A Treatise of Human Nature by David Hume, - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

contiguous and connected, to be placed before us; it is plain we must

attribute a perfect identity to this mass, provided all the parts

continue uninterruptedly and invariably the same, whatever motion or

change of place we may observe either in the whole or in any of the

parts. But supposing some very small or inconsiderable part to be added

to the mass, or subtracted from it; though this absolutely destroys

the identity of the whole, strictly speaking; yet as we seldom think so

accurately, we scruple not to pronounce a mass of matter the same, where

we find so trivial an alteration. The passage of the thought from the

object before the change to the object after it, is so smooth and easy,

that we scarce perceive the transition, and are apt to imagine, that it

is nothing but a continued survey of the same object.

There is a very remarkable circumstance, that attends this experiment;

which is, that though the change of any considerable part in a mass

of matter destroys the identity of the whole, let we must measure the

greatness of the part, not absolutely, but by its proportion to the

whole. The addition or diminution of a mountain would not be sufficient

to produce a diversity in a planet: though the change of a very few

inches would be able to destroy the identity of some bodies. It will be

impossible to account for this, but by reflecting that objects operate

upon the mind, and break or interrupt the continuity of its actions not

according to their real greatness, but according to their proportion to

each other: And therefore, since this interruption makes an object cease

to appear the same, it must be the uninterrupted progress o the thought,

which constitutes the imperfect identity.

This may be confirmed by another phenomenon. A change in any

considerable part of a body destroys its identity; but it is remarkable,

that where the change is produced gradually and insensibly we are less

apt to ascribe to it the same effect. The reason can plainly be no

other, than that the mind, in following the successive changes of the

body, feels an easy passage from the surveying its condition in one

moment to the viewing of it in another, and at no particular time

perceives any interruption in its actions. From which continued

perception, it ascribes a continued existence and identity to the

object.

But whatever precaution we may use in introducing the changes gradually,

and making them proportionable to the whole, it is certain, that where

the changes are at last observed to become considerable, we make a

scruple of ascribing identity to such different objects.

There is,

however, another artifice, by which we may induce the imagination to

advance a step farther; and that is, by producing a reference of the

parts to each other, and a combination to some common end or purpose.

A ship, of which a considerable part has been changed by frequent

reparations, is still considered as the same; nor does the difference

of the materials hinder us from ascribing an identity to it. The

common end, in which the parts conspire, is the same under all their

variations, and affords an easy transition of the imagination from one

situation of the body to another.

But this is still more remarkable, when we add a sympathy of parts

to their common end, and suppose that they bear to each other, the

reciprocal relation of cause and effect in all their actions and

operations. This is the case with all animals and vegetables; where not

only the several parts have a reference to some general purpose, but

also a mutual dependence on, and connexion with each other. The effect

of so strong a relation is, that though every one must allow, that in a

very few years both vegetables and animals endure a total change, yet we

still attribute identity to them, while their form, size, and substance

are entirely altered. An oak, that grows from a small plant to a large

tree, is still the same oak; though there be not one particle of matter,

or figure of its parts the same. An infant becomes a man-, and is

sometimes fat, sometimes lean, without any change in his identity.

We may also consider the two following phaenomena, which are remarkable

in their kind. The first is, that though we commonly be able to

distinguish pretty exactly betwixt numerical and specific identity, yet

it sometimes happens, that we confound them, and in our thinking and

reasoning employ the one for the other. Thus a man, who bears a noise,

that is frequently interrupted and renewed, says, it is still the same

noise; though it is evident the sounds have only a specific identity or

resemblance, and there is nothing numerically the same, but the cause,

which produced them. In like manner it may be said without breach of the

propriety of language, that such a church, which was formerly of brick,

fell to ruin, and that the parish rebuilt the same church of free-stone,

and according to modern architecture. Here neither the form nor

materials are the same, nor is there any thing common to the two

objects, but their relation to the inhabitants of the parish; and yet

this alone is sufficient to make us denominate them the same. But

we must observe, that in these cases the first object is in a manner

annihilated before the second comes into existence; by which means, we

are never presented in any one point of time with the idea of difference

and multiplicity: and for that reason are less scrupulous in calling

them the same.

Secondly, We may remark, that though in a succession of related objects,

it be in a manner requisite, that the change of parts be not sudden nor

entire, in order to preserve the identity, yet where the objects are

in their nature changeable and inconstant, we admit of a more sudden

transition, than would otherwise be consistent with that relation. Thus

as the nature of a river consists in the motion and change of parts;

though in less than four and twenty hours these be totally altered; this

hinders not the river from continuing the same during several ages. What

is natural and essential to any thing is, in a manner, expected; and

what is expected makes less impression, and appears of less moment, than

what is unusual and extraordinary. A considerable change of the former

kind seems really less to the imagination, than the most trivial

alteration of the latter; and by breaking less the continuity of the

thought, has less influence in destroying the identity.

We now proceed to explain the nature of personal identity, which has

become so great a question ill philosophy, especially of late years in

England, where all the abstruser sciences are studyed with a peculiar

ardour and application. And here it is evident, the same method of

reasoning must be continued which has so successfully explained the

identity of plants, and animals, and ships, and houses, and of all

the compounded and changeable productions either of art or nature. The

identity, which we ascribe to the mind of man, is only a fictitious one,

and of a like kind with that which we ascribe to vegetables and animal

bodies. It cannot, therefore, have a different origin, but must proceed

from a like operation of the imagination upon like objects.

But lest this argument should not convince the reader; though in my

opinion perfectly decisive; let him weigh the following reasoning, which

is still closer and more immediate. It is evident, that the identity,

which we attribute to the human mind, however perfect we may imagine it

to be, is not able to run the several different perceptions into one,

and make them lose their characters of distinction and difference, which

are essential to them. It is still true, that every distinct perception,

which enters into the composition of the mind, is a distinct existence,

and is different, and distinguishable, and separable from every other

perception, either contemporary or successive. But, as, notwithstanding

this distinction and separability, we suppose the whole train of

perceptions to be united by identity, a question naturally arises

concerning this relation of identity; whether it be something that

really binds our several perceptions together, or only associates

their ideas in the imagination. That is, in other words, whether in

pronouncing concerning the identity of a person, we observe some real

bond among his perceptions, or only feel one among the ideas we form of

them. This question we might easily decide, if we would recollect what

has been already proud at large, that the understanding never observes

any real connexion among objects, and that even the union of cause

and effect, when strictly examined, resolves itself into a customary

association of ideas. For from thence it evidently follows, that

identity is nothing really belonging to these different perceptions, and

uniting them together; but is merely a quality, which we attribute to

them, because of the union of their ideas in the imagination, when we

reflect upon them. Now the only qualities, which can give ideas an union

in the imagination, are these three relations abovementioned. There

are the uniting principles in the ideal world, and without them

every distinct object is separable by the mind, and may be separately

considered, and appears not to have any more connexion with any other

object, than if disjoined by the greatest difference and remoteness.

It is, therefore, on some of these three relations of resemblance,

contiguity and causation, that identity depends; and as the very essence

of these relations consists in their producing an easy transition

of ideas; it follows, that our notions of personal identity, proceed

entirely from the smooth and uninterrupted progress of the thought along

a train of connected ideas, according to the principles above-explained.

The only question, therefore, which remains, is, by what relations this

uninterrupted progress of our thought is produced, when we consider

the successive existence of a mind or thinking person.

And here it is

evident we must confine ourselves to resemblance and causation, and must

drop contiguity, which has little or no influence in the present case.

To begin with resemblance; suppose we coued see clearly into the

breast of another, and observe that succession of perceptions, which

constitutes his mind or thinking principle, and suppose that he always

preserves the memory of a considerable part of past perceptions; it is

evident that nothing coued more contribute to the bestowing a relation

on this succession amidst all its variations. For what is the memory but

a faculty, by which we raise up the images of past perceptions? And

as an image necessarily resembles its object, must not.

The frequent

placing of these resembling perceptions in the chain of thought, convey

the imagination more easily from one link to another, and make the whole

seem like the continuance of one object? In this particular, then, the

memory not only discovers the identity, but also contributes to

its production, by producing the relation of resemblance among the

perceptions. The case is the same whether we consider ourselves or

others.

As to causation; we may observe, that the true idea of the human mind,

is to consider it as a system of different perceptions or different

existences, which are linked together by the relation of cause and

effect, and mutually produce, destroy, influence, and modify each other.

Our impressions give rise to their correspondent ideas; said these ideas

in their turn produce other impressions. One thought chaces another,

and draws after it a third, by which it is expelled in its turn. In this

respect, I cannot compare the soul more properly to any thing than to a

republic or commonwealth, in which the several members are united by the

reciprocal ties of government and subordination, and give rise to other

persons, who propagate the same republic in the incessant changes of

its parts. And as the same individual republic may not only change its

members, but also its laws and constitutions; in like manner the

same person may vary his character and disposition, as well as his

impressions and ideas, without losing his identity.

Whatever changes

he endures, his several parts are still connected by the relation of

causation. And in this view our identity with regard to the passions

serves to corroborate that with regard to the imagination, by the making

our distant perceptions influence each other, and by giving us a present

concern for our past or future pains or pleasures.

As a memory alone acquaints us with the continuance and extent of this

succession of perceptions, it is to be considered, upon that account

chiefly, as the source of personal identity. Had we no memory, we never

should have any notion of causation, nor consequently of that chain of

causes and effects, which constitute our self or person.

But having once

acquired this notion of causation from the memory, we can extend the

same chain of causes, and consequently the identity of car persons

beyond our memory, and can comprehend times, and circumstances, and

actions, which we have entirely forgot, but suppose in general to have

existed. For how few of our past actions are there, of which we have

any memory? Who can tell me, for instance, what were his thoughts and

actions on the 1st of January 1715, the 11th of March 1719, and the 3rd

of August 1733? Or will he affirm, because he has entirely forgot the

incidents of these days, that the present self is not the same person

with the self of that time; and by that means overturn all the most

established notions of personal identity? In this view, therefore,

memory does not so much produce as discover personal identity, by

shewing us the relation of cause and effect among our different

perceptions. It will be incumbent on those, who affirm that memory

produces entirely our personal identity, to give a reason why we cm thus

extend our identity beyond our memory.

The whole of this doctrine leads us to a conclusion, which is of great

importance in the present affair, viz. that all the nice and subtile

questions concerning personal identity can never possibly be decided,

and are to be regarded rather as gramatical than as philosophical

difficulties. Identity depends on the relations of ideas; and these

relations produce identity, by means of that easy transition they

occasion. But as the relations, and the easiness of the transition may

diminish by insensible degrees, we have no just standard, by which we

can decide any dispute concerning the time, when they acquire or lose a

title to the name of identity. All the disputes concerning the identity

of connected objects are merely verbal, except so fax as the relation of

parts gives rise to some fiction or imaginary principle of union, as we

have already observed.

What I have said concerning the first origin and uncertainty of our

notion of identity, as applied to the human mind, may be extended with

little or no variation to that of simplicity. An object, whose different

co-existent parts are bound together by a close relation, operates upon

the imagination after much the same manner as one perfectly simple and

indivisible and requires not a much greater stretch of thought in order

to its conception. From this similarity of operation we attribute a

simplicity to it, and feign a principle of union as the support of this

simplicity, and the center of all the different parts and qualities of

the object.

Thus we have finished our examination of the several systems of

philosophy, both of the intellectual and natural world; and in our

miscellaneous way of reasoning have been led into several topics;

which will either illustrate and confirm some preceding part of this

discourse, or prepare the way for our following opinions. It is now time

to return to a more close examination of our subject, and to proceed in

the accurate anatomy of human nature, having fully explained the nature

of our judgment and understandings.

SECT. VII. CONCLUSION OF THIS BOOK.

But before I launch out into those immense depths of philosophy, which

lie before me, I find myself inclined to stop a moment in my present

station, and to ponder that voyage, which I have undertaken, and which

undoubtedly requires the utmost art and industry to be brought to a

happy conclusion. Methinks I am like a man, who having struck on many

shoals, and having narrowly escaped shipwreck in passing a small frith,

has yet the temerity to put out to sea in the same leaky weather-beaten

vessel, and even carries his ambition so far as to think of compassing

the globe under these disadvantageous circumstances. My memory of past

errors and perplexities, makes me diffident for the future. The wretched

condition, weakness, and disorder of the faculties, I must employ in my

enquiries, encrease my apprehensions. And the impossibility of amending

or correcting these faculties, reduces me almost to despair, and makes

me resolve to perish on the barren rock, on which I am at present,

rather than venture myself upon that boundless ocean, which runs

out into immensity. This sudden view of my danger strikes me with

melancholy; and as it is usual for that passion, above all others, to

indulge itself; I cannot forbear feeding my despair, with all those

desponding reflections, which the present subject furnishes me with in

such abundance.

I am first affrighted and confounded with that forelorn solitude,

in which I am placed in my philosophy, and fancy myself some strange

uncouth monster, who not being able to mingle and unite in society,

has been expelled all human commerce, and left utterly abandoned and

disconsolate. Fain would I run into the crowd for shelter and warmth;

but cannot prevail with myself to mix with such deformity. I call upon

others to join me, in order to make a company apart; but no one will

hearken to me. Every one keeps at a distance, and dreads that storm,

which beats upon me from every side. I have exposed myself to the enmity

of all metaphysicians, logicians, mathematicians, and even theologians;

and can I wonder at the insults I must suffer? I have declared my

disapprobation of their systems; and can I be surprized, if they should

express a hatred of mine and of my person? When I look abroad, I foresee

on every side, dispute, contradiction, anger, calumny and detraction.

When I turn my eye inward, I find nothing but doubt and ignorance.

All the world conspires to oppose and contradict me; though such is my

weakness, that I feel all my opinions loosen and fall of themselves,

when unsupported by the approbation of others. Every step I take is

with hesitation, and every new reflection makes me dread an error and

absurdity in my reasoning.

For with what confidence can I venture upon such bold enterprises, when

beside those numberless infirmities peculiar to myself, I find so many

which are common to human nature? Can I be sure, that in leaving all

established opinions I am following truth; and by what criterion shall

I distinguish her, even if fortune should at last guide me on her

foot-steps? After the most accurate and exact of my reasonings, I can

give no reason why I should assent to it; and feel nothing but a strong

propensity to consider objects strongly in that view, under which they

appear to me. Experience is a principle, which instructs me in

the several conjunctions of objects for the past. Habit is another

principle, which determines me to expect the same for the future; and

both of them conspiring to operate upon the imagination, make me form

certain ideas in a more intense and lively manner, than others, which

are not attended with the same advantages. Without this quality, by

which the mind enlivens some ideas beyond others (which seemingly is so

trivial, and so little founded on reason) we coued never assent to any

argument, nor carry our view beyond those few objects, which are present

to our senses. Nay, even to these objects we coued never attribute any

existence, but what was dependent on the senses; and must comprehend

them entirely in that succession of perceptions, which constitutes our

self or person. Nay farther, even with relation to that succession, we

coued only admit of those perceptions, which are immediately present to

our consciousness, nor coued those lively images, with which the memory

presents us, be ever received as true pictures of past perceptions. The

memory, senses, and understanding are, therefore, all of them founded on

the imagination, or the vivacity of our ideas.

No wonder a principle so inconstant and fallacious should lead us into

errors, when implicitly followed (as it must be) in all its variations.

It is this principle, which makes us reason from causes and effects; and

it is the same principle, which convinces us of the continued existence

of external objects, when absent from the senses. But though these two

operations be equally natural and necessary in the human mind, yet in

some circumstances they are [Sect. 4.] directly contrary, nor is it

possible for us to reason justly and regularly from causes and effects,

and at the same time believe the continued existence of matter. How

then shall we adjust those principles together? Which of them shall we

prefer? Or in case we prefer neither of them, but successively assent

to both, as is usual among philosophers, with what confidence can we

afterwards usurp that glorious title, when we thus knowingly embrace a

manifest contradiction?

This contradiction [Part III. Sect. 14.] would be more excusable, were

it compensated by any degree of solidity and satisfaction in the other

parts of our reasoning. But the case is quite contrary.

When we trace up

the human understanding to its first principles, we find it to lead us

into such sentiments, as seem to turn into ridicule all our past pains

and industry, and to discourage us from future enquiries. Nothing is

more curiously enquired after by the mind of man, than the causes of

every phenomenon; nor are we content with knowing the immediate causes,

but push on our enquiries, till we arrive at the original and ultimate

principle. We would not willingly stop before we are acquainted with

that energy in the cause, by which it operates on its effect; that tie,

which connects them together; and that efficacious quality, on which the

tie depends. This is our aim in all our studies and reflections: And

how must we be disappointed, when we learn, that this connexion, tie, or

energy lies merely in ourselves, and is nothing but that determination

of the mind, which is acquired by custom, and causes us to make

a transition from an object to its usual attendant, and from the

impression of one to the lively idea of the other? Such a discovery not

only cuts off all hope of ever attaining satisfaction, but even prevents

our very wishes; since it appears, that when we say we desire to know

the ultimate and operating principle, as something, which resides in

the external object, we either contradict ourselves, or talk without a

meaning.

This deficiency in our ideas is not, indeed, perceived in common life,

nor are we sensible, that in the most usual conjunctions of cause and

effect we are as ignorant of the ultimate principle, which binds them

together, as in the mos