A Treatise of Human Nature by David Hume, - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

is impossible they can make use of this answer, or fix the equality of

any line or surface by a numeration of its component parts. For since,

according to their hypothesis, the least as well as greatest figures

contain an infinite number of parts; and since infinite numbers,

properly speaking, can neither be equal nor unequal with respect to each

other; the equality or inequality of any portions of space can never

depend on any proportion in the number of their parts.

It is true, it

may be said, that the inequality of an ell and a yard consists in the

different numbers of the feet, of which they are composed; and that of

a foot and a yard in the number of the inches. But as that quantity we

call an inch in the one is supposed equal to what we call an inch in

the other, and as it is impossible for the mind to find this equality by

proceeding in infinitum with these references to inferior quantities: it

is evident, that at last we must fix some standard of equality different

from an enumeration of the parts.

There are some [See Dr. Barrow's mathematical lectures.], who pretend,

that equality is best defined by congruity, and that any two figures

are equal, when upon the placing of one upon the other, all their parts

correspond to and touch each other. In order to judge of this definition

let us consider, that since equality is a relation, it is not, strictly

speaking, a property in the figures themselves, but arises merely from

the comparison, which the mind makes betwixt them. If it consists,

therefore, in this imaginary application and mutual contact of parts, we

must at least have a distinct notion of these parts, and must conceive

their contact. Now it is plain, that in this conception we would run up

these parts to the greatest minuteness, which can possibly be conceived;

since the contact of large parts would never render the figures equal.

But the minutest parts we can conceive are mathematical points; and

consequently this standard of equality is the same with that derived

from the equality of the number of points; which we have already

determined to be a just but an useless standard. We must therefore look

to some other quarter for a solution of the present difficulty.

There are many philosophers, who refuse to assign any standard of

equality, but assert, that it is sufficient to present two objects, that

are equal, in order to give us a just notion of this proportion. All

definitions, say they, are fruitless, without the perception of such

objects; and where we perceive such objects, we no longer stand in need

of any definition. To this reasoning, I entirely agree; and assert, that

the only useful notion of equality, or inequality, is derived from the

whole united appearance and the comparison of particular objects.

It is evident, that the eye, or rather the mind is often able at one

view to determine the proportions of bodies, and pronounce them equal

to, or greater or less than each other, without examining or comparing

the number of their minute parts. Such judgments are not only common,

but in many cases certain and infallible. When the measure of a yard and

that of a foot are presented, the mind can no more question, that the

first is longer than the second, than it can doubt of those principles,

which are the most clear and self-evident.

There are therefore three proportions, which the mind distinguishes

in the general appearance of its objects, and calls by the names of

greater, less and equal. But though its decisions concerning these

proportions be sometimes infallible, they are not always so; nor are our

judgments of this kind more exempt from doubt and error than those on

any other subject. We frequently correct our first opinion by a review

and reflection; and pronounce those objects to be equal, which at first

we esteemed unequal; and regard an object as less, though before it

appeared greater than another. Nor is this the only correction, which

these judgments of our senses undergo; but we often discover our error

by a juxtaposition of the objects; or where that is impracticable, by

the use of some common and invariable measure, which being successively

applied to each, informs us of their different proportions. And even

this correction is susceptible of a new correction, and of different

degrees of exactness, according to the nature of the instrument,

by which we measure the bodies, and the care which we employ in the

comparison.

When therefore the mind is accustomed to these judgments and their

corrections, and finds that the same proportion which makes two figures

have in the eye that appearance, which we call equality, makes them also

correspond to each other, and to any common measure, with which they

are compared, we form a mixed notion of equality derived both from the

looser and stricter methods of comparison. But we are not content with

this. For as sound reason convinces us that there are bodies vastly more

minute than those, which appear to the senses; and as a false reason

would perswade us, that there are bodies infinitely more minute; we

clearly perceive, that we are not possessed of any instrument or art of

measuring, which can secure us from ill error and uncertainty. We are

sensible, that the addition or removal of one of these minute parts,

is not discernible either in the appearance or measuring; and as we

imagine, that two figures, which were equal before, cannot be equal

after this removal or addition, we therefore suppose some imaginary

standard of equality, by which the appearances and measuring are exactly

corrected, and the figures reduced entirely to that proportion. This

standard is plainly imaginary. For as the very idea of equality is that

of such a particular appearance corrected by juxtaposition or a common

measure. The notion of any correction beyond what we have instruments

and art to make, is a mere fiction of the mind, and useless as well

as incomprehensible. But though this standard be only imaginary, the

fiction however is very natural; nor is anything more usual, than for

the mind to proceed after this manner with any action, even after the

reason has ceased, which first determined it to begin.

This appears very

conspicuously with regard to time; where though it is evident we have no

exact method of determining the proportions of parts, not even so exact

as in extension, yet the various corrections of our measures, and their

different degrees of exactness, have given as an obscure and implicit

notion of a perfect and entire equality. The case is the same in many

other subjects. A musician finding his ear becoming every day more

delicate, and correcting himself by reflection and attention, proceeds

with the same act of the mind, even when the subject fails him, and

entertains a notion of a compleat TIERCE or OCTAVE, without being able

to tell whence he derives his standard. A painter forms the same fiction

with regard to colours. A mechanic with regard to motion. To the one

light and shade; to the other swift and slow are imagined to be capable

of an exact comparison and equality beyond the judgments of the senses.

We may apply the same reasoning to CURVE and RIGHT

lines. Nothing is

more apparent to the senses, than the distinction betwixt a curve and a

right line; nor are there any ideas we more easily form than the ideas

of these objects. But however easily we may form these ideas, it is

impossible to produce any definition of them, which will fix the precise

boundaries betwixt them. When we draw lines upon paper, or any continued

surface, there is a certain order, by which the lines run along from one

point to another, that they may produce the entire impression of a

curve or right line; but this order is perfectly unknown, and nothing

is observed but the united appearance. Thus even upon the system of

indivisible points, we can only form a distant notion of some unknown

standard to these objects. Upon that of infinite divisibility we cannot

go even this length; but are reduced meerly to the general appearance,

as the rule by which we determine lines to be either curve or right

ones. But though we can give no perfect definition of these lines, nor

produce any very exact method of distinguishing the one from the other;

yet this hinders us not from correcting the first appearance by a more

accurate consideration, and by a comparison with some rule, of whose

rectitude from repeated trials we have a greater assurance. And it is

from these corrections, and by carrying on the same action of the mind,

even when its reason fails us, that we form the loose idea of a perfect

standard to these figures, without being able to explain or comprehend

it.

It is true, mathematicians pretend they give an exact definition of a

right line, when they say, it is the shortest way betwixt two points.

But in the first place I observe, that this is more properly the

discovery of one of the properties of a right line, than a just

deflation of it. For I ask any one, if upon mention of a right line he

thinks not immediately on such a particular appearance, and if it is not

by accident only that he considers this property? A right line can be

comprehended alone; but this definition is unintelligible without a

comparison with other lines, which we conceive to be more extended. In

common life it is established as a maxim, that the straightest way is

always the shortest; which would be as absurd as to say, the shortest

way is always the shortest, if our idea of a right line was not

different from that of the shortest way betwixt two points.

Secondly, I repeat what I have already established, that we have no

precise idea of equality and inequality, shorter and longer, more than

of a right line or a curve; and consequently that the one can never

afford us a perfect standard for the other. An exact idea can never be

built on such as are loose and undetermined.

The idea of a plain surface is as little susceptible of a precise

standard as that of a right line; nor have we any other means of

distinguishing such a surface, than its general appearance. It is in

vain, that mathematicians represent a plain surface as produced by the

flowing of a right line. It will immediately be objected, that our idea

of a surface is as independent of this method of forming a surface, as

our idea of an ellipse is of that of a cone; that the idea of a right

line is no more precise than that of a plain surface; that a right line

may flow irregularly, and by that means form a figure quite different

from a plane; and that therefore we must suppose it to flow along two

right lines, parallel to each other, and on the same plane; which is a

description, that explains a thing by itself, and returns in a circle.

It appears, then, that the ideas which are most essential to geometry,

viz. those of equality and inequality, of a right line and a plain

surface, are far from being exact and determinate, according to our

common method of conceiving them. Not only we are incapable of telling,

if the case be in any degree doubtful, when such particular figures are

equal; when such a line is a right one, and such a surface a plain one;

but we can form no idea of that proportion, or of these figures, which

is firm and invariable. Our appeal is still to the weak and fallible

judgment, which we make from the appearance of the objects, and correct

by a compass or common measure; and if we join the supposition of

any farther correction, it is of such-a-one as is either useless or

imaginary. In vain should we have recourse to the common topic, and

employ the supposition of a deity, whose omnipotence may enable him to

form a perfect geometrical figure, and describe a right line without any

curve or inflexion. As the ultimate standard of these figures is derived

from nothing but the senses and imagination, it is absurd to talk of

any perfection beyond what these faculties can judge of; since the true

perfection of any thing consists in its conformity to its standard.

Now since these ideas are so loose and uncertain, I would fain ask any

mathematician what infallible assurance he has, not only of the more

intricate, and obscure propositions of his science, but of the most

vulgar and obvious principles? How can he prove to me, for instance,

that two right lines cannot have one common segment? Or that it is

impossible to draw more than one right line betwixt any two points?

should he tell me, that these opinions are obviously absurd, and

repugnant to our clear ideas; I would answer, that I do not deny, where

two right lines incline upon each other with a sensible angle, but it is

absurd to imagine them to have a common segment. But supposing these two

lines to approach at the rate of an inch in twenty leagues, I perceive

no absurdity in asserting, that upon their contact they become one. For,

I beseech you, by what rule or standard do you judge, when you assert,

that the line, in which I have supposed them to concur, cannot make

the same right line with those two, that form so small an angle betwixt

them? You must surely have some idea of a right line, to which this line

does not agree. Do you therefore mean that it takes not the points in

the same order and by the same rule, as is peculiar and essential to a

right line? If so, I must inform you, that besides that in judging after

this manner you allow, that extension is composed of indivisible points

(which, perhaps, is more than you intend) besides this, I say, I must

inform you, that neither is this the standard from which we form the

idea of a right line; nor, if it were, is there any such firmness in our

senses or imagination, as to determine when such an order is violated or

preserved. The original standard of a right line is in reality nothing

but a certain general appearance; and it is evident right lines may be

made to concur with each other, and yet correspond to this standard,

though corrected by all the means either practicable or imaginable.

To whatever side mathematicians turn, this dilemma still meets them.

If they judge of equality, or any other proportion, by the accurate and

exact standard, viz. the enumeration of the minute indivisible parts,

they both employ a standard, which is useless in practice, and actually

establish the indivisibility of extension, which they endeavour to

explode. Or if they employ, as is usual, the inaccurate standard,

derived from a comparison of objects, upon their general appearance,

corrected by measuring and juxtaposition; their first principles,

though certain and infallible, are too coarse to afford any such subtile

inferences as they commonly draw from them. The first principles are

founded on the imagination and senses: The conclusion, therefore, can

never go beyond, much less contradict these faculties.

This may open our eyes a little, and let us see, that no geometrical

demonstration for the infinite divisibility of extension can have so

much force as what we naturally attribute to every argument, which is

supported by such magnificent pretensions. At the same time we may learn

the reason, why geometry falls of evidence in this single point, while

all its other reasonings command our fullest assent and approbation.

And indeed it seems more requisite to give the reason of this exception,

than to shew, that we really must make such an exception, and regard

all the mathematical arguments for infinite divisibility as utterly

sophistical. For it is evident, that as no idea of quantity is

infinitely divisible, there cannot be imagined a more glaring absurdity,

than to endeavour to prove, that quantity itself admits of such a

division; and to prove this by means of ideas, which are directly

opposite in that particular. And as this absurdity is very glaring in

itself, so there is no argument founded on it which is not attended

with a new absurdity, and involves not an evident contradiction.

I might give as instances those arguments for infinite divisibility,

which are derived from the point of contact. I know there is no

mathematician, who will not refuse to be judged by the diagrams he

describes upon paper, these being loose draughts, as he will tell us,

and serving only to convey with greater facility certain ideas, which

are the true foundation of all our reasoning. This I am satisfyed with,

and am willing to rest the controversy merely upon these ideas. I desire

therefore our mathematician to form, as accurately as possible,

the ideas of a circle and a right line; and I then ask, if upon the

conception of their contact he can conceive them as touching in a

mathematical point, or if he must necessarily imagine them to concur

for some space. Whichever side he chuses, he runs himself into equal

difficulties. If he affirms, that in tracing these figures in his

imagination, he can imagine them to touch only in a point, he allows

the possibility of that idea, and consequently of the thing. If he says,

that in his conception of the contact of those lines he must make

them concur, he thereby acknowledges the fallacy of geometrical

demonstrations, when carryed beyond a certain degree of minuteness;

since it is certain he has such demonstrations against the concurrence

of a circle and a right line; that is, in other words, he can prove an

idea, viz. that of concurrence, to be INCOMPATIBLE with two other

ideas, those of a circle and right line; though at the same time he

acknowledges these ideas to be inseparable.

SECT. V. THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED.

If the second part of my system be true, that the idea of space

or extension is nothing but the idea of visible or tangible points

distributed in a certain order; it follows, that we can form no idea

of a vacuum, or space, where there is nothing visible or tangible. This

gives rise to three objections, which I shall examine together, because

the answer I shall give to one is a consequence of that which I shall

make use of for the others.

First, It may be said, that men have disputed for many ages concerning

a vacuum and a plenum, without being able to bring the affair to a

final decision; and philosophers, even at this day, think themselves

at liberty to take part on either side, as their fancy leads them. But

whatever foundation there may be for a controversy concerning the things

themselves, it may be pretended, that the very dispute is decisive

concerning the idea, and that it is impossible men coued so long reason

about a vacuum, and either refute or defend it, without having a notion

of what they refuted or defended.

Secondly, If this argument should be contested, the reality or at least

the possibility of the idea of a vacuum may be proved by the following

reasoning. Every idea is possible, which is a necessary and infallible

consequence of such as are possible. Now though we allow the world to be

at present a plenum, we may easily conceive it to be deprived of motion;

and this idea will certainly be allowed possible. It must also be

allowed possible, to conceive the annihilation of any part of matter by

the omnipotence of the deity, while the other parts remain at rest. For

as every idea, that is distinguishable, is separable by the imagination;

and as every idea, that is separable by the imagination, may be

conceived to be separately existent; it is evident, that the existence

of one particle of matter, no more implies the existence of another,

than a square figure in one body implies a square figure in every one.

This being granted, I now demand what results from the concurrence of

these two possible ideas of rest and annihilation, and what must we

conceive to follow upon the annihilation of all the air and subtile

matter in the chamber, supposing the walls to remain the same, without

any motion or alteration? There are some metaphysicians, who answer,

that since matter and extension are the same, the annihilation of one

necessarily implies that of the other; and there being now no distance

betwixt the walls of the chamber, they touch each other; in the same

manner as my hand touches the paper, which is immediately before me.

But though this answer be very common, I defy these metaphysicians to

conceive the matter according to their hypothesis, or imagine the floor

and roof, with all the opposite sides of the chamber, to touch each

other, while they continue in rest, and preserve the same position. For

how can the two walls, that run from south to north, touch each other,

while they touch the opposite ends of two walls, that run from east

to west? And how can the floor and roof ever meet, while they are

separated by the four walls, that lie in a contrary position? If you

change their position, you suppose a motion. If you conceive any thing

betwixt them, you suppose a new creation. But keeping strictly to the

two ideas of rest and annihilation, it is evident, that the idea, which

results from them, is not that of a contact of parts, but something

else; which is concluded to be the idea of a vacuum.

The third objection carries the matter still farther, and not only

asserts, that the idea of a vacuum is real and possible, but also

necessary and unavoidable. This assertion is founded on the motion we

observe in bodies, which, it is maintained, would be impossible and

inconceivable without a vacuum, into which one body must move in order

to make way for another.. I shall not enlarge upon this objection,

because it principally belongs to natural philosophy, which lies without

our present sphere.

In order to answer these objections, we must take the matter pretty

deep, and consider the nature and origin of several ideas, lest we

dispute without understanding perfectly the subject of the controversy.

It is evident the idea of darkness is no positive idea, but merely the

negation of light, or more properly speaking, of coloured and visible

objects. A man, who enjoys his sight, receives no other perception from

turning his eyes on every side, when entirely deprived of light, than

what is common to him with one born blind; and it is certain such-a-one

has no idea either of light or darkness. The consequence of this is,

that it is not from the mere removal of visible objects we receive

the impression of extension without matter; and that the idea of utter

darkness can never be the same with that of vacuum.

Suppose again a man to be supported in the air, and to be softly

conveyed along by some invisible power; it is evident he is sensible of

nothing, and never receives the idea of extension, nor indeed any idea,

from this invariable motion. Even supposing he moves his limbs to

and fro, this cannot convey to him that idea. He feels in that case a

certain sensation or impression, the parts of which are successive to

each other, and may give him the idea of time: But certainly are not

disposed in such a manner, as is necessary to convey the idea of space

or the idea of space or extension.

Since then it appears, that darkness and motion, with the utter removal

of every thing visible and tangible, can never give us the idea of

extension without matter, or of a vacuum; the next question is, whether

they can convey this idea, when mixed with something visible and

tangible?

It is commonly allowed by philosophers, that all bodies, which discover

themselves to the eye, appear as if painted on a plain surface, and that

their different degrees of remoteness from ourselves are discovered

more by reason than by the senses. Whe