The psychology of Nations by G.E. Partridge - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

CHAPTER I

ORIGINS AND BIOLOGICAL CONSIDERATIONS

The simplest possible interpretation of the causes of war that might

be offered is that war is a natural relation between original herds or

groups of men, inspired by the predatory instinct or by some other

instinct of the herd. To explain war, then, one need only refer to

this instinct as final, or at most account for the origin and genesis

of the instinct in question in the animal world. Some writers express

this very view, calling war an expression of an instinct or of several

instincts; others find different or more complex beginnings of war.

Nusbaum (86) says that both offense and defense are based upon an

_expansion impulse_. Nicolai (79) sees the beginning of war in

individual predatory acts, involving violence and the need of defense.

Again we find the migratory instinct, the instinct that has led groups

of men to move and thus to interfere with one another, regarded as the

cause of war, or as an important factor in the causes.

Sometimes a

purely physiological or growth impulse is invoked, or vaguely the

inability of primitive groups to adapt themselves to conditions, or to

gain access to the necessities of life. Le Bon (42) speaks of the

hunger and the desire that led Germanic forces as ancient hordes to

turn themselves loose upon the world.

Leaving aside for the moment the question of the nature of the

impulses or instincts which actuated the conduct of men originally and

brought them into opposition, as groups, to one another, we do find at

least some suggestion of a working hypothesis in these simple

explanations of war. Granted the existence of groups formed by the

accident of birth and based upon the most primitive protective and

economic associations, and assuming the presence of the emotions of

anger and fear or any instinct which is expressed as an impulse or

habit of the group, we might say that the conditions and factors for

the beginning of warfare are all present. When groups have desires

that can best and most simply be satisfied by the exertion of force

upon other groups, something equivalent to war has begun.

If we take the group (as herd or pack) and the instinct as the

original factors or data of society, however, we probably simplify the

situation too much. The question arises whether the motives are not

more complex, even from the beginning, and whether both the tendencies

or impulses by which the group was formed or held together and the

motives behind aggressive conduct against other groups have not been

produced or developed in the course of social relations, rather than

have been brought up from animal life, or at any point introduced as

instincts. We notice at least that animals living in groups do not in

general become aggressive within the species. Possibly it was by some

peculiarity of man's social existence, or his superior endowment of

intelligence or some unusual quality of his instincts, perhaps very

far back in animal life, that has in the end made him a warlike

creature. Man does seem to be a creature of _feelings_

rather than of

instincts as far back as we find much account of him, and to be

characterized rather by the weakness and variability of his instincts

than by their definiteness. It is quite likely, too, that man never

was at any stage a herd animal; in fact it seems certain that he was

not, and that his instincts were formed long before he began to live

in large groups at all. So he never acquired the mechanisms either for

aggression or defense that some creatures have.

Apparently he

inherited neither the physical powers nor the warlike spirit nor the

aggressive and predatory instincts that would have been necessary to

make of him a natural fighting animal; but rather, perhaps, he has

acquired his warlike habits, so to speak, since arriving at man's

estate. Endowed with certain tendencies which express themselves with

considerable variability in the processes by which the functions of

sex and nutrition are carried out, man never acquired the definiteness

of character and conduct that some animals have. He learned more from

animals, it may be, than he inherited from them, and it is quite

likely that far back in his animal ancestry he had greater flexibility

or adaptability than other animals. The aggressive instinct, the herd

instinct, the predatory instinct, the social instinct, the migratory

instinct, may never have been carried very far in the stock from which

man came. All this, however, at this point is only a suggestion of two

somewhat divergent points of view in regarding the primitive

activities of man from which his long history of war-making has taken

rise.

The view is widely held and continually referred to by many writers on

war and politics, that the most fundamental of all causes of war, or

the most general principle of it, is the principle of selection--that

war is a natural struggle between groups, especially between races,

the fittest in this struggle tending to survive. This view needs to be

examined sharply, as indeed it has been by several writers, in

connection with the present war. This biological theory or apology of

war appears in several forms, as applied to-day. They say that racial

stocks contend with one another for existence, and with this goes the

belief that nations fight for life, and that defeat in war tends

towards the extermination of nations. The Germans, we often hear, were

fighting for national existence, and the issue was to be a judgment

upon the fitness of their race to survive. This view is very often

expressed. O'Ryan and Anderson (5), military writers, for example, say

that the same aggressive motives prevail as always in warfare: nations

struggle for survival, and this struggle for survival must now and

again break out into war. Powers (75) says that nations seldom fight

for anything less than existence. Again (15) we read that conflicts

have their roots in history, in the lives of peoples, and the sounder,

and better, emerge as victors. There is a selective process on the

part of nature that applies to nations; they say that especially

increase of population forces upon groups an endless conflict, so that

absolute hostility is a law of nature in the world.

These views contain at least two very doubtful assumptions. One is

that nations do actually fight for existence,--that warfare is thus

selective to the point of eliminating races. The other is that in

warlike conflicts the victors are the superior peoples, the better

fitted for survival. Confusion arises and the discussion is

complicated by the fact that conflicts of men as groups of individuals

within the same species are somewhat anomalous among biological forms

of struggle. Commonly, struggle takes place among individuals,

organisms having definite characteristics and but slightly variable

each from its own kind contending with one another, by direct

competition or through adaptation, in the first case individuals

striving to obtain actually the same objects. Or, again, species

having the same relations to one another that individuals have,

contend in a similar manner.

Primitive groups of men, however, are not so definite; they are not

biological entities in any such sense as individuals and species are.

They are not definitely brought into conflict with one another, in

general, as contending for the same objects, and it is difficult to

see how, in the beginning, at least, economic pressure has been a

factor at all in their relations. Whatever may have been the motive

that for the most part was at work in primitive warfare, it is not at

all evident that _superior_ groups had any survival value. The groups

that contended with one another presumably differed most conspicuously

in the size of the group, and this was determined largely by chance

conditions. Other differences must have been quite subordinate to

this, and have had little selective value. The conclusion is that the

struggle of these groups with one another is not essentially a

_biological_ phenomenon.

The fact is that peace rather than war, taking the history of the

human race as a whole, is the condition in which selection of the

fittest is most active, for it is the power of adaptation to the

conditions of stable life, which are fairly uniform for different

groups over wide areas, that tests vitality and survival values, so

far as these values are biological. It may be claimed that war is very

often, if not generally, a means of interrupting favorable selective

processes, the unfit tending to prevail temporarily by force of

numbers, or even because of qualities that antagonize biological

progress. Viewing war in its later aspects, we can see that it is

often when nations are failing in natural competition that they resort

to the expedient of war to compensate for this loss, although they do

not usually succeed thereby in improving their economic condition as

they hope, or increase their chance of survival, or even demonstrate

their survival value. It is notorious that nations that conquer tend

to spend their vitality in conquest and introduce various factors of

deterioration into their lives. The inference is that a much more

complex relation exists among groups than the biological hypothesis

allows. Survival value indeed, as applied to men in groups, is not a

very clear concept. There may be several different criteria of

survival value, not comparable in any quantitative way among

themselves.

Scheler (77) says that we cannot account for war as a purely

biological phenomenon. Its roots lie deep in organic life, but there

is no direct development or exclusive development from animal behavior

to human. War is peculiarly human. That, in a way, may be accepted as

the truth. Warfare as we know it among human groups, as conflict

within the species is due in some way to, or is made possible by, the

secondary differentiations within species which give to groups, so to

speak, a pseudo-specific character. And these differences depend

largely upon the conditions that enter into the formation of

groups,--upon desires, impulses and needs arising in the social life

rather than in instinct as such. These characteristic differences are

not variations having selective value, but are traits that merely

differentiate the groups as _historical entities_. These secondary

variations have not resulted in the elimination of those having

inferior qualities, but have shared the fortunes of the groups that

possessed them,--the fortunes both of war and of peace.

_War, from

this point of view, belongs to history rather than to biology._ It

belongs to the realm of the particular rather than to the general in

human life. War has favored the survival of this or that group in a

particular place, but has probably not been instrumental in producing

any particular type of character in the world, either physical or

mental.

Very early in the history of mankind, in fact as far back as we can

trace history, we find these psychic differentiations, as factors in

the production of war. There are significant extensions and also

restrictions of the consciousness of kind pertaining to the life of

man, as distinguished from animals. Animals have not sufficient

intelligence to establish such perfect group identities as man does,

and they lack the affective motives for carrying on hostilities among

groups. They remain more clearly subjected to the simple laws of

biological selection, and are guided by instincts which do not impel

them to act aggressively as groups toward their own kind. Man proceeds

almost from the beginning to antagonize these laws, so that it is very

likely that the best, in the biological sense, has always had some

disadvantage, in human life, and may still have. The real value that

has thus been conserved by this human mode of life consists in

preserving a relatively large number of secondary types or individual

groups, rather than in insuring the predominance of any one

biologically superior type. _Man's work in the world is to make

history._ Even though war were a means of making a biologically

superior type of man prevail we should not be justified in saying that

it is thus vindicated as a method of selection.

Many writers whom we do not need to review in great detail have

contributed to the objections to the biological principle as an

explanation of war. Trotter (82) examines the doctrine that war is a

biological necessity, and says that there is no parallel in biology

for progress being accomplished as a result of a racial impoverishment

so extreme as is caused by war, that among gregarious animals other

than man direct conflict between major groups such as can lead to the

suppression of the less powerful is an inconspicuous phenomenon, and

that there is very little fighting within species, for species have

usually been too busy fighting their external enemies.

Mitchell (10)

says that war is not an aspect of the natural struggle for existence,

among individuals; that there is nothing in Darwinism that explains or

justifies wars; that the argument from race is worthless since there

are no pure races. M'Cabe (76) maintains that war is not a struggle

between inferior and superior national types. Dide (20) also discusses

the question of differences of race as causes of war, and the use that

has been made of this dogma. Chapman (39) says that no race question

is involved in the present war as has been supposed.

There is no

conflict of economic forces, no nations compelled to seek expansion.

Precisely how warfare originated (assuming that it arose in one way)

we shall probably never know, since we cannot now reconstruct the

actual history of man. We think of men as living at first in groups

containing a few individuals, and presumably for a long time these

small and isolated groups of men prevailed as the type of human

society. We can already detect the elements of conflict in these

groups, but whether warfare in the sense of deadly conflict originated

there we cannot know; or whether it was only in the experience of men

as large migrating hordes which had been formed by the amalgamation of

smaller groups under the influence of hunger or climatic change, that

warfare in any real sense came into the world. We do not know to what

extent the small groups of men we find in conditions of savagery now

represent primitive conditions. Fortunately, however, some of these

problems of origin are of but little practical importance and their

interest is chiefly antiquarian or historical.

The assumption that in the behavior of original groups of men war

arose as a natural result of the life of the group seems to be an

allowable hypothesis. Whether warlike conduct came by some

modification of the habits brought up from animal life as instinctive

reactions, or whether man invented warfare from some strong motive

peculiar to human life, and produced it intelligently, so to speak,

under stress of circumstances may have to remain an open question so

far as conclusive evidence is concerned. What we lack is a knowledge

of the type and form of the instincts of man in his first stages, and

the degree and kind of intelligence he had. But the reconstructed

pre-human history of man so far as we can make it seems to show, as we

have already suggested, that early man could have had no definite herd

instincts or pack instincts such as some of the animals have, that his

habits were plastic and guided by intelligence rather than by impulse.

His social life, his predaceous habits, the habit of killing large

game, his warfare must have been a gradual acquisition, and from the

beginning have been very different as regards motive and development

from animal behavior which judged externally may seem to be like it in

character and to have the same ends.

There are already inherent in any group of human individuals that fits

into such knowledge of man past and present as we have, all the

necessary motives of warfare in some form. There are the reactions of

anger made to any threat or injury, fear, the predaceous impulse and

habit, originating in hunger, the motives arising in sexual rivalry.

These motives are the source of behavior toward both members of the

group and outsiders. There is no absolute distinction between these

objects. It is of the nature of man to be both aggressive and social.

One instinct or motive did not come from the other, since there are

emotions and desires at every stage that tend, some of them to unite

and some to disrupt, the group. The sense of difference of kind and

the fear of the strange on the one hand, and the effect of propinquity

and practical necessity in the conduct in regard to the familiar on

the other make the reactions different in degree in the two spheres

but not different in kind. There is no aggressive instinct or war

motive that is directed exclusively toward the outsider.

Certain

tendencies toward violence and strife, modified and controlled within

the group, become unrestrained when directed toward the stranger.

Among these motives are those of sexual rivalry, fear, anger, desire,

and the play motive as an expression of any instinctive habits of

aggression that may have been phyletically established.

Since every individual creature has his needs that can be satisfied

only by preying in some way upon other animals of his own species or

others, the motives for strife are original in organic life. Every

animal lives in a world of which he is suspicious, and rightly so. He

is suspicious toward the members of his own kind and group, and toward

all strangers he shows watchfulness and fear. There are two motives,

therefore, of a highly practical nature that contribute to a general

state of unfriendliness in animal life. Both the motives of conflict

within the group, the habit of aggression and its complement, fear,

and the jealousy and display motive (the display itself probably

having originated as a show of ferocity on the part of males) must

have been transferred to relations between groups as a natural result

of the proximity of groups to one another, although this process is

not quite so simple as this would imply, since in part the outside

groups are produced by these very same antagonistic motives in the

group, for example the driving out of young males because of sexual

jealousy. The presence of other groups must have excited all the

motives of warfare at a very early stage, and this contrast had the

effect of stimulating the social feeling of the group and developing

control of impulses on the part of individuals within the group toward

one another. So the motives of combat, as shown within the group and

toward outsiders, developed, so to speak, by a dialectic process.

Fear and the predatory impulse, the sexual and display motive, play or

the hunting activity as a pleasure for its own sake, with a desire

perhaps to practice deception and to exercise intelligence, presumably

introduced some kind and degree of definite warfare among primitive

groups of men at a very early stage of human life, although of course

such a conclusion can be only speculative. Increasing intelligence,

the power of discriminating and of reacting to secondary likenesses

and differences, and especially the recognition of the nature of

death, and the advantages of killing rather than merely overcoming an

enemy, the discovery of the use of weapons, introduced warfare into

the world. Warfare is, then, not simply the negation of some original

principle of mutual aid, nor yet an expression of instinctive

aggressiveness or cruelty, but it is a product of original endowment,

of conditions of life, and of intelligence all together.

It is

practical, but at no stage can it be said to be _wholly_

practical.

Changes must have taken place in warfare as in other social reactions

as men passed through a number of stages from primitive wandering or a

relatively unstable life to a stable life, but the motives of conflict

cannot have been added to in any essential way. Through all the course

of history all the motives that originally made individuals of a group

or the groups as wholes antagonistic have remained, although the

mental processes have become generalized, fused and transformed. If

Gumplowicz is right we can still detect in any great society to-day

all the primitive individual and group animosities, tempered down and

held in check by laws and customs, but still existent and by no means

overcome and made innocuous.

These motives of warfare might best be traced out in four more or less

definite principles of conduct, or four purposes of war that appear

throughout primitive life. These are: 1) thievery, including wife

capture; 2) the fear motive; 3) cannibalism; 4) the display motive,

with the desire to intimidate and to display power (more or less

closely associated with the play motive, the love of hunting, gaming

and the dramatic motive).

Cannibalism, of course, is a special expression of the predatory

motive in general, or it is mainly that. Cannibalism was certainly

established early in primitive life, at least early enough to antedate

all religion, and although its origin and history are shrouded in

mystery, the motive was quite certainly practical.

Evidently it was

widespread if not universal. Whether it was introduced as a result of

a failure of animal food, as some think, or has a still more simple

explanation as a part of the original impulse which led men at a

certain stage of their development to become hunters, cannot be

determined. We know, however, that the alien human being was to some

extent included under the same concepts as the animal enemy and prey,

and presumably some of the strongest motives that led men to attack

animals also included man as an object, since the alien group was

regarded as in some degree different in kind from the in-group. It

may have been in the great migrations when all the aggressive motives

were increased that cannibalism became fixed as a habit.

Cannibalism may well have been the primitive motive of warfare as

serious deadly combat, but all predatory habits must have contributed

to establishing a more or less habitual state of warfare among all

groups of men. The predatory raid, with the reaction of defense, when

carried on as a group activity in any form, is in fact war, so far as

attack and defense were serious and deadly, and intelligence and

weapons were sufficiently developed to make man a dangerous opponent.

This predatory motive, of course, extended to all desired objects, and

these objects must have included all objects that could most simply be

acquired by stealing. They included food, women, and all other

possessions. The custom of driving out young males from the group, by

the jealousy of the old males, and of preventing males from obtaining

females within the group must have been one of the earliest and one of

the strongest incentives to predatory warfare. At first all property

of the group, for so long as groups were wandering, was to some extent

common, and attack and defense must have been common.

The objects of

predator