History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

play of the cognitive activities (that is, for an easy combination of the

manifold into unity) the beautiful object is purposive for us, for our

function of apprehension; it is--here we obtain a determination of the

judgment of taste from the standpoint of relation--

_purposive without a

definite purpose_. We know perfectly well that a landscape which attracts

us has not been specially arranged for the purpose of delighting us, and we

do not wish to find in a work of art anything of an intention to please.

An object is perfect when it is purposive for itself (corresponds to its

concept); useful when it is purposive for our desire (corresponds to a

practical intention of man); beautiful when the arrangement of its parts

is purposive for the relation between the fancy and understanding of

the beholder (corresponds in an unusual degree to the conditions of our

apprehension). Perfection is internal (real, objective) purposiveness, and

utility is external purposiveness, both for a definite purpose; beauty,

on the other hand, is purposiveness without a purpose, formal, subjective

purposiveness. The beautiful pleases by its mere form.

The satisfaction in

the perfect is of a conceptual or intellectual kind, the satisfaction in

the beautiful, emotional or aesthetic in character.

The combination of these four determinations yields an exhaustive

definition of the beautiful: The beautiful is that which universally and

necessarily arouses disinterested satisfaction by its mere form

(purposiveness without the representation of a purpose).

Since the pleasurableness of the beautiful rests on the fact that

it establishes a pleasing harmony between the imagination and the

understanding, hence between sensuous and intellectual apprehension, the

aesthetic attitude is possible only in sensuous-rational beings. The

agreeable exists for the animal as well, and the good is an object of

approval for pure spirits; but the beautiful exists for humanity alone.

Kant succeeded in giving very delicate and felicitous verbal expression

to these distinctions: the agreeable gratifies _(vergnügt)_ and excites

inclination _(Neigung)_; the good is approved _(gebilligt)_ and arouses

respect _(Achtung)_; the beautiful "pleases" _(gefällt)_

and finds "favor"

_(Gunst)_.

In the progress of the investigation the principle that beauty depends on

the form alone, and that the concept, the purpose, the nature of the

object is not taken into account at all in aesthetic judgment, experiences

limitation. In its full strictness this applies only to a definite and, in

fact, a subordinate division of the beautiful, which Kant marks off under

the name of pure or _free_ beauty. With this he contrasts _adherent_

beauty, as that which presupposes a generic concept to which its form must

correspond and which it must adequately present. Too much a purist not

to mark the coming in of an intellectual pleasure as a beclouding of the

"purity" of the aesthetic satisfaction, he is still just enough to admit

the higher worth of adherent beauty. For almost the whole of artificial

beauty and a considerable part of natural beauty belong to this latter

division, which we to-day term ideal and characteristic beauty. Examples of

free or purely formal beauty are tapestry patterns, arabesques, fountains,

flowers, and landscapes, the pleasurableness of which rests simply on the

proportion of their form and relations, and not upon their conformity to a

presupposed significance and determination of the thing.

A building, on the

contrary--a dwelling, a summer-house, a temple--is considered beautiful

only when we perceive in it not merely harmonious relations of the parts

one to another, but also an agreement between the form and the purpose or

generic concept: a church must not look like a chalet.

Here the external

form is compared with an inner nature, and harmony is required between form

and content. Adherent beauty is significant and expressive beauty, which,

although the satisfaction in it is not "purely"

aesthetic, nevertheless

stands higher than pure beauty, because it gives to the understanding also

something to think, and hence busies the whole spirit.

The analytical investigations concerning the nature of the beautiful

receive a valuable supplement in the classical definition of genius. Kant

gives two definitions of productive talent, one formal and one genetic.

Natural beauty is a beautiful thing; artificial beauty, a beautiful

representation of a thing. The gift of agreeably presenting a thing which

in itself, perhaps, is ugly, is called taste. To judge of the beautiful

it is sufficient to possess taste, but for its production there is still

another talent needed, spirit or genius. For an art product can fulfill

the demands of taste and yet not aesthetically satisfy; while formally

faultless, it may be spiritless.

While beautiful nature looks as though it were art (as though it were

calculated for our enjoyment), beautiful art should resemble nature, must

not appear to be intentional though, no doubt, it is so, must show a

careful but not an overnice adherence to rules (_i.e._, not one which

fetters the powers of the artist). This is the case when the artist bears

the rule in himself, that is, when he is gifted. Genius is the

innate disposition (through) which (nature) gives rules to art; its

characteristics are originality, exemplariness, and unreflectiveness. It

does not produce according to definite rules which can be learned, but

it is a law in itself, it is original. It creates instinctively without

consciousness of the rule, and cannot describe how it produces its results.

It creates typical works which impel others to follow, not to imitate. It

is only in art that there are geniuses, _i.e._, spirits who produce that

which absolutely cannot be learned, while the great men of science differ

only in degree, not in kind, from their imitators and pupils, and that

which they discover can be learned by rule.

This establishes the criteria by which genius may be recognized. If we ask

by what psychological factors it is produced the answer is as follows:

Genius presupposes a certain favorable relation between imagination and

reason. Genius is the faculty of aesthetic Ideas, but an aesthetic Idea is

a representation of the imagination which animates the mind, which adds to

a concept of the understanding much of ineffable thought, much that belongs

to the concept but which cannot be comprehended in a definite concept. With

the aid of this idea Kant solves the antinomy of the aesthetic judgment.

The thesis is: The judgment of taste is not based upon concepts; for

otherwise it would admit of controversy (would be determinable by proofs).

The antithesis is: It is based upon concepts; for otherwise we could not

contend about it (endeavor to obtain assent). The two principles are

reconcilable, for "concept" is understood differently in the two cases.

That which the thesis rightly seeks to exclude from the judgment of beauty

is the determinate concept of the understanding; that which the antithesis

with equal justice pronounces indispensable is the indeterminate concept,

the aesthetic Idea.

The freest play is afforded the imagination by poetry, the highest of

all arts, which, with rhetoric ("insidious," on account of its earnest

intention to deceive), forms the group termed arts of speech. To the class

of formative arts belong architecture, sculpture, and painting as the art

of design. A third group, the art of the beautiful play of sensations,

includes painting as the art of color, and music, which as a "fine" art is

placed immediately after poetry, as an "agreeable" art at the very foot of

the list, and as the play of tone in the vicinity of the entertaining play

of fortune [games of chance] and the witty play of thought. The explanation

of the comic (the ludicrous is based, according to Kant, on a sudden

transformation of strained expectation into nothing) lays great (indeed

exaggerated) weight on the resulting physiological phenomena, the

bodily shock which heightens vital feeling and favors health, and which

accompanies the alternating tension and relaxation of the mind.

Besides free and adherent beauty, there is still a third kind of aesthetic

effect, the Sublime. The beautiful pleases by its bounded form. But also

the boundless and formless can exert aesthetic effect: that which is great

beyond all comparison we judge sublime. Now this magnitude is either

extensive in space and time or intensive greatness of force or power;

accordingly there are two forms of the sublime. That phenomenon which mocks

the power of comprehension possessed by the human imagination or surpasses

every measure of our intuition, as the ocean and the starry heavens, is

mathematically sublime. That which overcomes all conceivable resistance,

as the terrible forces of nature, conflagrations, floods, earthquakes,

hurricanes, thunderstorms, is dynamically sublime or mighty. The former

is relative to the cognitive, the latter to the appetitive faculty. The

beautiful brings the imagination and the understanding into accord; by

the sublime the fancy is brought into a certain favorable relation, not

directly to be termed harmony, with reason. In the one case there arose a

restful, positively pleasurable mood; here a shock is produced, an indirect

and negative pleasure proceeding from pain. Since the sublime exceeds the

functional capability of our sensuous representations and does violence to

the imagination, we first feel small at the sight of the absolutely great,

and incapable of compassing it with our sensuous glance.

The sensibility is

not equal to the impression; this at first seems contrary to purpose and

violent. This humiliating impression, however, is quickly followed by a

reaction, and the vital forces, which were at first checked, are stimulated

to the more lively activity. Moreover, it is the sensuous part of man

which is humbled and the spiritual part that is exalted: the overthrow of

sensibility becomes a triumph for reason. The sight of the sublime, that

is, awakens the _Idea of the unconditioned, of the infinite_. This Idea can

never be adequately presented by an intuition, but can be aroused only

by the inadequacy of all that is sensuous to present it; the infinite is

presented through the impossibility of presenting it. We cannot intuit the

infinite, but we can think it. In comparison with reason (as the faculty of

Ideas, the faculty of thinking the infinite) even the greatest thing that

can be given in the sense-world appears small; reason is the absolutely

great. "That is sublime the mere ability to think which proves a faculty

of the mind surpassing every standard of sense." "That is sublime which

pleases immediately through its opposition to the interest of the senses."

The conflict between phantasy and reason, the insufficiency of the former

for the attainment of the rational Idea, makes us conscious of the

superiority of reason. Just because we feel small as sensuous beings we

feel great as rational beings. The pleasure (related to the moral feeling

of respect and, like this, mingled with a certain pain) which accompanies

this consciousness of inner greatness is explained by the fact that the

imagination, in acknowledging reason superior, places itself in the

appropriate and purposive relation of subordination. It is evident from the

foregoing that the truly sublime is reason, the moral nature of man, his

predisposition and destination, which point beyond the present world.

Schiller declares that "in space the sublime does not dwell," and

Kant says, "Sublimity is contained in none of the things of nature, but

only in our mind, in so far as we are conscious of being superior to nature

within us and without us." Nevertheless, since in this contemplation we fix

our thoughts entirely on the object without reflecting on ourselves, we

transfer the admiration of right due to the reason and its Idea of the

infinite by subreption to the object by which the Idea is occasioned, and

call the object itself sublime, instead of the mood which it wakes in us.

If the sublime marks the point where the aesthetic touches on the boundary

of the moral, the beautiful is also not without some relation to the good.

By showing the agreement of sensibility and reason, which is demanded by

the moral law, realized in aesthetic intuition (as a voluntary yielding of

the imagination to the legitimacy of the understanding), it gives us the

inspiring consciousness that the antithesis is reconcilable, that the

rational can be presented in the sensuous, and so becomes a "symbol of the

good."

%(b) Teleological Judgment.%--Teleological judgment is not knowledge, but

a way of looking at things which comes into play where the causal or

mechanical explanation fails us. This is not the case if the purposiveness

is external, relative to its utility for something else.

The fact that the

sand of the sea-shore furnishes a good soil for the pine neither furthers

nor prevents a causal knowledge of it. Only inner purposiveness, as it

is manifested in the products of organic nature, brings the mechanical

explanation to a halt. Organisms are distinguished above inorganic forms by

the fact that of themselves they are at once cause and effect, that they

are self-productive and this both as a species (the oak springs from the

acorn, and in its turn bears acorns) and as individuals (self-preservation,

growth, and the replacement of dying parts by new ones), and also by the

fact that the reciprocally productive parts are in their form and their

existence all conditioned by the whole. This latter fact, that the whole is

the determining ground for the parts, is perfectly obvious in the products

of human art. For here it is the representation of the whole (the idea of

the work desired) which as the ground precedes the existence and the form

of the parts (of the machine). But where is the subject to construct

organisms according to its representations of ends? We may neither conceive

nature itself as endowed with forces acting in view of ends, nor a

praetermundane intelligence interfering in the course of nature. Either of

these suppositions would be the death of natural philosophy: the hylozoist

endows matter with a property which conflicts with its nature, and the

theist oversteps the boundary of possible experience.

Above all, the

analogy of the products of organic nature with the products of human

technique is destroyed by the fact that machines do not reproduce

themselves and their parts cannot produce one another, while the organism

organizes itself.

For our discursive understanding an interaction between the whole and the

parts is completely incomprehensible. We understand when the parts precede

the whole (mechanically) or the representation of the whole precedes

the parts (teleologically); but to think the whole itself (not the Idea

thereof) as the ground of the parts, which is demanded by organic life,

is impossible for us. It would have been otherwise if an intuitive

understanding had been bestowed upon us. For a being possessing

intellectual intuition the antithesis between possibility and actuality,

between necessity and contingency, between mechanism and teleology, would

disappear along with that between thought and intuition.

For such a being

everything possible (all that it thinks) would be at the same time

actual (present for intuition), and all that appears to us

contingent--intentionally selected from several possibilities and in order

to an end--would be necessary as well; with the whole would be given

the parts corresponding thereto, and consequently natural mechanism

and purposive connection would be identical, while for us, to whom the

intuitive understanding is denied, the two divide. Hence the teleological

view is a mere form of human representation, a subjective principle. We may

not say that a mechanical origin of living beings is impossible, but only

that we are unable to understand it. If we knew how a blade of grass or

a frog sprang from mechanical forces, we would also be in a position to

produce them.

The antinomy of the teleological judgment--thesis: all production of

material things and their forms must be judged to be possible according to

merely mechanical laws; antithesis: some products of material nature cannot

be judged to be possible according to merely mechanical laws, but to judge

them requires the causality of final causes--is insoluble so long as both

propositions are taken for constitutive principles; but it is soluble when

they are taken as regulative principles or standpoints for judgment. For it

is in no wise contradictory, on the one hand, to continue the search for

mechanical causes as far as this is in any way possible, and, on the other,

clearly to recognize that, at last, this will still leave a remainder which

we cannot make intelligible without calling to our aid the concept of ends.

Assuming that it were possible to carry the explanation of life from life,

from ancestral organisms (for the _generatio aequivoca_

is an absurd

theory) so far that the whole organic world should represent one great

family descended from one primitive form as the common mother, even

then the concept of final causes would only be pushed further back, not

eliminated: the origin of the first organization will always resist

mechanical explanation. Besides this mission of putting limits to causal

derivation and of filling the gap in knowledge by a necessary, although

subjective, way of looking at things, the Idea of ends has still another,

the direct promotion of knowledge from efficient causes through the

discovery of new causal problems. Thus, for example, physiology owes the

impulse to the discovery of previously unnoticed mechanical connections

(cf. also p. 382 note) to the question concerning the purpose of organs.

As doctrines mechanism and teleology are irreconcilable and impossible;

as rules or maxims of inquiry they are compatible, and the one as

indispensable as the other.

After the problem of life, which is insoluble by means of the mechanical

explanation, has necessitated the application of the concept of ends, the

teleological principle must, at least by way of experiment, be extended to

the whole of nature. This consideration culminates in the position that

man, as the subject of morality, must be held to be the final aim of the

world, for it is only in regard to a moral being that no further inquiry

can be raised as to the purpose of its existence. It also repeats the

moral argument for the existence of a supreme reason, thus supplementing

physico-theology, which is inadequate to the demonstration of one

absolutely perfect Deity; so that the third _Critique_, like the two

preceding, concludes with the Idea of God as an object of practical faith.

* * * * *

There are three original and pregnant pairs of thoughts which cause Kant's

name to shine in the philosophical sky as a star of the first magnitude:

the demand for a critique of knowledge and the proof of _a priori_ forms

of knowledge; the moral autonomy and the categorical imperative; the

regulative validity of the Ideas of reason and the practical knowledge of

the transcendent world. No philosophical theory, no scientific hypothesis

can henceforth avoid the duty of examining the value and legitimacy of its

conclusions, as to whether they keep within the limits of the competency of

human reason; whether Kant's determination of the origin and the limits of

knowledge may count on continued favor or not, the fundamental critical

idea, that reflection upon the nature and range of our cognitive faculty is

indispensable, retains its validity for all cases and makes an end of all

philosophizing at random.[1] No ethical system will with impunity pass by

the autonomous legislation of reason and the unconditional imperative (the

admonition of conscience translated into conceptual language): the nature

and worth of moral will will be everywhere sought in vain if they are not

recognized where Kant has found them--in the unselfish disposition, in that

maxim which is fitted to become a general law for all rational beings.

The doctrine of the Ideas, finally, reveals to us, beyond the daylight of

phenomenal knowledge, the starlit landscape of another mode of looking at

things,[2] in which satisfaction is afforded for the hitherto unmet wishes

of the heart and demands of the reason.

[Footnote 1: "_Reason_ consists just in this, that we are able to give

account of all our concepts, opinions, and assertions, either on objective

or subjective grounds."]

[Footnote 2: Those who regard all future metaphysics as refuted by the

Critique of Reason are to be referred to the positive side of the Kantian

doctrine of Ideas. Kant admits that the mechanical explanation does not

satisfy reason, and that, besides it, a judgment according to Ideas is

legitimate. When, therefore, the speculation of the constructive school

gives an ideal interpretation of the world, it may be regarded as an

extended application of "regulative principles," which exceeds its

authority only when it professes to be "objective knowledge."]

The effect of the three _Critiques_ upon the public was very varied. The

first great work excited alarm by the sharpness of its negations and its

destruction of dogmatic metaphysics, which to its earliest readers appeared

to be the core of the matter; Kant was for them the universal destroyer.

Then the Science of Knowledge brought into prominence the positive,

boldly conquering side, the investigation of the conditions of empirical

knowledge. In later times the endeavor has been made to do justice to both

sides, but, in opposition to the overbold procedure of the constructive

thinkers, who had fallen into a revived dogmatism, more in the spirit of

caution and resignation. The second great work aroused glowing enthusiasm:

"Kant is no mundane luminary," writes Jean Paul in regard to the _Critique

of Practical Reason_, "but a whole solar system shining at once."

The third, because of its subject and by its purpose of synthetic

reconciliation between fields heretofore sharply separated, gained the

sympathy of our poet-heroes Schiller and Goethe, and awakened in a young,

speculative spirit Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature.

Schelling reclaimed

the intuitive understanding, which Kant had problematically attributed to

the primal spirit, as the property of the philosopher, after Fichte had

drawn attention to the fact that the consciousness of the categorical

imperative, which Kant had not thoroughly investigated, could be nothing

else than intellectual intuition, because in it knowing and doing coincide.

Fichte, however, does not derive the material for his system from the

_Critique of Judgment_, though he also had a high appreciation of it, but

from the two earlier _Critiques_, the fundamental conceptions of which

he--following the hint that practical and theoretical reason are only

different applications of one and the same reason--

brings into the closest

connection. He unites the central idea of the practical philosophy, the

freedom and autonomous legislation of the will, with the leading principle

of the theoretical philosophy, the spontaneity of the understanding, under

the original synthesis of the pure ego, in order to deduce from the

activity of the ego not only the _a priori_ forms of knowledge, but also,

rejecting the thing in itself, t