Beyond Good and Evil by Friedrich Nietzsche - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

Chapter VII. Our Virtues

214. OUR Virtues?--It is probable that we, too, have still our virtues, although naturally they  are  not  those  sincere  and  massive  virtues  on  account  of  which  we  hold  our grandfathers in esteem and also at a little distance from us. We Europeans of the day after tomorrow,  we  firstlings  of  the  twentieth  century--with  all  our  dangerous  curiosity,  our multifariousness and art of disguising, our mellow and seemingly sweetened cruelty in sense and spirit--we shall presumably, IF we must have virtues, have those only which have  come  to  agreement  with  our  most  secret and heartfelt inclinations, with our most ardent  requirements:  well,  then,  let  us  look  for  them  in  our  labyrinths!--where,  as  we know,  so  many  things  lose  themselves,  so  many  things  get  quite  lost!  And  is  there anything finer than to SEARCH for one's own virtues? Is it not almost to BELIEVE in one's own virtues? But this "believing in one's own virtues"--is it not practically the same as what was formerly called one's "good conscience," that long, respectable pigtail of an idea,  which  our  grandfathers  used  to  hang  behind  their  heads,  and  often  enough  also behind  their  understandings?  It  seems,  therefore,  that  however  little  we  may  imagine ourselves to be old-fashioned and grandfatherly respectable in other respects, in one thing we are nevertheless the worthy grandchildren of our grandfathers, we last Europeans with good consciences: we also still wear their pigtail.--Ah! if you only knew how soon, so very soon--it will be different!

215. As in the stellar firmament there are sometimes two suns which determine the path of one planet, and in certain cases suns of different colours shine around a single planet, now with red light, now with green, and then simultaneously illumine and flood it with motley  colours:  so  we  modern  men,  owing  to  the  complicated  mechanism  of  our "firmament," are determined by DIFFERENT moralities; our actions shine alternately in different colours, and are seldom unequivocal--and there are often cases, also, in which our actions are MOTLEY-COLOURED.

216. To love one's enemies? I think that has been well learnt: it takes place thousands of times at present on a large and small scale; indeed, at times the higher and sublimer thing takes place:--we learn to DESPISE when we love, and precisely when we love best; all of it,  however,  unconsciously,  without  noise,  without  ostentation,  with  the  shame  and secrecy of goodness, which forbids the utterance of the pompous word and the formula of virtue. Morality as attitude--is opposed to our taste nowadays. This is ALSO an advance, as it was an advance in our fathers that religion as an attitude finally became opposed to their  taste,  including  the  enmity  and  Voltairean  bitterness  against  religion  (and  all  that formerly  belonged  to  freethinker-  pantomime).  It  is  the  music  in  our  conscience,  the dance in our spirit, to which Puritan litanies, moral sermons, and goody- goodness won't chime.

217. Let us be careful in dealing with those who attach great importance to being credited with  moral  tact  and  subtlety  in  moral  discernment!  They never  forgive us if they have once  made  a  mistake  BEFORE  us  (or  even  with  REGARD  to  us)--they  inevitably become  our  instinctive  calumniators  and  detractors,  even  when  they  still  remain  our "friends."--Blessed are the forgetful: for they "get the better" even of their blunders.

218.   The   psychologists   of   France--and   where   else   are   there   still   psychologists nowadays?--have never yet exhausted their bitter and manifold enjoyment of the betise bourgeoise,  just  as  though  .  .  .  in  short,  they  betray  something  thereby.  Flaubert,  for instance, the honest citizen of Rouen, neither saw, heard, nor tasted anything else in the end; it was his mode of self-torment and refined cruelty. As this is growing wearisome, I would   now   recommend   for   a   change   something   else   for   a   pleasure--namely,   the unconscious astuteness with which good, fat, honest mediocrity always behaves towards loftier spirits and the tasks they have to perform, the subtle, barbed, Jesuitical astuteness, which is a thousand times subtler than the taste and understanding of the middle-class in its  best  moments--subtler  even  than  the  understanding  of  its  victims:--a  repeated  proof that "instinct" is the most intelligent of all kinds of intelligence which have hitherto been discovered. In short, you psychologists, study the philosophy of the "rule" in its struggle with the "exception": there you have a spectacle fit for Gods and godlike malignity! Or, in plainer words, practise vivisection on "good people," on the "homo bonae voluntatis," ON YOURSELVES!

219.  The  practice  of  judging  and  condemning  morally,  is  the  favourite  revenge  of  the intellectually  shallow  on  those  who  are  less  so, it  is  also  a kind  of indemnity  for  their being badly endowed by nature, and finally, it is an opportunity for acquiring spirit and BECOMING subtle--malice spiritualises. They are glad in their inmost heart that there is a standard according to which those who are over-endowed with intellectual goods and privileges,  are  equal  to  them,  they  contend  for  the  "equality  of  all  before  God,"  and almost NEED the belief in God for this purpose. It is among them that the most powerful antagonists of atheism are found. If any one were to say to them "A lofty spirituality is beyond  all  comparison  with  the  honesty  and  respectability  of  a  merely  moral  man"--it would make them furious, I shall take care not to say so. I would rather flatter them with my  theory  that  lofty  spirituality  itself  exists  only  as  the  ultimate  product  of  moral qualities, that it is a synthesis of all qualities attributed to the "merely moral" man, after they  have  been  acquired  singly  through  long  training  and  practice,  perhaps  during  a whole series of generations, that lofty spirituality is precisely the spiritualising of justice, and the beneficent severity which knows that it is authorized to maintain GRADATIONS OF RANK in the world, even among things--and not only among men.

220. Now that the praise of the "disinterested person" is so popular one must--probably not without some danger--get an idea of WHAT people actually take an interest in, and what  are  the  things  generally  which  fundamentally  and  profoundly  concern  ordinary men--including   the   cultured,   even   the   learned,   and   perhaps   philosophers   also,   if appearances  do  not  deceive.  The  fact  thereby becomes  obvious  that  the  greater  part  of what interests and charms higher natures, and more refined and fastidious tastes, seems absolutely "uninteresting" to the average man--if, notwithstanding, he perceive devotion to  these  interests,  he  calls  it  desinteresse,  and  wonders  how  it  is  possible  to  act "disinterestedly."   There   have   been   philosophers   who   could   give   this   popular astonishment a seductive and mystical, other-worldly expression (perhaps because they  did not know the higher nature by experience?), instead of stating the naked and candidly reasonable  truth  that  "disinterested"  action  is  very  interesting  and  "interested"  action, provided   that.   .   .   "And   love?"--What!   Even   an   action   for   love's   sake   shall   be "unegoistic"? But you fools--! "And the praise of the self- sacrificer?"--But whoever has really  offered  sacrifice  knows  that  he  wanted  and  obtained  something  for  it--perhaps something from himself for something from himself; that he relinquished here in order to have more there, perhaps in general to be more, or even feel himself "more." But this is a realm of questions and answers in which a more fastidious spirit does not like to stay: for here truth has to stifle her yawns so much when she is obliged to answer. And after all, truth is a woman; one must not use force with her.

221. "It sometimes happens," said a moralistic pedant and trifle- retailer, "that I honour and respect an unselfish man: not, however, because he is unselfish, but because I think he has a right to be useful to another man at his own expense. In short, the question is always  who  HE  is,  and  who  THE  OTHER  is.  For  instance,  in  a  person  created  and destined for command, self- denial and modest retirement, instead of being virtues, would be  the  waste  of virtues:  so  it  seems  to  me.  Every  system of unegoistic morality  which takes itself unconditionally and appeals to every one, not only sins against good taste, but is also an incentive to sins of omission, an ADDITIONAL seduction under the mask of philanthropy--and  precisely  a  seduction  and  injury  to  the  higher,  rarer,  and  more privileged types of men. Moral systems must be compelled first of all to bow before the GRADATIONS OF RANK; their presumption must be driven home to their conscience-- until they thoroughly understand at last that it is IMMORAL to say that 'what is right for one is proper for another.'"--So said my moralistic pedant and bonhomme. Did he perhaps deserve to be laughed at when he thus exhorted systems of morals to practise morality? But one should not be too much in the right if one wishes to have the laughers on ONE'S OWN side; a grain of wrong pertains even to good taste.

222.  Wherever  sympathy  (fellow-suffering)  is  preached  nowadays--  and,  if  I  gather rightly, no other religion is any longer preached--let the psychologist have his ears open through all the vanity, through all the noise which is natural to these preachers (as to all preachers),  he  will  hear  a  hoarse,  groaning,  genuine  note  of  SELF-CONTEMPT.  It belongs to the overshadowing and uglifying of Europe, which has been on the increase for  a  century  (the  first  symptoms  of  which  are  already  specified  documentarily  in  a thoughtful letter of Galiani to Madame d'Epinay)--IF IT IS NOT REALLY THE CAUSE THEREOF!  The  man  of  "modern  ideas,"  the  conceited  ape,  is  excessively  dissatisfied with  himself--this  is  perfectly  certain.  He  suffers,  and  his  vanity  wants  him  only  "to suffer with his fellows."

223. The hybrid European--a tolerably ugly plebeian, taken all in all--absolutely requires a costume: he needs history as a storeroom of costumes. To be sure, he notices that none of the costumes fit him properly--he changes and changes. Let us look at the nineteenth century with respect to these hasty preferences and changes in its masquerades of style, and also with respect to its moments of desperation on account of "nothing suiting" us. It is  in  vain  to  get  ourselves  up  as  romantic,  or  classical,  or  Christian,  or  Florentine,  or barocco,  or  "national,"  in  moribus  et  artibus:  it  does  not  "clothe  us"!  But  the  "spirit,"  especially the "historical spirit," profits even by this desperation: once and again a new sample of the past or of the foreign is tested, put on, taken off, packed up, and above all studied--we are the first studious age in puncto of "costumes," I mean as concerns morals, articles of belief, artistic tastes, and religions; we are prepared as no other age has ever been  for  a  carnival  in  the  grand  style,  for  the  most  spiritual  festival--laughter  and arrogance, for the transcendental height of supreme folly and Aristophanic ridicule of the world. Perhaps we are still discovering the domain of our invention just here, the domain where even we can still be original, probably as parodists of the world's history and as God's  Merry-Andrews,--perhaps,  though  nothing  else  of  the  present  have  a  future,  our laughter itself may have a future!

224. The historical sense (or the capacity  for  divining  quickly the order of rank of the valuations  according  to  which  a  people,  a  community,  or  an  individual  has  lived,  the "divining  instinct"  for  the  relationships  of  these  valuations,  for  the  relation  of  the authority of the valuations to the authority of the operating forces),--this historical sense, which we Europeans claim as our specialty, has come to us in the train of the enchanting and mad semi-barbarity into which Europe has been plunged by the democratic mingling of classes and races--it is only the nineteenth century that has recognized this faculty as its sixth sense. Owing to this mingling, the past of every form and mode of life, and of cultures which were formerly closely contiguous and superimposed on one another, flows forth into us "modern souls"; our instincts now run back in all directions, we ourselves are a kind of chaos: in the end, as we have said, the spirit perceives its advantage therein. By means of our semi-barbarity in body and in desire, we have secret access everywhere, such  as  a  noble  age  never  had;  we  have  access  above  all  to  the  labyrinth  of  imperfect civilizations, and to every form of semi-barbarity that has at any time existed on earth; and in so far as the most considerable part of human civilization hitherto has just been semi-barbarity, the "historical sense" implies almost the sense and instinct for everything, the  taste  and  tongue  for  everything:  whereby  it  immediately  proves  itself  to  be  an IGNOBLE sense.  For  instance,  we  enjoy  Homer  once  more:  it  is  perhaps  our  happiest acquisition that we know how to appreciate Homer, whom men of distinguished culture (as the French of the seventeenth century, like Saint- Evremond, who reproached him for his ESPRIT VASTE, and even Voltaire, the last echo of the century) cannot and could not so easily appropriate--whom they scarcely permitted themselves to enjoy. The very decided  Yea  and  Nay  of  their  palate,  their  promptly  ready  disgust,  their  hesitating reluctance with regard to everything strange, their horror of the bad taste even of lively curiosity, and in general the averseness of every distinguished and self-sufficing culture to avow a new desire, a dissatisfaction with its own condition, or an admiration of what is strange: all this determines and disposes them unfavourably even towards the best things of the world which are not their property or could not become their prey--and no faculty is  more  unintelligible  to  such  men  than  just  this  historical  sense,  with  its  truckling, plebeian curiosity. The case is not different with Shakespeare, that marvelous Spanish- Moorish-Saxon  synthesis  of  taste,  over  whom  an  ancient  Athenian  of  the  circle  of AEschylus  would  have  half-killed  himself  with  laughter  or  irritation:  but  we--accept precisely this wild motleyness, this medley of the most delicate, the most coarse, and the most artificial, with a secret confidence and cordiality; we enjoy it as a refinement of art reserved expressly for us, and allow ourselves to be as little disturbed by the repulsive  fumes  and  the  proximity  of  the  English  populace  in  which  Shakespeare's  art  and  taste lives, as perhaps on the Chiaja of Naples, where, with all our senses awake, we go our way, enchanted and voluntarily, in spite of the drain-odour of the lower quarters of the town. That as men of the "historical sense" we have our virtues, is not to be disputed:-- we  are  unpretentious,  unselfish,  modest,  brave,  habituated  to  self-control  and  self- renunciation,  very  grateful,  very  patient,  very  complaisant--but  with  all  this  we  are perhaps not very "tasteful." Let us finally confess it, that what is most difficult for us men of  the  "historical  sense"  to  grasp,  feel,  taste,  and  love,  what  finds  us  fundamentally prejudiced and almost hostile, is precisely the perfection and ultimate maturity in every culture and art, the essentially noble in works and men, their moment of smooth sea and halcyon  self-sufficiency,  the  goldenness  and  coldness  which  all  things  show  that  have perfected  themselves.  Perhaps  our  great  virtue  of  the  historical  sense  is  in  necessary contrast to GOOD taste, at least to the very bad taste; and we can only evoke in ourselves imperfectly, hesitatingly, and with compulsion the small, short, and happy godsends and glorifications of human life as they shine here and there: those moments and marvelous experiences when a great power has voluntarily come to a halt before the boundless and infinite,--when  a  super-abundance  of  refined  delight  has  been  enjoyed  by  a  sudden checking and petrifying, by standing firmly and planting oneself fixedly on still trembling ground.  PROPORTIONATENESS  is  strange  to  us,  let  us  confess  it  to  ourselves;  our itching  is  really  the  itching  for  the  infinite,  the  immeasurable.  Like  the  rider  on  his forward panting horse, we let the reins fall before the infinite, we modern men, we semi- barbarians--and are only in OUR highest bliss when we--ARE IN MOST DANGER.

225. Whether it be hedonism, pessimism, utilitarianism, or eudaemonism, all those modes of thinking which measure the worth of things according to PLEASURE and PAIN, that is, according to accompanying circumstances and secondary considerations, are plausible modes of thought and naivetes, which every one conscious of CREATIVE powers and an artist's  conscience  will  look  down  upon  with  scorn,  though  not  without  sympathy. Sympathy  for  you!--to  be  sure,  that  is  not  sympathy  as  you  understand  it:  it  is  not sympathy  for  social  "distress,"  for  "society"  with  its  sick  and  misfortuned,  for  the hereditarily  vicious  and  defective  who  lie  on  the  ground  around  us;  still  less  is  it sympathy for the grumbling, vexed, revolutionary slave-classes who strive after power-- they call it "freedom." OUR sympathy is a loftier and further-sighted sympathy:--we see how MAN dwarfs himself, how YOU dwarf him! and there are moments when we view YOUR sympathy with an indescribable anguish, when we resist it,--when we regard your seriousness as more dangerous than any kind of levity. You want, if possible--and there is not a more foolish "if possible" --TO DO AWAY WITH SUFFERING; and we?--it really seems  that  WE  would  rather  have  it  increased  and  made  worse  than  it  has  ever  been! Well-being,  as  you  understand  it--is  certainly  not  a  goal;  it  seems  to  us  an  END;  a condition   which   at   once   renders   man   ludicrous   and   contemptible--and   makes   his destruction DESIRABLE! The discipline of suffering, of GREAT suffering--know ye not that it is only THIS discipline that has produced all the elevations of humanity hitherto? The tension of soul in misfortune which communicates to it its energy, its shuddering in view of rack and ruin, its inventiveness and bravery in undergoing, enduring, interpreting, and  exploiting  misfortune,  and  whatever  depth,  mystery,  disguise,  spirit,  artifice,  or greatness has been bestowed upon the soul--has it not been bestowed through suffering,  through  the  discipline  of  great  suffering?  In  man  CREATURE  and  CREATOR  are united: in man there is not only matter, shred, excess, clay, mire, folly, chaos; but there is also the creator, the sculptor, the hardness of the hammer, the divinity of the spectator, and the seventh day--do ye understand this contrast? And that YOUR sympathy for the "creature in man" applies to that which has to be fashioned, bruised, forged, stretched, roasted, annealed, refined--to that which must necessarily SUFFER, and IS MEANT to suffer? And our sympathy--do ye not understand what our REVERSE sympathy applies to, when it resists your sympathy as the worst of all pampering and enervation?--So it is sympathy AGAINST sympathy!--But to repeat it once more, there are higher problems than  the  problems  of  pleasure  and  pain  and  sympathy;  and  all  systems  of  philosophy which deal only with these are naivetes.

226. WE IMMORALISTS.--This world with which WE are concerned, in which we have to fear and love, this almost invisible, inaudible world of delicate command and delicate obedience, a world of "almost" in every respect, captious, insidious, sharp, and tender-- yes, it is well protected from clumsy spectators and familiar curiosity! We are woven into a strong net and garment of duties, and CANNOT disengage ourselves--precisely here, we are "men of duty," even we! Occasionally, it is true, we dance in our "chains" and betwixt our "swords"; it is none the less true that more often we gnash our teeth under the circumstances, and are impatient at the secret hardship of our lot. But do what we will, fools  and  appearances  say  of  us:  "These  are  men  WITHOUT  duty,"--  we  have  always fools and appearances against us!

227.  Honesty,  granting  that  it  is  the  virtue  of  which  we  cannot  rid  ourselves,  we  free spirits--well,  we  will  labour  at  it  with  all  our  perversity  and  love,  and  not  tire  of "perfecting"  ourselves  in  OUR  virtue,  which  alone  remains:  may  its  glance  some  day overspread  like  a  gilded,  blue,  mocking  twilight  this  aging  civilization  with  its  dull gloomy seriousness! And if, nevertheless, our honesty should one day grow weary, and sigh, and stretch its limbs, and find us too hard, and would fain have it pleasanter, easier, and gentler, like an agreeable vice, let us remain HARD, we latest Stoics, and let us send to its help whatever devilry we have in us:--our disgust at the clumsy and undefined, our "NITIMUR   IN   VETITUM,"   our   love   of   adventure,   our   sharpened   and   fastidious curiosity, our most subtle, disguised, intellectual Will to Power and universal conquest, which rambles and roves avidiously around all the realms of the future--let us go with all our "devils" to the help of our "God"! It is probable that people will misunderstand and mistake us on that account: what does it matter! They will say: "Their 'honesty'--that is their devilry, and nothing else!" What does it matter! And even if they were right--have not all Gods hitherto been such sanctified, re-baptized devils? And after all, what do we know of ourselves?  And what the spirit that leads us wants TO BE CALLED?  (It is a question of names.) And how many spirits we harbour? Our honesty, we free spirits--let us be careful lest it become our vanity, our ornament and ostentation, our limitation, our stupidity! Every virtue inclines to stupidity, every stupidity to virtue; "stupid to the point of sanctity," they say in Russia,-- let us be careful lest out of pure honesty we eventually become saints and bores! Is not life a hundred times too short for us-- to bore ourselves? One would have to believe in eternal life in order to . . .

228.  I  hope  to  be  forgiven  for  discovering  that  all  moral  philosophy  hitherto  has  been tedious and has belonged to the soporific appliances--and  that  "virtue," in  my opinion, has been MORE injured by the TEDIOUSNESS of its advocates than by anything else; at the  same  time,  however,  I  would  not  wish  to  overlook  their  general  usefulness.  It  is desirable that as few people as possible should reflect upon morals, and consequently it is very  desirable  that  morals  should  not  some  day  become  interesting!  But  let  us  not  be afraid! Things still remain today as they have always been: I see no one in Europe who has (or DISCLOSES) an idea of the fact that philosophizing concerning morals might be conducted in a dangerous, captious, and ensnaring manner--that CALAMITY might be involved therein. Observe, for example, the indefatigable, inevitable English utilitarians: how  ponderously  and  respectably  they  stalk  on,  stalk  along  (a  Homeric  metaphor expresses  it  better)  in  the  footsteps  of  Bentham,  just  as  he  had  already  stalked  in  the footsteps of the respectable Helvetius! (no, he was not a dangerous man, Helvetius, CE SENATEUR  POCOCURANTE,  to  use  an  expression  of  Galiani).  No  new  thought, nothing of the nature of a finer turning or better expression of an old thought, not even a proper  history  of  what  has  been  previously  thought  on  the  subject:  an  IMPOSSIBLE literature, taking it all in all, unless one knows how to leaven it with some mischief. In effect,  the  old  English  vice  called  CANT,  which  is  MORAL  TARTUFFISM,  has insinuated itself also into these moralists (whom one must certainly read with an eye to their motives if one MUST read them), concealed this time under the new form of the scientific spirit; moreover, there is not absent from them a secret struggle with the pangs of  conscience,  from  which  a  race  of  former  Puritans  must  naturally  suffer,  in  all  their scientific tinkering with morals. (Is not a moralist the opposite of a Puritan? That is to say,  as  a  thinker  who  regards  morality  as  questionable,  as  worthy  of  interrogation,  in short,  as  a  problem?  Is  moralizing  not-immoral?)  In  the  end,  they  all  want  English morality to be recognized as authoritative, inasmuch as mankind, or the "general utility," or "the happiness of the greatest number,"--no! the happiness of ENGLAND, will be best served thereby. They would like, by all means, to convince themselves that the striving after  English  happiness,  I  mean  after  COMFORT  and  FASHION  (and  in  the  highest instance, a seat in Parliament), is at the same time the true path of virtue; in fact, that in so far as there has been virtue in the world hitherto, it has just consisted in such striving. Not  one  of  those  ponderous,  conscience-stricken  herding-animals  (who  undertake  to advocate  the  cause  of  egoism  as  conducive  to  the  general  welfare)  wants  to  have  any knowledge or inkling of the facts that the "general welfare" is no ideal, no goal, no notion that can be at all grasped, but is only a nostrum,--that what is fair to one MAY NOT at all be  fair  to  another,  that  the  requirement  of  one  morality  for  all  is  really  a  detriment  to higher men, in short, that there is a DISTINCTION OF RANK between man and man, and   consequently   between   morality   and   morality.   They   are   an   unassuming   and fundamentally  mediocre  species  of  men,  these  utilitarian  Englishmen,  and,  as  already remarked, in so far as they are tedious, one cannot think highly enough of their utility. One ought even to ENCOURAGE them, as has been partially attempted in the following rhymes:-–

Hail, ye worthies, barrow-wheeling,

"Longer--better," aye revealing,

Stiffer aye in head and knee;

Unenraptured, never jesting,     Mediocre everlasting,

SANS GENIE ET SANS ESPRIT!

229.  In  these  later  ages,  which  may  be  proud  of  their  humanity,  there  still  remains  so much fear, so much SUPERSTITION of the fear, of the "cruel wild beast," the mastering of which constitutes the very pride of these humaner ages--that even obvious truths, as if by  the  agreement  of  centuries,  have  long  remained  unuttered,  because  they  have  the appearance  of  helping  the  finally  slain  wild  beast  back  to  life  again.  I  perhaps  risk something when I allow such a truth to escape; let others capture it again and give it so much  "milk  of  pious  sentiment"  [FOOTNOTE:  An  expression  from  Schiller's  William Tell,  Act  IV,  Scene  3.]  to  drink,  that  it  will  lie  down  quiet  and  forgotten,  in  its  old corner.--One ought to learn anew about cruelty, and open one's eyes; one ought at last to learn impatience,  in order  that  such immodest gross  errors--as, for  instance,  have  been fostered  by  ancient  and  modern  philosophers  with  regard  to  tragedy--may  no  longer wander about virtuously and boldly. Almost everything that we call "higher culture" is based upon the spiritualising and intensifying of CRUELTY--this is my thesis; the "wild beast" has not been slain at all, it lives, it flourishes, it has only been-- transfigured. That which constitutes the painful delight of tragedy is cruelty; that which operates agreeably in  so-called  tragic  sympathy,  and  at  the  basis  even  of  everything  sublime,  up  to  the highest  and  most  delicate  thrills  of  metaphysics,  obtains  its  sweetness  solely  from  the intermingled ingredient of cruelty. What the Roman enjoys in the arena, the Christian in the ecstasies of the cross, the Spaniard at the sight of the faggot and stake, or of the bull- fight, the present-day Japanese who presses his way to the tragedy, the workman of the Parisian suburbs who has a homesickness for bloody revolutions, the Wagnerienne who, with unhinged will, "undergoes" the performance of "Tristan and Isolde"--what all these enjoy,  and  strive  with  mysterious  ardour  to  drink  in,  is  the  philtre  of  the  great  Circe "cruelty."  Here,  to  be  sure,  we  must  put  aside  entirely  the  blundering  psychology  of former times, which could only teach with regard to cruelty that it originated at the sight of  the  suffering  of  OTHERS:  there  is  an  abundant,  super-abundant  enjoyment  even  in one's  own  suffering,  in  causing  one's  own  suffering--and  wherever  man  has  allowed himself to be persuaded to self-denial in the RELIGIOUS sense, or to self-mutilation, as among  the  Phoenicians  and  ascetics, or in general, to desensualisation, decarnalisation, and  contrition,  to  Puritanical  repentance-spasms,  to  vivisection  of  conscience  and  to Pascal-  like  SACRIFIZIA  DELL'  INTELLETO,  he  is  secretly  allured  and  impelled forwards  by  his  cruelty,  by  the  dangerous  thrill  of  cruelty  TOWARDS  HIMSELF.-- Finally,  let  us  consider  that  even  the  seeker  of  knowledge  operates  as  an  artist  and glorifier  of  cruelty,  in  that  he  compels  his  spirit  to  perceive  AGAINST  its  own inclination,  and  often  enough  against  the  wishes  of  his  heart:--he  forces  it  to  say  Nay, where he would like to affirm, love, and adore; indeed, every instance of taking a thing profoundly and fundamentally, is a violation, an intentional injuring of the fundamental  will of the spirit, which instinctively aims at appearance and superficiality,--even in every desire for knowledge there is a drop of cruelty.

230. Perhaps what I have said here about a "fundamental will of the spirit" may not be understood  without  further  details;  I  may  be  allowed  a  word  of  explanation.--That imperious something which is popularly called "the spirit," wishes to be master internally and externally, and to feel itself