A Treatise of Human Nature by David Hume, - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

other. Their constant conjunction in past instances has produced such

a habit in the mind, that it always conjoins them in its thought, and

infers the existence of the one from that of its usual attendant. When

it considers the dye as no longer supported by the box, it can not

without violence regard it as suspended in the air; but naturally places

it on the table, and views it as turning up one of its sides. This

is the effect of the intermingled causes, which are requisite to our

forming any calculation concerning chances.

Secondly, It is supposed, that though the dye be necessarily determined

to fall, and turn up one of its sides, yet there is nothing to fix the

particular side, but that this is determined entirely by chance. The

very nature and essence of chance is a negation of causes, and the

leaving the mind in a perfect indifference among those events, which

are supposed contingent. When therefore the thought is determined by the

causes to consider the dye as falling and turning up one of its sides,

the chances present all these sides as equal, and make us consider every

one of them, one after another, as alike probable and possible. The

imagination passes from the cause, viz. the throwing of the dye, to the

effect, viz. the turning up one of the six sides; and feels a kind of

impossibility both of stopping short in the way, and of forming any

other idea. But as all these six sides are incompatible, and the dye

cannot turn up above one at once, this principle directs us not to

consider all of them at once as lying uppermost; which we look upon

as impossible: Neither does it direct us with its entire force to any

particular side; for in that case this side would be considered as

certain and inevitable; but it directs us to the whole six sides after

such a manner as to divide its force equally among them.

We conclude in

general, that some one of them must result from the throw: We run all

of them over in our minds: The determination of the thought is common to

all; but no more of its force falls to the share of any one, than what

is suitable to its proportion with the rest. It is after this manner the

original impulse, and consequently the vivacity of thought, arising from

the causes, is divided and split in pieces by the intermingled chances.

We have already seen the influence of the two first qualities of the

dye, viz. the causes, and the number and indifference of the sides, and

have learned how they give an impulse to the thought, and divide that

impulse into as many parts as there are unites in the number of sides.

We must now consider the effects of the third particular, viz. the

figures inscribed on each side. It is evident that where several

sides have the same figure inscribe on them, they must concur in their

influence on the mind, and must unite upon one image or idea of a figure

all those divided impulses, that were dispersed over the several sides,

upon which that figure is inscribed. Were the question only what side

will be turned up, these are all perfectly equal, and no one coued ever

have any advantage above another. But as the question is concerning the

figure, and as the same figure is presented by more than one side: it is

evident, that the impulses belonging to all these sides must re-unite

in that one figure, and become stronger and more forcible by the union.

Four sides are supposed in the present case to have the same figure

inscribed on them, and two to have another figure. The impulses of

the former are, therefore, superior to those of the latter. But as the

events are contrary, and it is impossible both these figures can be

turned up; the impulses likewise become contrary, and the inferior

destroys the superior, as far as its strength goes. The vivacity of the

idea is always proportionable to the degrees of the impulse or tendency

to the transition; and belief is the same with the vivacity of the idea,

according to the precedent doctrine.

SECT. XII. OF THE PROBABILITY OF CAUSES.

What I have said concerning the probability of chances can serve to

no other purpose, than to assist us in explaining the probability of

causes; since it is commonly allowed by philosophers, that what the

vulgar call chance is nothing but a secret and concealed cause. That

species of probability, therefore, is what we must chiefly examine.

The probabilities of causes are of several kinds; but are all derived

from the same origin, viz. THE ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS TO A PRESENT

IMPRESSION. As the habit, which produces the association, arises from

the frequent conjunction of objects, it must arrive at its perfection by

degrees, and must acquire new force from each instance, that falls under

our observation. The first instance has little or no force: The second

makes some addition to it: The third becomes still more sensible; and it

is by these slow steps, that our judgment arrives at a full assurance.

But before it attains this pitch of perfection, it passes through

several inferior degrees, and in all of them is only to be esteemed a

presumption or probability. The gradation, therefore, from probabilities

to proofs is in many cases insensible; and the difference betwixt these

kinds of evidence is more easily perceived in the remote degrees, than

in the near and contiguous.

It is worthy of remark on this occasion, that though the species of

probability here explained be the first in order, and naturally takes

place before any entire proof can exist, yet no one, who is arrived at

the age of maturity, can any longer be acquainted with it. It is true,

nothing is more common than for people of the most advanced knowledge

to have attained only an imperfect experience of many particular events;

which naturally produces only an imperfect habit and transition: But

then we must consider, that the mind, having formed another observation

concerning the connexion of causes and effects, gives new force to

its reasoning from that observation; and by means of it can build an

argument on one single experiment, when duly prepared and examined. What

we have found once to follow from any object, we conclude will for ever

follow from it; and if this maxim be not always built upon as certain,

it is not for want of a sufficient number of experiments, but because

we frequently meet with instances to the contrary; which leads us to

the second species of probability, where there is a contrariety in our

experience and observation.

It would be very happy for men in the conduct of their lives and

actions, were the same objects always conjoined together, and, we had

nothing to fear but the mistakes of our own judgment, without having any

reason to apprehend the uncertainty of nature. But as it is frequently

found, that one observation is contrary to another, and that causes and

effects follow not in the same order, of which we have I had experience,

we are obliged to vary our reasoning on, account of this uncertainty,

and take into consideration the contrariety of events.

The first

question, that occurs on this head, is concerning the nature and causes

of the contrariety.

The vulgar, who take things according to their first appearance,

attribute the uncertainty of events to such an uncertainty in the

causes, as makes them often fail of their usual influence, though

they meet with no obstacle nor impediment in their operation. But

philosophers observing, that almost in every part of nature there is

contained a vast variety of springs and principles, which are hid,

by reason of their minuteness or remoteness, find that it is at least

possible the contrariety of events may not proceed from any contingency

in the cause, but from the secret operation of contrary causes. This

possibility is converted into certainty by farther observation, when

they remark, that upon an exact scrutiny, a contrariety of effects

always betrays a contrariety of causes, and proceeds from their mutual

hindrance and opposition. A peasant can give no better reason for the

stopping of any clock or watch than to say, that commonly it does not

go right: But an artizan easily perceives, that the same force in the

spring or pendulum has always the same influence on the wheels; but

fails of its usual effect, perhaps by reason of a grain of dust, which

puts a stop to the whole movement. From the observation of several

parallel instances, philosophers form a maxim, that the connexion

betwixt all causes and effects is equally necessary, and that its

seeming uncertainty in some instances proceeds from the secret

opposition of contrary causes.

But however philosophers and the vulgar may differ in their explication

of the contrariety of events, their inferences from it are always of the

same kind, and founded on the same principles. A contrariety of events

in the past may give us a kind of hesitating belief for the future after

two several ways. First, By producing an imperfect habit and transition

from the present impression to the related idea. When the conjunction of

any two objects is frequent, without being entirely constant, the mind

is determined to pass from one object to the other; but not with

so entire a habit, as when the union is uninterrupted, and all the

instances we have ever met with are uniform and of a piece-.. We find

from common experience, in our actions as well as reasonings, that

a constant perseverance in any course of life produces a strong

inclination and tendency to continue for the future; though there

are habits of inferior degrees of force, proportioned to the inferior

degrees of steadiness and uniformity in our conduct.

There is no doubt but this principle sometimes takes place, and

produces those inferences we draw from contrary phaenomena: though I

am perswaded, that upon examination we shall not find it to be the

principle, that most commonly influences the mind in this species of

reasoning. When we follow only the habitual determination of the mind,

we make the transition without any reflection, and interpose not a

moment's delay betwixt the view of one object and the belief of that,

which is often found to attend it. As the custom depends not upon any

deliberation, it operates immediately, without allowing any time for

reflection. But this method of proceeding we have but few instances

of in our probable reasonings; and even fewer than in those, which are

derived from the uninterrupted conjunction of objects.

In the former

species of reasoning we commonly take knowingly into consideration

the contrariety of past events; we compare the different sides of the

contrariety, and carefully weigh the experiments, which we have on each

side: Whence we may conclude, that our reasonings of this kind arise

not directly from the habit, but in an oblique manner; which we must now

endeavour to explain.

It is evident, that when an object is attended with contrary effects, we

judge of them only by our past experience, and always consider those

as possible, which we have observed to follow from it.

And as past

experience regulates our judgment concerning the possibility of these

effects, so it does that concerning their probability; and that effect,

which has been the most common, we always esteem the most likely. Here

then are two things to be considered, viz. the reasons which determine

us to make the past a standard for the future, and the manner how we

extract a single judgment from a contrariety of past events.

First we may observe, that the supposition, that the future resembles

the past, is not founded on arguments of any kind, but is derived

entirely from habit, by which we are determined to expect for the future

the same train of objects, to which we have been accustomed. This habit

or determination to transfer the past to the future is full and perfect;

and consequently the first impulse of the imagination in this species of

reasoning is endowed with the same qualities.

But, secondly, when in considering past experiments we find them of a

contrary nature, this determination, though full and perfect in itself,

presents us with no steady object, but offers us a number of disagreeing

images in a certain order and proportion. The first impulse, therefore,

is here broke into pieces, and diffuses itself over all those images, of

which each partakes an equal share of that force and vivacity, that is

derived from the impulse. Any of these past events may again happen;

and we judge, that when they do happen, they will be mixed in the same

proportion as in the past.

If our intention, therefore, be to consider the proportions of contrary

events in a great number of instances, the images presented by our past

experience must remain in their FIRST FORM, and preserve their first

proportions. Suppose, for instance, I have found by long observation,

that of twenty ships, which go to sea, only nineteen return. Suppose

I see at present twenty ships that leave the port: I transfer my past

experience to the future, and represent to myself nineteen of these

ships as returning in safety, and one as perishing.

Concerning this

there can be no difficulty. But as we frequently run over those several

ideas of past events, in order to form a judgment concerning one single

event, which appears uncertain; this consideration must change the FIRST

FORM of our ideas, and draw together the divided images presented

by experience; since it is to it we refer the determination of that

particular event, upon which we reason. Many of these images are

supposed to concur, and a superior number to concur on one side. These

agreeing images unite together, and render the idea more strong and

lively, not only than a mere fiction of the imagination, but also than

any idea, which is supported by a lesser number of experiments. Each new

experiment is as a new stroke of the pencil, which bestows an additional

vivacity on the colours without either multiplying or enlarging the

figure. This operation of the mind has been so fully explained in

treating of the probability of chance, that I need not here endeavour to

render it more intelligible. Every past experiment may be considered as

a kind of chance; I it being uncertain to us, whether the object will

exist conformable to one experiment or another. And for this reason

every thing that has been said on the one subject is applicable to both.

Thus upon the whole, contrary experiments produce an imperfect belief,

either by weakening the habit, or by dividing and afterwards joining in

different parts, that perfect habit, which makes us conclude in general,

that instances, of which we have no experience, must necessarily

resemble those of which we have.

To justify still farther this account of the second species of

probability, where we reason with knowledge and reflection from

a contrariety of past experiments, I shall propose the following

considerations, without fearing to give offence by that air of subtilty,

which attends them. Just reasoning ought still, perhaps, to retain

its force, however subtile; in the same manner as matter preserves its

solidity in the air, and fire, and animal spirits, as well as in the

grosser and more sensible forms.

First, We may observe, that there is no probability so great as not to

allow of a contrary possibility; because otherwise it would cease to be

a probability, and would become a certainty. That probability of causes,

which is most extensive, and which we at present examine, depends on a

contrariety of experiments: and it is evident An experiment in the past

proves at least a possibility for the future.

Secondly, The component parts of this possibility and probability are of

the same nature, and differ in number only, but not in kind. It has been

observed, that all single chances are entirely equal, and that the

only circumstance, which can give any event, that is contingent, a

superiority over another is a superior number of chances. In like

manner, as the uncertainty of causes is discovery by experience, which

presents us with a view of contrary events, it is plain, that when we

transfer the past to the future, the known to the unknown, every past

experiment has the same weight, and that it is only a superior number

of them, which can throw the ballance on any side. The possibility,

therefore, which enters into every reasoning of this kind, is composed

of parts, which are of the same nature both among themselves, and with

those, that compose the opposite probability.

Thirdly, We may establish it as a certain maxim, that in all moral as

well as natural phaenomena, wherever any cause consists of a number

of parts, and the effect encreases or diminishes, according to the

variation of that number, the effects properly speaking, is a compounded

one, and arises from the union of the several effects, that proceed from

each part of the cause. Thus, because the gravity of a body encreases or

diminishes by the encrease or diminution of its parts, we conclude that

each part contains this quality and contributes to the gravity of the

whole. The absence or presence of a part of the cause is attended with

that of a proportionable part of the effect. This connexion or constant

conjunction sufficiently proves the one part to be the cause of the

other. As the belief which we have of any event, encreases or diminishes

according to the number of chances or past experiments, it is to be

considered as a compounded effect, of which each part arises from a

proportionable number of chances or experiments.

Let us now join these three observations, and see what conclusion we can

draw from them. To every probability there is an opposite possibility.

This possibility is composed of parts, that are entirely of the same

nature with those of the probability; and consequently have the same

influence on the mind and understanding. The belief, which attends the

probability, is a compounded effect, and is formed by the concurrence

of the several effects, which proceed from each part of the probability.

Since therefore each part of the probability contributes to the

production of the belief, each part of the possibility must have the

same influence on the opposite side; the nature of these parts being

entirely the same. The contrary belief, attending the possibility,

implies a view of a certain object, as well as the probability does

an opposite view. In this particular both these degrees of belief are

alike. The only manner then, in which the superior number of similar

component parts in the one can exert its influence, and prevail above

the inferior in the other, is by producing a stronger and more lively

view of its object. Each part presents a particular view; and all these

views uniting together produce one general view, which is fuller and

more distinct by the greater number of causes or principles, from which

it is derived.

The component parts of the probability and possibility, being alike

in their nature, must produce like effects; and the likeness of their

effects consists in this, that each of them presents a view of a

particular object. But though these parts be alike in their nature, they

are very different in their quantity and number; and this difference

must appear in the effect as well as the similarity. Now as the view

they present is in both cases full and entire, and comprehends the

object in all its parts, it is impossible that in this particular there

can be any difference; nor is there any thing but a superior vivacity

in the probability, arising from the concurrence of a superior number of

views, which can distinguish these effects.

Here is almost the same argument in a different light.

All our

reasonings concerning the probability of causes are founded on the

transferring of past to future. The transferring of any past experiment

to the future is sufficient to give us a view of the object; whether

that experiment be single or combined with others of the same kind;

whether it be entire, or opposed by others of a contrary kind. Suppose,

then, it acquires both these qualities of combination and opposition, it

loses not upon that account its former power of presenting a view of the

object, but only concurs with and opposes other experiments, that have

a like influence. A question, therefore, may arise concerning the manner

both of the concurrence and opposition. As to the concurrence, there is

only the choice left betwixt these two hypotheses.

First, That the view

of the object, occasioned by the transference of each past experiment,

preserves itself entire, and only multiplies the number of views. Or,

SECONDLY, That it runs into the other similar and correspondent views,

and gives them a superior degree of force and vivacity.

But that the

first hypothesis is erroneous, is evident from experience, which

informs us, that the belief, attending any reasoning, consists in

one conclusion, not in a multitude of similar ones, which would only

distract the mind, and in many cases would be too numerous to be

comprehended distinctly by any finite capacity. It remains, therefore,

as the only reasonable opinion, that these similar views run into each

other, and unite their forces; so as to produce a stronger and clearer

view, than what arises from any one alone. This is the manner, in which

past experiments concur, when they are transfered to any future event.

As to the manner of their opposition, it is evident, that as the

contrary views are incompatible with each other, and it is impossible

the object can at once exist conformable to both of them, their

influence becomes mutually destructive, and the mind is determined to

the superior only with that force, which remains, after subtracting the

inferior.

I am sensible how abstruse all this reasoning must appear to the

generality of readers, who not being accustomed to such profound

reflections on the intellectual faculties of the mind, will be apt to

reject as chimerical whatever strikes not in with the common received

notions, and with the easiest and most obvious principles of philosophy.

And no doubt there are some pains required to enter into these

arguments; though perhaps very little are necessary to perceive the

imperfection of every vulgar hypothesis on this subject, and the little

light, which philosophy can yet afford us in such sublime and such

curious speculations. Let men be once fully perswaded of these two

principles, THAT THERE, IS NOTHING IN ANY OBJECT, CONSIDERed IN ITSELF,

WHICH CAN AFFORD US A REASON FOR DRAWING A CONCLUSION

BEYOND it; and,

THAT EVEN AFTER THE OBSERVATION OF THE FREQUENT OR

CONSTANT CONJUNCTION

OF OBJECTS, WE HAVE NO REASON TO DRAW ANY INFERENCE

CONCERNING ANY

OBJECT BEYOND THOSE OF WHICH WE HAVE HAD EXPERIENCE; I say, let men be

once fully convinced of these two principles, and this will throw them

so loose from all common systems, that they will make no difficulty of

receiving any, which may appear the most extraordinary.

These principles

we have found to be sufficiently convincing, even with regard to our

most certain reasonings from causation: But I shall venture to affirm,

that with regard to these conjectural or probable reasonings they still

acquire a new degr