A history of Jewish Medieval Philosophy by Isaac Husik - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

CHAPTER III

SAADIA BEN JOSEPH AL-FAYYUMI (892-942)

Saadia was the first important Jewish philosopher. Philo of Alexandria does not come within our purview as he was not

mediæval. Besides his work is not systematic, being in the nature of a commentary on Holy Writ. Though Philo was a

good and loyal Jew, he stood, so to speak, apart from the real centre of Jewish intellectual and spiritual development. He

was on the one hand too closely dependent on Greek thought and on the other had only a limited knowledge of Jewish

thought and tradition. The Bible he knew only in the Greek translation, not in the original Hebrew; and of the Halaka,

which was still in the making in Palestine, he knew still less.

It was different with Saadia. In the tenth century the Mishna and the Talmud had been long completed and formed

theoretically as well as practically the content of the Jew's life and thought. Sura in Babylonia, where Saadia was the

head of the academy, was the chief centre of Jewish learning, and Saadia was the heir in the main line of Jewish

development as it passed through the hands of lawgiver and prophet, scribe and Pharisee, Tanna and Amora, Saburai

and Gaon. As the head of the Sura academy he was the intellectual representative of the Jewry and Judaism of his day.

His time was a period of agitation and strife, not only in Judaism but also in Islam, in whose lands the Jews lived and to

whose temporal rulers they owed allegiance in the East as well as in Spain.

In Islam we saw in the introduction how the various schools of the Kadariya, the Muʿtazila and the Ashariya arose in

obedience to the demand of clarifying the chief problems of faith, science and life. In Judaism there was in addition to this

more general demand the more local and internal conflict of Karaite and Rabbanite which centred about the problem of

tradition. Saadia found himself in the midst of all this and proved equal to the occasion.

We are not here concerned with the vicissitudes of Saadia's personal life or of his literary career as opponent of the

Karaite sect. Nor can we afford more than merely to state that Jewish science in the larger sense begins with Saadia.

Hebrew grammar and lexicography did not exist before him. The Bible had been translated into several languages before

Saadia's day, but he was the first to translate it into Arabic, and the first to write a commentary on it. But the greatest

work of Saadia, that which did the most important service to the theory of Judaism, and by which he will be best

remembered, is his endeavor to work out a system of doctrine which should be in harmony with the traditions of Judaism

on the one hand and with the most authoritative scientific and philosophic opinion of the time on the other. Israeli, we

have seen, was interested in science before Saadia. As a physician he was probably more at home in purely physical

discussions than Saadia. But there is no evidence that he had the larger interest of the Gaon of Sura, namely, to

construct a system of Judaism upon the basis of scientific doctrine. Possibly the example of Islam was lacking in Israeli's

environment, as he does not seem to be acquainted with the theories and discussions of the Mutakallimun, and draws

his information from Aristotelian and Neo-Platonic sources. Saadia was in the very midst of Arab speculation as is

evident from the composition of his chef d'œuvre, "Emunot ve-Deot," Beliefs and Opinions.[37]

The work is arranged on the Muʿtazilite model. The two main divisions in works of this character are Unity and Justice.

The first begins with some preliminary considerations on the nature and sources of knowledge. It proceeds then to prove

the existence of God by showing that the world cannot have existed from eternity and must have been created in time.

Creation implies a creator. This is followed by arguments showing that God is one and incorporeal. The rest is devoted

to a discussion of the divine attributes with the purpose of showing that God's unity and simplicity are not affected by

them. The section on unity closes with a refutation of opposing views, such as those of the dualists or Trinitarians or

infidels. The section on Justice centres about the doctrine of free will. Hence psychology and ethics are treated in this

part of the work. To this may be added problems of a more dogmatic nature, eschatological and otherwise. We shall see

in the sequel that Saadia's masterpiece is modeled on the same plan.

But not merely the plan and arrangement of his work give evidence of the influence upon Saadia of Islamic schools,

many of his arguments, those for example on the existence of God and the creation of the world, are taken directly from

them. Maimonides, who was a strong opponent of the Mutakallimun, gives an outline of their fundamental principles and

their arguments for the existence, unity and incorporeality of God.[38] Some of these are identical with those of Saadia.

Saadia, however, is not interested in pure metaphysics as such. His purpose is decidedly apologetic in the defence of

Judaism and Jewish dogma. Hence we look in vain in his book for definite views on the constitution of existing

substances, on the nature of motion, on the meaning of cause, and so on. We get a glimpse of his attitude to some of

these questions in an incidental way.

The Mutakallimun were opposed to the Aristotelian theory of matter and form, and substituted for it the atomic theory.

God created atoms without magnitude or quality, and he likewise created qualities to inhere in groups of atoms. These

qualities they called accidents, and one of their important discussions was whether an accident can last more than a

moment of time. The opinions were various and the accidents were classified according to their powers of duration. That

is, there were some accidents which once created continued to exist of their own accord some length of time, and there

were others which had to be re-created anew every moment in order to continue to exist. Saadia does not speak of

matter and form as constituting the essence of existing things; he does speak of substance and accident,[39] which might

lead us to believe that he held to the atomic theory, since he speaks of the accidents as coming and going one after the

other, which suggests the constant creation spoken of by the Mutakallimun. On the other hand, when he answers an

objection against motion, which is as old as Zeno, namely, how can we traverse an infinitely divisible distance, since it is

necessary to pass an infinite number of parts, he tells us that it is not necessary to have recourse to the atomic theory or

other theories adopted by some Muʿtazilites to meet this objection. We may believe in the continuity and infinite

divisibility of matter, but as long as this divisibility is only potentially infinite, actually always finite, our ability to traverse

the space offers no difficulty.[40] Finally, in refuting the second theory of creation, which combines Platonism with

atomism, he argues against an atomic theory primarily because of its implications of eternity of the atoms, but partly also

on other grounds, which would also affect the Kalamistic conceptions of the atoms.[41] These points are not treated by

Saadia expressly but are only mentioned incidentally in the elucidation of other problems dealing with the creation of the

world and the existence of God.

Like Israeli Saadia shows considerable familiarity with Aristotelian notions as found in the Logic, the Physics and the

Psychology. It is doubtful, however, whether he really knew Aristotle's more important treatises at first hand and in detail.

The "Categories," a small treatise forming the first book of Aristotle's logic, he no doubt knew, but the other Aristotelian

concepts he probably derived from secondary sources. For while he passes in review all the ten categories showing that

none of them is applicable to God,[42] we scarcely find any mention of such important and fundamental Aristotelian

conceptions as matter and form, potentiality and actuality, the four causes, formal, material, efficient and final—concepts

which as soon as Aristotle began to be studied by Al Farabi and Avicenna became familiar to all who wrote anything at all

bearing on philosophy, theology, or Biblical exegesis. Nay, the very concepts which he does employ seem to indicate in

the way he uses them that he was not familiar with the context in which they are found in the Aristotelian treatises, or with

the relation they bear to other views of Aristotle. Thus no one who knew Aristotle at first hand could make the mistake of

regarding his definition of the soul as making the latter an accident.[43] When Saadia speaks of six kinds of motion [44]

instead of three, he shows clearly that his knowledge of the Aristotelian theory of motion was limited to the little of it that

is contained in the "Categories."

We are thus justified in saying, that Saadia's sources are Jewish literature and tradition, the works of the Mutakallimun,

particularly the Muʿtazilites, and Aristotle, whose book on the "Categories" he knew at first hand.

Saadia tells us he was induced to write his book because he found that the beliefs and opinions of men were in an

unsatisfactory state. While there are some persons who are fortunate enough to possess the truth and to know that they

have it and rejoice thereat, this is not true of all. For there are others who when they have the truth know it not, and

hence let it slip; others are still less fortunate and adopt false and erroneous opinions, which they regard as true; while

still others vacillate continually, going from one opinion and belief to another. This gave him pain and he thought it his

duty to make use of his limited knowledge to help them. A conscientious study of his book will tend to remove doubt and

will substitute belief through knowledge for belief through tradition. Another result of such study, not less important, will

be improvement of character and disposition, which will affect for the better a man's life in every respect, in relation to

God as well as to his fellowmen.[45]

One may ask why it is that one encounters so many doubts and difficulties before arriving at true knowledge. The answer

is, a human being is a creature, i. e., a being dependent upon another for its existence, and it is in the nature of a

creature as such that it must labor for the truth with the sweat of its brow. For whatever a man does or has to do with is

subject to time; each work must be accomplished gradually, step by step, part by part, in successive portions of time. And

as the task before him is at the beginning complex, he has to analyze and simplify it. This takes time; while certainty and

knowledge cannot come until the task is accomplished. Before that point is reached he is naturally in doubt.[46]

The sources of truth are three. First is that to which the senses testify. If our normal sense perceives under normal

conditions which are free from illusion, we are certain of that perception.

The judgment is another source of truth. There are certain truths of which we are certain. This applies especially to such

judgments of value, as that truth is good and falsehood is bad. In addition to these two sources of immediate knowledge,

there is a third source based upon these two. This is logical inference. We are led to believe what we have not directly

perceived or a matter concerning which we have no immediate knowledge of the second kind, because we infer it from

something else which we have perceived or of which we have immediate certainty. Thus we believe man has a soul

though we have never seen it because we infer its presence from its activity, which we do see.

These three sources are universal. They are not peculiar to a given race or religious denomination, though there are

some persons who deny the validity of some or all of them. We Jews believe in them and in still another source of truth,

namely, authentic tradition.[47]

Some think that a Jew is forbidden to speculate or philosophize about the truths of religion. This is not so. Genuine and

sincere reflection and speculation is not prohibited. What is forbidden is to leave the sacred writings aside and rely on

any opinions that occur to one concerning the beginnings of time and space. For one may find the truth or one may miss

it. In any case until a person finds it, he is without a religious guide; and if he does find what seems to him the truth and

bases his belief and conduct upon it, he is never sure that he may not later be assailed by doubts, which will lead him to

drop his adopted belief. But if we hold fast to the commandments of the Bible, our own ratiocination on the truths of

religion will be of great benefit to us.[48]

Our investigation of the facts of our religion will give us a reasoned and scientific knowledge of those things which the

Prophets taught us dogmatically, and will enable us to answer the arguments and criticisms of our opponents directed

against our faith. Hence it is not merely our privilege but our duty to confirm the truths of religion by reason.[49]

Here a question presents itself. If the reason can discover by itself the truths communicated to us by divine revelation,

why was it necessary to have recourse to the latter? Why was it not left to the reason alone to guide us in our belief and

in our conduct? The answer is, as was suggested before, that human reason proceeds gradually and does not reach its

aim until the end of the process. In the meantime one is left without a guide. Besides not everybody's reason is adequate

to discover truth. Some are altogether incapable of this difficult task, and many more are exposed to harassing doubts

and perplexities which hinder their progress. Hence the necessity of revelation, because in the witness of the senses all

are equally at home, men and women, young and old.[50]

The most important fact of religion is the existence of God. We know it from the Bible, and we must now prove it by

reason. The proof is necessarily indirect because no one of us has seen God, nor have we an immediate certainty of his

existence. We must prove it then by the method of inference. We must start with something we do know with certainty

and proceed from it through as many steps of logical inference as may be necessary until we reach the object of our

search.[51]

The world and the things in it are directly accessible to our senses and our judgment. How long has the world been in

existence and how did it come to be? The answers to these questions also we do not know through our senses, and we

must prove them by a chain of reasoning. There are several possibilities. The world just as it is may have existed from

eternity. If so nobody made it; it just existed, and we have no proof of God. The world in its present form might have

proceeded from a primitive matter. This hypothesis only removes the problem further back. For, leaving aside the

question how did this prime matter develop into the complex world of our experience, we direct our attention to the prime

matter itself, and ask, Has it existed from eternity or did it come to be? If it existed from eternity, then nobody made it, and

we have no proof of a God, for by God we mean an intelligent being acting with purpose and design, and the cause of

the existence of everything in creation. The third alternative is that whether the world was developed out of a primitive

matter or not, it at any rate, or the primitive matter, as the case may be, was made in time, that is, it was created out of

nothing. If so there must have been someone who created it, as nothing can create itself. Here we have proof of the

existence of God. It follows therefore that we must first show that the world is not eternal, that it came to be in time, and

this is what Saadia does.

Here are some of his proofs. The world is finite in magnitude. For the world consists of the earth, which is in the centre,

and the heavens surrounding it on all sides. This shows that the earth is finite, for an infinite body cannot be surrounded.

But the heavens are finite too, for they make a complete revolution in twenty-four hours. If they were infinite it would take

an infinite time to complete a revolution. A finite body cannot have an infinite power. This Saadia regards as self-evident,

though Aristotle, from whom this statement is derived, gives the proof. Hence the force or power within the world which

keeps it going is finite and must one day be exhausted. But this shows also that it could not have gone on from eternity.

Hence the world came to be in time.[52]

Another proof is based on the composite character of all things in heaven and earth. Minerals, plants and animals are

made up of parts and elements. The heavens consist of spheres, one within the other. The spheres are studded with

stars. But composition implies a time when the composition took place. In other words, the parts must have been there

first and somebody put them together. Hence the world as we see it now is not eternal.[53]

A special form of composition, which is universal, is that of substance and accident. Plants and animals are born (or

sprout), grow and decay. These manifestations are the accidents of the plant or animal's substance. The heavenly

bodies have various motions, lights and colors as their accidents. But these accidents are not eternal, since they come

and go. Hence the substances bearing the accidents, without which they cannot exist, are also temporal like them.

Hence our world is not eternal.[54]

Finally, past time itself cannot be eternal. For this would mean that an infinite time has actually elapsed down to our day.

But this is a contradiction in terms. What is already accomplished cannot be infinite. Infinity is possible only as a

potentiality, for example, we may speak of a given length as infinitely divisible. This merely means that one may mentally

continue dividing it forever, but we can never say that one has actually made an infinite number of divisions. Therefore

not merely the world, but even time must have begun to be.[55]

It will be seen that the first three arguments prove only that the world in the form which it has now is not eternal. The

possibility is not yet excluded of an eternal matter out of which the world proceeded or was made. The fourth argument

proves a great deal. It shows that nothing which is subject to time can be eternal, hence not even prime matter. God can

be eternal because he is not subject to time. Time, as we shall see later, cannot exist without motion and moving things,

hence before the world there was no time, and the fourth argument does not apply to premundane existence.

To complete the first three arguments Saadia therefore proceeds to show that the world, which we now know came to be

in time, must have been made by someone (since nothing can make itself), and that too out of nothing, and not out of a

pre-existing eternal matter.

If an eternal matter existed before the world, the explanation of the origin of the world is open to two possibilities. One is

that there is nothing outside of this matter and the world which came from it. This is absurd, for it would mean that an

unintelligent dead thing is the cause of intelligence and life in the universe. We must therefore have recourse to the other

alternative that someone, an intelligent being, made the world out of the primitive, eternal matter. This is also impossible.

For if the matter is eternal like the maker of the world, it is independent of him, and would not be obedient to his will to

adapt itself to his purpose. He could therefore not make the world out of it.

The only alternative left now is that the author of the universe is an intelligent being, and that nothing outside of him is

eternal. He alone is responsible for the existence of the world, which was at one time nothing. Whether he first created a

matter and then from it the universe, or whether he made the world outright, is of secondary importance.[56]

There is still a possibility that instead of making the world out of nothing, God made it out of himself, i. e., that it

emanated from him as light from the sun. This, as we know, is the opinion of the Neo-Platonists; and Israeli comes very

close to it as we saw before (p. 6). Saadia is strongly opposed to any such doctrine.

It is unlikely, he says, that an eternal substance having neither form, condition, measure, place or time, should change

into a body or bodies having those accidents; or that a wise being, not subject to change or influence, or

comprehensibility should choose to make himself into a body subject to all of these. What could have induced a just

being who does no wrong to decree that some of his parts should be subject to such evils as matter and material beings

are afflicted with? It is conceivable only in one of two ways. Either they deserved it for having done wrong, or they did not

deserve it, and it was an act of violence that was committed against them. Both suppositions are absurd. The fact of the

matter is that the authors of this opinion to avoid the theory of creation ex nihilo went from the frying pan into the fire. To

be sure, creation out of nothing is difficult to conceive, but this is the reason why we ascribe this power to God alone. To

demand that we show how this can be done is to demand that we ourselves become creators.[57]

The question what existed in place of the earth before it was created evinces ignorance of the idea of place. By place is

meant simply the contact of two bodies in which the one is the place of the other. When there is no earth and no bodies

there is no such thing as place.

The same thing applies to time. Time means the persistence of existing things in heaven and earth under changing

conditions. Where there is no world, there is no time. This answers the objection raised by some, namely, how is it

possible that before all these bodies were made time existed void of objects? Or the other difficulty which is closely

related, viz., Why did not God create the world before he did? The answer to both is, there was no before and there was

no time, when the world was not.

The following question is a legitimate one, Why did God create all things? And our answer is, there was no cause which

made him create them, and yet they were not made in vain. God wished to exhibit his wisdom; and his goodness

prompted him to benefit his creatures by enabling them to worship him.[58]

We have now proved the existence of God as the cause of the existence of all things. We must now try to arrive at some

notion of what God is as far as this is in our power. God cannot be corporeal or body, for in our proof of his existence we

began with the world which is body and arrived at the notion of God as the cause of all corporeal existence. If God

himself is corporeal our search is not at an end, for we should still want to know the cause of him. Being the cause of all

body, he is not body and hence is for our knowledge ultimate, we cannot go beyond him. But if God is not corporeal, he

is not subject to motion or rest or anger or favor, for to deny the corporeality of God and still look for these accidents in

him is to change the expression and retain the idea. Bodily accidents involve body.[59]

The incorporeality of God proves also his unity. For what is not body cannot have the corporeal attributes of quantity or

number, hence God cannot be more than one.[60] And there are many powerful arguments besides against a dualistic

theory.

A unitary effect cannot be the result of two independent causes. For if one is responsible for the whole, there is nothing

left for the other, and the assumption of his existence is gratuitous. If the effect consists of two parts of which each does

one, we have really two effects. But the universe is one and its parts cannot be separated.[61] Again, if one of them

wishes to create a thing and cannot without the help of the other, neither is all-powerful, which is inconsistent with the

character of deity. If he can compel the other to help him, they are both under necessity. And if they are free and

independent, then if one should desire to keep a body alive and the other to kill it, the body would have to be at the same

time alive and dead, which is absurd. Again, if each one can conceal aught from the other, neither is all-knowing. If they

cannot, they are not all-powerful.[62]

Having proved God's existence, unity and incorporeality, he proceeds to discuss his most essential attributes, which are,

Life, Omnipotence, and Omniscience. These easily follow from what was said before. We cannot conceive a creator ex

nihilo unless he is all-powerful; power implies life; and the thing made cannot be perfect unless its maker knows what it

is going to be before he makes it.

These three concepts our reason discovers with one act of its thinking effort, for they are all involved in the concept,

Maker. There is no gradual inference from one to the other. The reason we are forced to use three expressions is

because of the limitations of language. Hence it must not be thought that they involve plurality in God. They are simply

the implications of the one expression, Maker, and as that does not suggest plurality in God's essence, but signifies only

that there is a thing made by the maker, so the three derivative terms, Living, Omnipotent, Omniscient, imply no more.

The Christians erred in this matter in making God a trinity. They say one cannot create unless he is living and wise,

hence they regard his life and his wisdom as two other things outside of his essence. But this is a mistake. For in saying

there are several attributes in him distinct one from the other, they say in effect that he is corporeal—an error which we

have already refuted. Besides they do not understand what constitutes proof: In man we say that his life and his

knowledge are not his essence because we see that he sometimes has them and sometimes not. In God this is not the