History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

latter, by the philosophy of mythology and revelation, which goes back to

Aristotle and the Gnostics. In the first period the absolute for Schelling

is creative nature; in the second, the identity of opposites; in the third

it is an antemundane process which advances from the not-yet-present of

the contraries to their overcoming. In neither of these advances is it

Schelling's intention to break with his previous teachings, but in each

case only to add a supplement. That which has hitherto been the whole is

retained as a part. The philosophy of nature takes its place beside the

completed Fichtean transcendental philosophy, with equal rights, though

with a reversed procedure; then the theory of identity assumes a place

above both; finally, a positive (existential) philosophy is added to the

previous negative (rational) philosophy.

%1a. Philosophy of Nature.%

Schelling agrees with Fichte that philosophy is transcendental science,

the doctrine of the conditions of consciousness, and has to answer the

question, What must take place in order that knowledge may arise? They

agree, further, that these conditions of knowledge are necessary acts,

outgoings of an active original ground which is not yet conscious self, but

seeks to become such, and that the material world is the product of these

actions. Nature exists in order that the ego may develop. But while Fichte

correctly understood the purpose of nature, to help intelligence into

being, he failed to recognize the dignity of nature, for he deprived it of

all self-dependence, all life of its own, all generative power, and treated

it merely as a dead tool, as a passive, merely posited non-ego. Nature

is not a board which the original ego nails up before itself in order,

striking against it, to be driven back upon itself, to be compelled to

reflection, and thereby to become theoretical ego; in order, further,

working over the non-ego, and transforming it, to exercise its practical

activity: but it is a ladder on which spirit rises to itself. Spirit

develops out of nature; nature itself has a spiritual element in it; it

is undeveloped, slumbering, unconscious, benumbed intelligence. By

transferring to nature the power of self-position or of being subject,

Schelling exalts the drudge of the Science of Knowledge to the throne.

The threefold division, "infinite original activity--

nature or

object--individual ego or subject," remains as in Fichte, only that the

first member is not termed pure ego, but nature, yet creative nature,

_natura naturans_. Schelling's aim is to show how from the object a subject

arises, from the existent something represented, from the representable a

representer, from nature an ego. He could only hope to solve this problem

if he conceived natural objects--in the highest of which, man, he makes

conscious spirit break forth or nature intuit itself--as themselves the

products of an original subject, of a creative ground striving toward

consciousness. For him also doing is more original than being. It would not

be exact, therefore, to define the difference between Fichte and Schelling

by saying that, with the former, nature proceeds from the ego, and with the

latter the ego, from nature. It is rather true that with them both nature

and spirit are alike the products of a third and higher term, which seeks

to become spirit, and can accomplish this only by positing nature. In the

Science of Knowledge, it is true, this higher ground is conceived as an

ethical, in the Philosophy of Nature as a physical, power, although one

framed for intelligence; in the former, moreover, the _natura naturata_

appears as the position once for all of a non-spiritual, in the latter as

a progressive articulated construction, with gradually increasing

intelligence. In the unconscious products of nature, nature's aim to

reflect upon itself, to become intelligence, fails, in man it succeeds.

Nature is the embryonic life of spirit. Nature and spirit are essentially

identical: "That which is posited _out of_ consciousness is in its essence

the same as that which is posited _in_ consciousness also." Therefore

"the knowable must itself bear the impress of the knower." Nature the

preliminary stage, not the antithesis, of spirit; history, a continuation

of physical becoming; the parallelism between the ideal and the real

development-series--these are ideas from Herder which Schelling introduces

into the transcendental philosophy. The Kantio-Fichtean moralism, with

its sharp contraposition of nature and spirit, is limited in the

_Naturphilosophie_ by Herder's physicism.

"Nature _is a priori_" (everything individual in it is pre-determined by

the whole, by the Idea of a nature in general); hence the forms of nature

can be deduced from the concept of nature. The philosopher creates nature

anew, he constructs it. Speculative physics considers nature as _subject_,

becoming, productivity (not, like empirical science, as object, being,

product), and for this purpose it needs, instead of individualizing

reflection, an intuition directed to the whole. To this productive nature,

as to the absolute ego of Fichte, are ascribed two opposite activities,

one expansive or repulsive, and one attractive, and on these is based the

universal law of _polarity_. The absolute productivity strives toward an

infinite product, which it never attains, because apart from arrest no

product exists. At definite points a check must be given it in order that

something knowable may arise. Thus every product in nature is the result

of a positive, centrifugal, accelerating, universalizing force, and a

negative, limiting, retarding, individualizing one. The endlessness of the

creative activity manifests itself in various ways: in the striving for

development on the part of every product, in the preservation of the genus

amid the disappearance of individuals, in the endlessness of the series of

products. Nature's creative impulse is inexhaustible, it transcends every

product. Qualities are points of arrest in the one universal force of

nature; all nature is a connected development. Because of the opposition in

the nature-ground between the stimulating and the retarding activity, the

law of duality everywhere rules. To these two forces, however, still a

third factor must be added as their copula, which determines the relation

or measure of their connection. This is the source of the threefold

division of the Philosophy of Nature. The magnet with its union of opposite

polar forces is the type of all configuration in nature.

With Fichte's synthetic method and Herder's naturalistic principles

Schelling combines Kantian ideas, especially Kant's dynamism (matter is

a force-product),[1] and his view of the organic (organisms are

self-productive beings, and are regarded by us as ends in themselves,

because of the interaction between their members and the whole). The three

organic functions sensibility, irritability, and reproduction, on the other

hand, Schelling took from Kielmeyer, whose address _On the Relations of

the Organic Forces_, 1793, excited great attention. The concept of life is

dominant in Schelling's theory of nature. The organic is more original than

the inorganic; the latter must be explained from the former; that which is

dead must be considered as a product of departing life.

No less erroneous

than the theory of a magic vital force is the mechanical interpretation,

which looks on life merely as a chemical phenomenon. The dead, mechanical

and chemical, forces are merely the negative conditions of life; to them

there must be added as a positive force a vital stimulus external to the

individual, which continually rekindles the conflict between the opposing

activities on which the vital process depends. Life consists, that is, in

the perpetual prevention of the equilibrium which is the object of the

chemical process. This constant disturbance proceeds from "universal

nature," which, as the common principle of organic and inorganic nature, as

that which determines them for each other, which founds a pre-established

harmony between them, deserves the name of the world-soul. Schelling

thus recognizes a threefold nature: organized, inorganic, and universal

organizing (according to Harms, cosmical) nature, of which the two former

arise from the third and are brought by it into connection and harmony. (As

Schelling here takes an independent middle course between the mechanical

explanation of life and the assumption of a specific vital force, so in

all the burning physical questions of the time he seeks to rise above the

contending parties by means of mediating solutions.

Thus, in the question

of "single or double electricity," he ranges himself neither on the side of

Franklin nor on that of his opponents; in regard to the problem of light,

endeavors to overcome the antithesis between Newton's emanation theory and

the undulation theory of Euler; and, in his chapter on combustion, attacks

the defenders of phlogiston as well as those who deny it).

[Footnote 1: Schelling terms his philosophy of nature dynamic atomism,

since it posits pure intensities as the simple (atoms), from which

qualities are to be explained.]

Schelling's philosophy of nature[1] proposes to itself three chief

problems: the construction of general, indeterminate, homogeneous

matter, with differences in density alone, of determinate, qualitatively

differentiated matter and its phenomena of motion or the dynamical process,

and of the organic process. For each of these departments of nature an

original force in universal nature is assumed--gravity, light, and their

copula, universal life. Gravity--this does not mean that which as the force

of attraction falls within the view of sensation, for it is the union of

attraction and repulsion--is the principle of corporeality, and produces

in the visible world the different conditions of aggregation in solids,

fluids, and gases. Light--this, too, is not to be confounded with actual

light, of which it is the cause--is the principle of the soul (from it

proceeds all intelligence, it is a spiritual potency, the "first subject"

in nature), and produces in the visible world the dynamical processes

magnetism, electricity, and chemism. The higher unity of gravity and

light is the copula or life, the principle of the organic, of animated

corporeality or the processes of growth and reproduction, irritability,

and sensibility.

[Footnote 1: This is contained in the following treatises: _Ideas for a

Philosophy of Nature, 1797; On the World-soul, 1798; First Sketch of a

System of the Philosophy of Nature, 1799; Universal Deduction of the

Dynamical Process or the Categories of Physics_ (in the _Zeitschrift für

spekulative Physik_) 1800. In the above exposition, however, the modified

philosophy of nature of the second period has also been taken into

account.]

General _matter_ or the filling of space, arises from the co-operation of

three forces: the centrifugal, which manifests itself as repulsion (first

dimension), the centripetal, manifested as attraction (second dimension),

and the synthesis of the two, manifested as gravity (third dimension).

These forces are raised by light to a higher potency, and then make their

appearance as the causes of the _dynamical_ process or of the specific

differences of matter. The linear function of magnetism is the condition

of coherence; the surface force of electricity, the basis of the qualities

perceivable by sense; the tri-dimensional force of the chemical process, in

which the two former are united, produces the chemical qualities. Galvanism

forms the transition to living nature, in which through the operation of

the "copula" these three dynamical categories are raised to _organic_

categories. To magnetism as the most general, and hence the lowest force,

corresponds reproduction (the formative impulse, as nutrition, growth, and

production, including the artistic impulse); electricity develops into

irritability or excitability; the higher analogue to the chemical process

as the most individual and highest stage is sensibility or the capacity

of feeling. (Such at least is Schelling's doctrine after Steffens had

convinced him of the higher dignity of that which is individual, whereas

at first he had made sensibility parallel with magnetism, and reproduction

with chemism, because the former two appear most seldom, and the latter

most frequently. Electricity and irritability always maintained their

intermediate position.) With the awakening of feeling nature has attained

its goal--intelligence. As inorganic substances are distinguished only by

relative degrees of repulsion and attraction, so the differentiation of

organisms is conditioned by the relation of the three vital functions: in

the lower forms reproduction predominates, then irritability gradually

increases, while in the highest forms both of these are subordinated to

sensibility. All species, however, are connected by a common life, all the

stages are but arrests of the same fundamental force.

This accentuation

of the unity of nature, which establishes a certain kinship between

Schelling's philosophy of nature and Darwinism, was a great idea, which

deserves the thanks of posterity in spite of such defects as its often

sportive, often heedlessly bold reasoning in details.

The parallelism of the potencies of nature, as we have developed it by

leaving out of account the numerous differences between the various

expositions of the _Naturphilosophie_, may be shown by a table:

I. UNIVERSAL NATURE. II. INORGANIC NATURE III.

ORGANIC NATURE.

(ORGANIZING)

3. Copula 3.

Organization

or Life. |

___^___ /Chemical \ G |

/Sensi- Man.

/ \ |Process (3d| a |

|bility. __^__

2. Light 2._Dynamical_|Dimen- | l | |

/ \

(Soul). _Process_. < sion) | v |

|Irritabi- Male

b. At- \ (Determi- |Electri- | a

|_|lity. (=Light)

traction.| nate |city (2d Di->n

|Animal.

>1. Gra- matter.) | mension.) | i |

| vity 1. Indeter- |Magnetism | s

|Repro- Female

a. Re- | (Body) minate |(1st Di- | m

|duction (-Gravity)

pulsion / _matter_. \ mension.) / \

Plant.

%1b. Transcendental Philosophy.%

The philosophy of nature explained the products of nature teleologically,

deduced them from the concept or the mission of nature, by ignoring the

mechanical origin of physical phenomena and inquiring into the significance

of each stage in nature in view of this ideal meaning of the whole. It asks

what is the outcome of the chemical process for the whole of nature, what

is given by electricity, by magnetism, etc.--what part of the general aim

of nature is attained, is realized through this or that group of phenomena.

The philosophy of spirit given in the _System of Transcendental Idealism_,

1800, finds itself confronted by corresponding questions concerning the

phenomena of intelligence, of morals, and of art. Here again Schelling does

not trace out the mechanics of the soul-life, but is interested only in the

meaning, in the teleological significance of the psychical functions.

His aim is a constructive psychology in the Fichtean sense, a history of

consciousness, and the execution of his design as well closely follows the

example of the _Wissenschaftslehre_.

Since truth is the agreement of thought and its object, every cognition

necessarily implies the coming together of a subjective and an objective

factor. The problem of this coming together may be treated in two ways.

With the philosophy of nature we may start from the object and observe how

intelligence is added to nature. The transcendental philosophy takes the

opposite course, it takes its position with the subject, and asks, How

is there added to intelligence an object corresponding to it? The

transcendental philosopher has need of intellectual intuition in order to

recognize the original object-positing actions of the ego, which remain

concealed from common consciousness, sunk in the outcome of these acts. The

_theoretical_ part of the system explains the representation of objective

reality (the feeling connected with certain representations that we are

compelled to have them), from pure self-consciousness, whose opposing

moments, a real and an ideal force, limit each other by degrees,--and

follows the development of spirit in three periods ("epochs"). The first

of these extends from sensation, in which the ego finds itself limited, to

productive intuition, in which a thing in itself is posited over against

the ego and the phenomenon between the two; the second, from this point to

reflection (feeling of self, outer and inner intuition together with space

and time, the categories of relation as the original categories); the

third, finally, through judgment, wherein intuition and concept are

separated as well as united, up to the absolute act of will. Willing is

the continuation and completion of intuition;[1]

intuition was unconscious

production, willing is conscious production. It is only through action that

the world becomes objective for us, only through interaction with other

active intelligences that the ego attains to the consciousness of a real

external world, and to the consciousness of its freedom.

The _practical_

part follows the will from impulse (the feeling of contradiction between

the ideal and the object) through the division into moral law and resistant

natural impulse up to arbitrary will. Observations on legal order, on the

state, and on history are added as "supplements." The law of right, by

which unlawful action is directed against itself, is not a moral, but a

natural order, which operates with blind necessity. The state, like law, is

a product of the genus, and not of individuals. The ideal of a cosmopolitan

legal condition is the goal of _history_, in which caprice and conformity

to law are one, in so far as the conscious free action of individuals

subserves an unconscious end prescribed by the world-spirit. History is the

never completed revelation of the absolute (of the unity of the conscious

and the unconscious) through human freedom. We are co-authors in the

historical world-drama, and invent our own parts. Not until the third (the

religious) period, in which he reveals himself as

"providence," will God

_be_; in the past (the tragical) period, in which the divine power was felt

as "fate," and in the present (the mechanical) period, in which he appears

as the "plan of nature," God is not, but is only _becoming_.

[Footnote 1: With this transformation of the antithesis between knowledge

and volition into a mere difference in degree, Schelling sinks back to the

standpoint of Leibnitz. In all the idealistic thinkers who start from Kant

we find the endeavor to overcome the Critical dualism of understanding and

will, as also that between intellect and sensibility.

Schiller brings the

contrary impulses of the ego into ultimate harmonious union in artistic

activity. Fichte traces them back to a common ground; Schelling combines

both these methods by extolling art as a restoration of the original

identity. Hegel reduces volition to thought, Schopenhauer makes intellect

proceed from will.]

An interesting supplement to the Fichtean philosophy is furnished by the

third, the _aesthetic_, part of the transcendental idealism, which makes

use of Kant's theory of the beautiful in a way similar to that in which the

philosophy of nature had availed itself of his theory of the organic.

Art is the higher third in which the opposition between theoretical and

practical action, the antithesis of subject and object, is removed; in

which cognition and action, conscious and unconscious activity, freedom and

necessity, the impulse of genius and reflective deliberation are united.

The beautiful, as the manifestation of the infinite in the finite, shows

the problem of philosophy, the identity of the real and the ideal, solved

in sensuous appearance. Art is the true organon and warrant of philosophy;

she opens up to philosophy the holy of holies, is for philosophy the

supreme thing, the revelation of all mysteries. Poesy and philosophy (the

aesthetic intuition of the artist and the intellectual intuition of

the thinker) are most intimately related; they were united in the old

mythology--why should not this repeat itself in the future?

%2. System of Identity.%

The assertion which had already been made in the first period that "nature

and spirit are fundamentally the same," is intensified in the second into

the proposition, "The ground of nature and spirit, the absolute, is the

identity of the real and the ideal," and in this form is elevated into

a principle. As the absolute is no longer employed as a mere ground of

explanation, but is itself made the object of philosophy, the doctrine of

identity is added to the two co-ordinate disciplines, the philosophy of

nature and the philosophy of spirit, as a higher third, which serves as a

basis for them, and in Schelling's exposition of which several phases must

be distinguished.[1]

[Footnote 1: The philosophy of identity is given in the following

treatises: _Exposition of my System of Philosophy, 1801; Further

Expositions of the System of Philosophy, 1802; Bruno, or on the Divine and

Natural Principle of Things, 1803; Lectures on the Method of Academical

Study, 1803; Aphorisms by way of Introduction to the Philosophy of Nature,

Aphorisms on the Philosophy of Nature_ (both in the _Jahrbücher für

Medizin), 1806_. Besides these the following also bear on this doctrine:

the additions to the second edition of the _Ideas_, 1803, and the

_Exposition_, against Fichte, 1806.]

Following Spinoza, whom he at first imitated even in the geometrical method

of proof, Schelling teaches that there are two kinds of knowledge, the

philosophical knowledge of the reason and the confused knowledge of

the imagination, and, as objects of these, two forms of existence, the

infinite, undivided existence of the absolute, and the finite existence of

individual things, split up into multiplicity and becoming. The manifold

and self-developing things of the phenomenal world owe their existence

to isolating thought alone; they possess as such no true reality, and

speculation proves them void. While things appear particular to inadequate

representation, the philosopher views them _sub specie aeterni_, in their

_per se_, in their totality, in the identity, as Ideas.

To construe things

is to present them as they are in God. But in God all things are one;

in the absolute all is absolute, eternal, infinitude itself. (Accord-to

Hegel's parody, the absolute is the night, in which all cows are black.)

The world-ground appears as nature and spirit; yet in itself it is neither

the one nor the other, but the unity of both which is raised above all

contrariety, the indifference of objective and subjective. Although amid

the finitude of the things of the world the self-identity of the absolute

breaks up into a plurality of self-developing individual existences, yet