A history of Jewish Medieval Philosophy by Isaac Husik - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

CHAPTER XV

LEVI BEN GERSON

Among the men who devoted themselves to philosophical investigation in the century and a half after Maimonides's

death, the greatest and most independent was without doubt Levi ben Gerson or Gersonides, as he is also called. There

were others who were active as commentators, translators and original writers, and who achieved a certain fame, but

their work was too little original to merit more than very brief notice in these pages. Isaac Albalag[331a] (second half of

thirteenth century) owes what reputation he enjoys to the boldness with which he enunciated certain doctrines, such as

the eternity of the world and particularly the notion, well enough known among the Averroists of the University of Paris at

that time and condemned by the Church, but never before announced or defended in Jewish philosophy—the so-called

doctrine of the twofold truth. This was an attitude assumed in self-defence, sincerely or not as the case may be, by a

number of scholastic writers, who advanced philosophic views at variance with the dogma of the Church. They

maintained that a given thesis might be true and false at the same time, true for philosophy and false for theology, or vice

versa.[332] Shem Tob Falaquera (1225-1290) is a more important man than Albalag. He was a thorough student of the

Aristotelian and other philosophy that was accessible to him through his knowledge of Arabic. Munk's success in

identifying Avicebron with Gabirol (p. 63) was made possible by Falaquera's translation into Hebrew of extracts from the

"Fons Vitæ." Of great importance also is Falaquera's commentary of Maimonides's "Guide," which, with that of Moses of

Narbonne (d. after 1362), is based upon a knowledge of Arabic and a thorough familiarity with the Aristotelian philosophy

of the Arabs, and is superior to the better known commentaries of Shemtob, Ephodi, and Abarbanel. Falaquera also

wrote original works of an ethical and philosophical character.

Joseph Ibn Caspi (1297-1340) is likewise a meritorious figure as a commentator of Maimonides and as a philosophical

exegete of Scripture. But none of these men stands out as an independent thinker with a strong individuality, carrying

forward in any important and authoritative degree the work of the great Maimonides. Great Talmudic knowledge, which

was a necessary qualification for national recognition, these men seem not to have had; and on the other hand none of

them felt called upon or able to make a systematic synthesis of philosophy and Judaism in a large way.

Levi ben Gerson (1288-1344) was the first after Maimonides who can at all be compared with the great sage of Fostat.

He was a great mathematician and astronomer; he wrote supercommentaries on the Aristotelian commentaries of

Averroes, who in his day had become the source of philosophical knowledge for the Hebrew student; he was thoroughly

versed in the Talmud as his commentary on the Pentateuch shows; and he is one of the recognized Biblical exegetes of

the middle ages. Finally in his philosophical masterpiece "Milhamot Adonai" (The Wars of the Lord), [333] he undertakes

to solve in a thoroughly scholastic manner those problems in philosophy and theology which Maimonides had either not

treated adequately or had not solved to Gersonides's satisfaction. That despite the technical character and style of the

"Milhamot," Gersonides achieved such great reputation shows in what esteem his learning and critical power were held

by his contemporaries. His works were all written in Hebrew, and if he had any knowledge of Arabic and Latin it was very

limited, too limited to enable him to make use of the important works written in those languages.[334] His fame extended

beyond the limits of Jewish thought, as is shown by the fact that his scientific treatise dealing with the astronomical

instrument he had discovered was translated into Latin in 1377 by order of Pope Clement VI, and his supercommentaries

on the early books of the Aristotelian logic were incorporated, in Latin translation, in the Latin editions of Aristotle and

Averroes of the 16th century.[335]

Levi ben Gerson's general attitude to philosophical study and its relation to the content of Scripture is the same as had

become common property through Maimonides and his predecessors. The happiness and perfection of man are the

purpose of religion and knowledge. This perfection of man, or which is the same thing, the perfection of the human soul,

is brought about through perfection in morals and in theoretical speculation, as will appear more clearly when we discuss

the nature of the human intellect and its immortality. Hence the purpose of the Bible is to lead man to perfect himself in

these two elements—morals and science. For this reason the Law consists of three parts. The first is the legal portion of

the Law containing the 613 commandments, mandatory and prohibitive, concerning belief and practice. This is

preparatory to the second and third divisions of the Pentateuch, which deal respectively with social and ethical conduct,

and the science of existence. As far as ethics is concerned it was not practicable to lay down definite commandments

and prohibitions because it is so extremely difficult to reach perfection in this aspect of life. Thus if the Torah gave

definite prescriptions for exercising and controlling our anger, our joy, our courage, and so on, the results would be very

discouraging, for the majority of men would be constantly disobeying them. And this would lead to the neglect of the

other commandments likewise. Hence the principles of social and ethical conduct are inculcated indirectly by means of

narratives exemplifying certain types of character in action and the consequences flowing from their conduct. The third

division, as was said before, contains certain teachings of a metaphysical character respecting the nature of existence.

This is the most important of all, and hence forms the beginning of the Pentateuch. The account of creation is a study in

the principles of philosophical physics.[336]

As to the relations of reason and belief or authority, Levi ben Gerson shares in the optimism of the Maimonidean school

and the philosophic middle age generally, that there is no opposition between them. The priority should be given to

reason where its demands are unequivocal, for the meaning of the Scriptures is not always clear and is subject to

interpretation.[337] On the other hand, after having devoted an entire book of his "Milhamot" to a minute investigation of

the nature of the human intellect and the conditions of its immortality, he disarms in advance all possible criticism of his

position from the religious point of view by saying that he is ready to abandon his doctrine if it is shown that it is in

disagreement with religious dogma. He developed his views, he tells us, because he believes that they are in agreement

with the words of the Torah. [338] This apparent contradiction is to be explained by making a distinction between the

abstract statement of the principle and the concrete application thereof. In general Levi ben Gerson is so convinced of

man's prerogative as a rational being that he cannot believe the Bible meant to force upon him the belief in things which

are opposed to reason. Hence, since the Bible is subject to interpretation, the demands of the reason are paramount

where they do not admit of doubt. On the other hand, where the traditional dogma of Judaism is clear and outspoken, it is

incumbent upon man to be modest and not to claim the infallibility of direct revelation for the limited powers of logical

inference and deduction.

We must now give a brief account of the questions discussed in the "Milhamot Adonai." And first a word about

Gersonides's style and method. One is reminded, in reading the Milhamot, of Aristotle as well as Thomas Aquinas. There

is no rhetoric and there are no superfluous words. All is precise and technical, and the vocabulary is small. One is

surprised to see how in a brief century or so the Hebrew language has become so flexible an instrument in the

expression of Aristotelian ideas. Levi ben Gerson does not labor in the expression of his thought. His linguistic instrument

is quite adequate and yields naturally to the manipulation of the author. Gersonides, the minute logician and analyst, has

no use for rhetorical flourishes and figures of speech. The subject, he says, is difficult enough as it is, without being

made more so by rhetorical obscuration, unless one intends to hide the confusion of one's thought under the mask of fine

writing.[339] Like Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas, he gives a history of the opinions of others in the topic under discussion,

and enumerates long lists of arguments pro and con with rigorous logical precision. The effect upon the reader is

monotonous and wearisome. Aristotle escapes this by the fact that he is groping his way before us. He has not all his

ideas formulated in proper order and form ready to deliver. He is primarily the investigator, not the pedagogue, and the

brevity and obscurity of his style pique the ambitious reader and spur him on to puzzle out the meaning. Not so Thomas

Aquinas and the scholastics generally. As the term scholastic indicates, they developed their method in the schools.

They were expositors of what was ready made, rather than searchers for the new. Hence the question of form was an

important one and was determined by the purpose of presenting one's ideas as clearly as may be to the student. Add to

this that the logic of Aristotle and the syllogism was the universal method of presentation and the monotony and

wearisomeness becomes evident. Levi ben Gerson is in this respect like Aquinas rather than like Aristotle. And he is the

first of his kind in Jewish literature. Since the larger views and problems were already common property, the efforts of

Gersonides were directed to a more minute discussion of the more technical details of such problems as the human

intellect, prophecy, Providence, creation, and so on. For this reason, too, it will not be necessary for us to do more than

give a brief résumé of the results of Gersonides's lucubrations without entering into the really bewildering and hair-

splitting arguments and distinctions which make the book so hard on the reader.

We have already had occasion in the Introduction (p. xxxvi) to refer briefly to Aristotle's theory of the intellect and the

distinction between the passive and the active intellects in man. The ideas of the Arabs were also referred to in our

treatment of Judah Halevi, Ibn Daud and Maimonides (pp. 180 f., 213 f., 282). Hillel ben Samuel, as we saw (p. 317 ff.),

was the first among the Jews who undertook to discuss in greater detail the essence of the three kinds of intellect,

material, acquired and active, as taught by the Mohammedan and Christian Scholastics, and devoted some space to the

question of the unity of the material intellect. Levi ben Gerson takes up the same question of the nature of the material

intellect and discusses the various views with more rigor and minuteness than any of his Jewish predecessors. His chief

source was Averroes. The principal views concerning the nature of the possible or material intellect in man were those

attributed to Alexander of Aphrodisias, the most important Greek commentator of Aristotle (lived about 200 of the

Christian Era), Themistius, another Aristotelian Greek commentator who lived in the time of Emperor Julian, and

Averroes, the famous Arabian philosopher and contemporary of Maimonides. All these three writers pretended to

expound Aristotle's views of the passive intellect rather than propound their own. And Levi ben Gerson discusses their

ideas before giving his own.

Alexander's idea of the passive intellect in man is that it is simply a capacity residing in the soul for receiving the

universal forms of material things. It has no substantiality of its own, and hence does not survive the lower functions of

the soul, namely, sensation and imagination, which die with the body. This passive intellect is actualized through the

Active Intellect, which is not a part of man at all, but is identified by Alexander with God. The Active Intellect is thus pure

form and actuality, and enables the material or possible intellect in man, originally a mere potentiality, to acquire general

ideas, and thus to become an intellect with a content. This is called the actual or acquired intellect, which though at first

dependent on the data of sense, may succeed later in continuing its activity unaided by sense perception. And in so far

as the acquired intellect thinks of the purely immaterial ideas and things which make up the content of the divine intellect

(the Active Intellect), it becomes identified with the latter and is immortal. The reason for supposing that the material

intellect in man is a mere capacity residing in the soul and not an independent substance is because as having the

capacity to receive all kinds of forms it must itself not be of any form. Thus in order that the sense of sight may receive all

colors as they are, it must itself be free from color. If the sight had a color of its own, this would prevent it from receiving

other colors. Applying this principle to the intellect we make the same inference that it must in itself be neutral, not

identified with any one idea or form, else this would color all else knocking for admission, and the mind would not know

things as they are. Now a faculty which has no form of its own, but is a mere mirror so to speak of all that may be

reflected in it, cannot be a substance, and must be simply a power inherent in a substance and subject to the same fate

as that in which it inheres. This explains the motive of Alexander's view and is at the same time a criticism of the doctrine

of Themistius.

This commentator is of the opinion that the passive intellect of which Aristotle speaks is not a mere capacity inherent in

something else, but a real spiritual entity or substance independent of the lower parts of the soul, though associated with

them during the life of the body, and hence is not subject to generation and destruction, but is eternal. In support of this

view may be urged that if the passive intellect were merely a capacity of the lower parts of the soul, we should expect it

to grow weaker as the person grows older and his sensitive and imaginative powers are beginning to decline; whereas

the contrary is the case. The older the person the keener is his intellect. The difficulty, however, remains that if the

human intellect is a real substance independent of the rest of the soul, why is it that at its first appearance in the human

being it is extremely poor in content, being all but empty, and grows as the rest of the body and the soul is developed?

To obviate these difficulties, Averroes in his commentary on the De Anima of Aristotle practically identifies (according to

Levi ben Gerson's view of Averroes) the material intellect with the Active Intellect. The Active Intellect according to him is

neither identical with the divine, as Alexander maintains, nor is it a part of man, as Themistius and others think, but is the

last of the separate Intelligences, next to the spiritual mover of the lunar sphere. It is a pure actuality, absolutely free from

matter, and hence eternal. This Active Intellect in some mysterious manner becomes associated with man, and this

association results in a temporary phase represented by the material intellect. As a result of the sense perceptions,

images of the external objects remain in the imagination, and the Active Intellect takes hold of these images, which are

potentially universal ideas, and by its illumination produces out of them actual ideas and an intellect in which they reside,

the material intellect. The material intellect is therefore the result of the combination of the Active Intellect with the

memory images, known as phantasmata (φαντάσματα), in the human faculty of imagination. So long as this association

exists, the material intellect receives the intelligible forms as derived from the phantasmata, and these forms are

represented by such ideas as "all animal is sensitive," "all man is rational," i. e., ideas concerning the objects of this

world. This phase of man's mind ceases when the body dies, and the Active Intellect alone remains, whose content is

free from material forms. The Active Intellect contemplates itself, a pure intelligence. At the same time it is possible for

man to identify himself with the Active Intellect as he acquires knowledge in the material intellect, for the Active Intellect is

like light which makes the eye see. In seeing, the eye not merely perceives the form of the external object, but indirectly

also receives the light which made the object visible. In the same way the human soul in acquiring knowledge as implicit

in its phantasmata, at the same time gets a glimpse of the spiritual light which converted the phantasma into an explicit

idea (cf. above, p. 320). When the soul in man perfects itself with all the knowledge of this world it becomes identified

with the Active Intellect, which may be likened to the intellect or soul of the corporeal world.

In this combination of the views of Alexander and Themistius Averroes succeeds in obviating the criticisms levelled at the

two former. That the power of the material intellect grows keener with age though the corporeal organs are weaker,

supports Averroes's doctrine as against Alexander, to whom it is a mere capacity dependent upon the mixture of the

elements in the human body. But neither is he subject to the objection applying to Themistius's view, that a real

independent entity could scarcely be void of all forms and a mere receptacle. For the material intellect as it really is in

itself when not in combination with the human body is not a mere receptacle or empty potentiality. It is the Active Intellect,

which combines in itself all immaterial forms and thinks them as it thinks itself. It is only in its individualized aspect that it

becomes a potential intellect ready to receive all material forms.

But what Averroes gains here he loses elsewhere. There are certain considerations which are fatal to his doctrine. Thus

it would follow that theoretical studies which have no practical aim are useless. But this is impossible. Nature has put in

us the ability as well as the desire to speculate without reference to practical results. The pleasure we derive from

theoretical studies is much greater than that afforded by the practical arts and trades. And nature does nothing in vain.

Theoretical studies must therefore have some value. But in Averroes's theory of the material intellect they have none. For

all values may be divided into those which promote the life of the body and those which lead to the final happiness of

man. The former is clearly not served by those theoretical speculations which have no practical aim. On the contrary,

they hinder it. Deep students of the theoretical sciences forego all bodily pleasures, and often do without necessities. But

neither can there be any advantage in theoretical speculation for ultimate human happiness. For human happiness

according to Averroes (and he is in a sense right, as we shall see later) consists in union with the Active Intellect. But this

union takes place as a matter of course according to his theory at the time of death, whether a man be wise or a fool. For

the Active Intellect then absorbs the material.

Another objection to Averroes's theory is the following. If the material intellect is in essence the same as the Active

Intellect, it is a separate, immaterial substance, and hence is, like the Active Intellect, one. For only that which has matter

as its substratum can be quantitatively differentiated. Thus A is numerically different from B, though A and B are both

men (i. e., qualitatively the same), because they are corporeal beings. Forms as such can be differentiated qualitatively

only. Horse is different from ass in quality. Horse as such and horse as such are the same. It follows from this that the

material intellect, being like the Active Intellect an immaterial form, cannot be numerically multiplied, and therefore is one

only. But if so, no end of absurdities follows. For it means that all men have the same intellect, hence the latter is wise

and ignorant at the same time in reference to the same thing, in so far as A knows a given thing and B does not know it.

It would also follow that A can make use of B's sense experience and build his knowledge upon it. All these inferences

are absurd, and they all follow from the assumption that the material intellect is in essence the same as the Active

Intellect. Hence Averroes's position is untenable.[340]

Gersonides then gives his own view of the material intellect, which is similar to that of Alexander. The material intellect is

a capacity, and the prime matter is the ultimate subject in which it inheres. But there are other powers or forms inhering

in matter prior to the material intellect. Prime matter as such is not endowed with intellect, or all things would have human

reason. Prime matter when it reaches the stage of development of the imaginative faculty is then ready to receive the

material intellect. We may say then that the sensitive soul, of which the imaginative faculty is a part, is the subject in

which the material intellect inheres. The criticism directed against Alexander, which applies here also, may be answered

as follows. The material intellect is dependent upon its subject, the sensitive soul, for its existence only, not for the

manner of receiving its knowledge. Hence the weakening or strengthening of its subject cannot affect it directly at all.

Indirectly there is a relation between the two, and it works in the reverse direction. When the sensitive powers are

weakened and their activities diminish, there is more opportunity for the intellect to monopolize the one soul for itself and

increase its own activity, which the other powers have a tendency to hinder, since the soul is one for all these contending

powers. It follows of course that the material intellect in man is not immortal. As a capacity of the sensitive soul, it dies

with the latter. What part of the human soul it is that enjoys immortality and on what conditions we shall see later. But

before we do this, we must try to understand the nature of the Active Intellect.[341]

We know now that the function of the Active Intellect is to actualize the material intellect, i. e., to develop the capacity

which the latter has of extracting general ideas from the particular memory images (phantasmata) in the faculty of

imagination, so that this capacity, originally empty of any content, receives the ideas thus produced, and is thus

constituted into an actual intellect. From this it follows that the Active Intellect, which enables the material intellect to form

ideas, must itself have the ideas it induces in the latter, though not necessarily in the same form. Thus an artisan, who

imposes the form of chair upon a piece of wood, must have the form of chair in his mind, though not the same sort as he

realizes in the wood. Now as all the ideas acquired by the material intellect constitute one single activity so far as the end

and purpose is concerned (for it all leads to the perfection of the person), the agent which is the cause of it all must also

be one. Hence there are not many Active Intellects, each responsible for certain ideas, but one Intellect is the cause of all

the ideas realized in the material intellect. Moreover, as this Active Intellect gives the material intellect not merely a

knowledge of separate ideas, but also an understanding of their relations to each other, in other words of the systematic

unity connecting all ideas into one whole, it follows that the Active Intellect has a knowledge of the ideas from their

unitary aspect. In other words, the unity of purpose and aim which is evident in the development of nature from the prime

matter through the forms of the elements, the plant soul, the animal soul and up to the human reason, where the lower is

for the sake of the higher, must reside as a unitary conception in the Active Intellect.

For the Active Intellect has another function besides developing the rational capacity in man. We can arrive at this insight

by a consideration undertaken from a different point of view. If we consider the wonderful and mysterious development of

a seed, which is only a piece of matter, in a purposive manner, passing through various stages and producing a highly

complicated organism with psychic powers, we must come to the conclusion, as Aristotle does, that there is an intellect

operating in this development. As all sublunar nature shows a unity of purpose, this intellect must be one. And as it

cannot be like one of its products, it must be eternal and not subject to generation and decay. But these are the

attributes which, on grounds taken from the consideration of the intellectual activity in man, we ascribed to the Active

Intellect. Hence it is the Active Intellect. And we have thus shown that it has two functions. One is to endow sublunar

nature with the intelligence and purpose visible in its processes and evolutions; the other is to enable the rational power

in man to rise from a tabula rasa to an actual intellect with a content. From both these activities it is evident that the

Active Intellect has a knowledge of sublunar creation as a systematic unity.

This conception of the Active Intellect, Levi ben Gerson says, will also answer all the difficulties by which other

philosophers are troubled concerning the possibility of knowledge and the nature of definition. The problems are briefly

these. Knowledge concerns itself with the permanent and universal. There can be no real knowledge of the particular, for

the particular is never the same, it is constantly changing and in the end disappears altogether. On the other hand, the