning of spirit in the world--and it is this way

rather than through _language_ that we must undertake to know and to

explain life. On the other hand, it is for the business of practical,

social living that the material sciences should have most significance

in education. There is no science, not even mathematics, that cannot

be taught as a phase of the adventure of spirit in the world, and none

that cannot in some way be made to aid spirit in finding and keeping

its true course in the future. Such use of all culture is what we mean

by humanism. The secret of the difference in the educational ideals of

those whom we may call the old humanists and the new is that to one

education means predominantly _learning_, and to the other it means

mainly _living_. Living, for the child, means growing into the life of

the world by participating in spirit and in body, according to the

child's needs and capacities, in the activities of the world. To gain

a consciousness of the meaning of those activities through a knowledge

of their history and by an appreciation of their purpose is indeed the

main purpose of learning.

FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 1: _Educational Review_, February, 1919.]

[Footnote 2: _Educational Review_, February, 1919.]

[Footnote 3: _Teachers College Record_, January, 1919.]