History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

the pure intuitions and the categories, and the Critique of Judgment, he

rejects, and with full consciousness, just those parts of Kant on which the

Fichtean school had built further. Finally, Herbart's method of thought,

his impersonality, the at times anxious caution of his inquiry, and the

neatness of his conceptions, are somewhat akin to Kant's, only that he

lacked the gift of combination to a much greater degree than his great

predecessor on the Königsberg rostrum. His remarkable acuteness is busier

in loosening than in binding; it is more happy in the discovery of

contradictions than in their resolution. Therefore he does not belong to

the kings who have decided the fate of philosophy for long periods of time;

he stands to one side, though it is true he is the most important figure

among these who occupy such a position.

The first to give his adherence to Herbart in essential positions, and so

to furnish occasion for the formation of an Herbartian school, was Drobisch

(born 1802), in two critiques which appeared in 1828 and 1830. Besides

Drobisch, from whom we have valuable discussions of Logic (1836, 5th ed.,

1887) and Empirical Psychology (1842), and an interesting essay on _Moral

Statistics and the Freedom of the Will_ (1867), L.

Strümpell (born 1812;

_The Principal Points in Herbart's Metaphysics Critically Examined_, 1840),

is a professor in Leipsic. The organ of the school, the _Zeitschrift

für exakte Philosophie_, now edited by Flügel (the first volume, 1860,

contained a survey of the literature of the school), was at first issued

by T. Ziller, the pedagogical thinker, and Allihn. The _Zeitschrift für

Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft_, from 1859, edited by M. Lazarus

(born 1824; _The Life of the Soul_, 3 vols., 1856

_seq_., 3d ed., 1883

_seq_.) and H. Steinthal (born 1823; _The Origin of Language_, 4th ed.,

1888; _Sketch of the Science of Language_, part i. 2d ed., 1881; _General

Ethics_, 1885) of Berlin, also belongs to the Herbartian movement.

Distinguished service has been done in psychology by Nahlowsky (_The Life

of Feeling_, 1862, 2d. ed., 1884), Theodor Waitz in Marburg (1821-84;

_Foundation of Psychology_, 1846; _Text-book of Psychology_, 1849), and

Volkmann in Prague (1822-77; _Text-book of Psychology_, 3d. ed., by

Cornelius, 1884 and 1885); while Friedrich Exner (died 1853) was formerly

much spoken of as an opponent of the Hegelian psychology (1843-44). Robert

Zimmermann in Vienna (born 1824) represents an extreme formalistic tendency

in aesthetics (_History of Aesthetics_, 1858; _General Esthetics as Science

of Form_, 1865; further, a series of thorough essays on subjects in the

history of philosophy). Among historians of philosophy Thilo has given a

rather one-sided representation of the Herbartian standpoint. The school's

philosophers of religion have been mentioned above (p.

532). Beneke, whom

we have joined with Fries on account of his anthropological standpoint,

stands about midway between Herbart and Schopenhauer. He shares in the

former's interest in psychology, in the latter's foundation of metaphysical

knowledge on inner experience, and in the dislike felt by both for Hegel;

while, on the other hand, he differs from Herbart in his empirical method,

and from Schopenhauer in the priority ascribed to representation over

effort.

%3. Pessimism: Schopenhauer.%

Schopenhauer is in all respects the antipodes of Herbart. If in Herbart

philosophy breaks up into a number of distinct special inquiries,

Schopenhauer has but one fundamental thought to communicate, in the

carrying out of which, as he is convinced, each part implies the whole and

is implied by the whole. The former operates with sober concepts where the

latter follows the lead of gifted intuition. The one is cool, thorough,

cautious, methodical to the point of pedantry; the other is passionate,

ingenious, unmethodical to the point of capricious dilettantism. In the one

case, philosophy is as far as possible exact science, in which the person

of the thinker entirely retires behind the substance of the inquiry; in the

other, philosophy consists in a sum of artistic conceptions, which derive

their content and value chiefly from the individuality of the author. The

history of philosophy has no other system to show which to the same

degree expresses and reflects the personality of the philosopher as

Schopenhauer's. This personality, notwithstanding its limitations and its

whims, was important enough to give interest to Schopenhauer's views, even

apart from the relative truth which they contain.

Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860) was the son of a merchant in Dantzic and

his wife Johanna, _née_ Trosiener, who subsequently became known as a

novelist. His early training was gained from foreign travel, but after the

death of his father he exchanged the mercantile career, which he had begun

at his father's request, for that of a scholar, studying under G.E. Schulze

in Göttingen, and under Fichte at Berlin. In 1813 he gained his doctor's

degree in Jena with a dissertation _On the Fourfold Root of the Principle

of Sufficient Reason_. Then he moved from Weimar, the residence of his

mother, where he had associated considerably with Goethe and had been

introduced to Indian philosophy by Fr. Mayer, to Dresden (1814-18). In the

latter place he wrote the essay _On Sight and Colors_

(1816; subsequently

published by the author in Latin), and his chief work, _The World as Will

and Idea_ (1819; new edition, with a second volume, 1844). After the

completion of the latter he began his first Italian journey, while his

second tour fell in the interval between his two quite unsuccessful

attempts (in Berlin 1820 and 1825) to propagate his philosophy from the

professor's desk. From 1831 until his death he lived in learned retirement

in Frankfort-on-the-Main. Here he composed the opuscule _On Will in

Nature_, 1836, the prize treatises _On the Freedom of the Human Will_ and

_On the Foundation of Ethics_ (together, _The Two Fundamental Problems

of Ethics_, 1841), and the collection of minor treatises _Parerga and

Paralipomena_, 2 vols., 1851 (including an essay "On Religion").

J. Frauenstädt has published a considerable amount of posthumous material

(among other things the translation, _B. Gracians Handorakel der

Weltklugheit_); the _Collected Works_ (6 vols., 1873-74, 2d ed., 1877, with

a biographical notice); _Lichtstrahlen aus Schopenhauers Werken_, 1861, 5th

ed. 1885; and a _Schopenhauer Lexicon_, 2 vols., 1871.[1]

[Footnote 1: From the remaining Schopenhauer literature (F. Laban has

published a chronological survey of it, 1880) we may call attention to the

critiques of the first edition of the chief work by Herbart and Beneke, and

that of the second edition by Fortlage (_Jenaische Litteratur Zeitung_,

1845, Nos. 146-151); J.E. Erdmann _Herbart und Schopenhauer, eine Antithese

(Zeitschrift für Philosophie_, 1851); Wilh. Gwinner, _Schopenhauers

Leben_, 1878 (the second edition of _Schopenhauer aus persönlichem

Umgang dargestellt_, 1862); Fr. Nietzsche, _Schopenhauer als Erzieher

(Unzeitgemässe Betrachtungen, Stück iii_., 1874); O.

Busch, _A.

Schopenhauer_, 2d. ed., 1878; K. Peters, _Schopenhauer als Philosoph und

Schriftsteller_, 1880; R. Koeber, _Die Philosophie A.

Schopenhauers_, 1888.

[The English reader may be referred to Haldane and Kemp's translation of

_The World as Will and Idea_, 3 vols., 1883-86; the translation of _The

Fourfold Root_ and the _Will in Nature_ in Bohn's Philosophical Library,

1889; Saunders's translations from the _Parerga and Paralipomena_, 1889

_seq_.; Helen Zimmern's _Arthur Schopenhauer, his Life and his Philosophy_,

1876; W. Wallace's _Schopenhauer_, Great Writers Series, 1890 (with a

bibliography by Anderson, including references to numerous magazine

articles, etc.); Sully's _Pessimism_, 2d ed., 1882, chap. iv.; and Royce's

_Spirit of Modern Philosophy_, chap, viii., 1892.--TR.]]

In regard to subjective idealism Schopenhauer confesses himself a

thoroughgoing Kantian. That sensations are merely states in us has long

been known; Kant opened the eyes of the world to the fact that the forms of

knowledge are also the property of the subject. I know things only as they

appear to me, as I represent them in virtue of the constitution of my

intellect; the world is my idea. The Kantian theory, however, is capable of

simplification, the various forms of cognition may be reduced to a single

one, to the category of causality or principle of sufficient reason--which

was preferred by Kant himself--as the general expression of the regular

connection of our representations. This principle, in correspondence with

the several classes of objects, or rather of representations--viz., pure

(merely formal) intuitions, empirical (complete) intuitions, acts of will,

abstract concepts--has four forms: it is the _principium rationis essendi,

rationis fiendi, rationis agendi, rationis cognoscendi_.

The _ratio

essendi_ is the law which regulates the coexistence of the parts of space

and the succession of the divisions of time. The _ratio fiendi_ demands for

every change of state another from which it regularly follows as from its

cause, and a substance as its unchangeable substratum--

matter. All changes

take place necessarily, all that is real is material; the law of causality

is valid for phenomena alone, not beyond them, and holds only for the

states of substances, not for substances themselves. In inorganic nature

causes work mechanically, in organic nature as stimuli (in which the

reaction is not equal to the action), and in animated nature as motives.

A motive is a conscious (but not therefore a free) cause; the law of

motivation is the _ratio agendi_. This serial order,

"mechanical cause,

stimulus, and motive," denotes only distinctions in the mode of action, not

in the necessity of action. Man's actions follow as inevitably from his

character and the motives which influence him as a clock strikes the hours;

the freedom of the will is a chimera. Finally, the _ratio cognoscendi_

determines that a judgment must have a sufficient ground in order to be

true. Judgment or the connection of concepts is the chief activity of the

reason, which, as the faculty of abstract thought and the organ of science,

constitutes the difference between man and the brute, while the possession

of the understanding with its intuition of objects is common to both. In

opposition to the customary overestimation of this gift of mediate

representations, of language, and of reflection, Schopenhauer gives

prominence to the fact that the reason is not a creative faculty like the

understanding, but only a receptive power, that it clarifies and transforms

the content furnished by intuition without increasing it by new

representations.

Objective cognition is confined within the circle of our representations;

all that is knowable is phenomenon. Space, time, and causality spread out

like a triple veil between us and the _per se_ of things, and prevent a

vision of the true nature of the world. There is one point, however, at

which we know more than mere phenomena, where of these three disturbing

media only one, time-form, separates us from the thing in itself. This

point is the consciousness of ourselves.

On the one hand, I appear to myself as body. My body is a temporal,

spatial, material object, an object like all others, and with them subject

to the laws of objectivity. But besides this objective cognition, I have,

further, an immediate consciousness of myself, through which I apprehend

my true being--I know myself as willing. My will is more than a mere

representation, it is the original element in me, the truly real which

appears to me as body. The will is related to the intellect as the primary

to the secondary, as substance to accident; it is related to the body

as the inner to the outer, as reality to phenomenon. The act of will is

followed at once and inevitably by the movement of the body willed, nay,

the two are one and the same, only given in different ways: will is the

body seen from within, body the will seen from without, the will become

visible, objectified. After the analogy of ourselves, again, who appear to

ourselves as material objects but in truth are will, all existence is to

be judged. The universe is the _mac-anthropos_; the knowledge of our own

essence, the key to the knowledge of the essence of the world. Like our

body, the whole world is the visibility of will. The human will is the

highest stage in the development of the same principle which manifests its

activity in the various forces of nature, and which properly takes its name

from the highest species. To penetrate further into the inner nature of

things than this is impossible. What that which presents itself as will

and which still remains after the negation of the latter (see below) is in

itself, is for us absolutely unknowable.

The world is _per se_ will. None of the predicates are to be attributed to

the primal will which we ascribe to things in consequence of our subjective

forms of thought--neither determination by causes or ends, nor plurality:

it stands outside the law of causality, as also outside space and time,

which form the _principium individuationis_. The primal will is groundless,

blind stress, unconscious impulse toward existence; it is one, the one

and all, [Greek: en nai pan]. That which manifests itself as gravity, as

magnetic force, as the impulse to growth, as the _vis medicatrix naturae_,

is only this one world-will, whose unity (not conscious character!) shows

itself in the purposiveness of its embodiments. The essence of each thing,

its hidden quality, at which empirical explanation finds its limit, is its

will: the essence of the stone is its will to fall; that of the lungs is

the will to breathe; teeth, throat, and bowels are hunger objectified.

Those qualities in which the universal will gives itself material

manifestation form a series with grades of increasing perfection, a realm

of unchangeable specific forms or eternal Ideas, which (with a real value

difficult to determine) stand midway between the one primal will and

the numberless individual beings. That the organic individual does not

perfectly correspond to the ideal of its species, but only approximates

this more or less closely, is grounded in the fact that the stadia in the

objectification of the will, or the Ideas, contend, as it were, for matter;

and whatever of force is used up in the victory of the higher Ideas over

the lower is lost for the development of the examples of the former. The

higher the level on which a being stands the clearer the expression of its

individuality. The most general forces of nature, which constitute the raw

mass, play the fundamental bass in the world-symphony, the higher stages

of inorganic nature, with the vegetable and animal worlds, the harmonious

middle parts, and man the guiding treble, the significant melody. With the

human brain the world as idea is given at a stroke; in this organ the will

has kindled a torch in order to throw light upon itself and to carry out

its designs with careful deliberation; it has brought forth the intellect

as its instrument, which, with the great majority of men, remains in a

position of subservience to the will. Brain and thought are the same; the

former is nothing other than the will to know, as the stomach is will

to digest. Those only talk of an immaterial soul who import into

philosophy--where such ideas do not belong--concepts taught them when they

were confirmed.

Schopenhauer's philosophy is as rich in inconsistencies as his personality

was self-willed and unharmonious. "He carries into his system all the

contradictions and whims of his capricious nature," says Zeller. From the

most radical idealism (the objective world a product of representation) he

makes a sharp transition to the crassest materialism (thought a function of

the brain); first matter is to be a mere idea, now thought is to be merely

a material phenomenon! The third and fourth books of _The World as Will and

Idea_, which develop the aesthetic and ethical standpoint of their author,

stand in as sharp a contradiction to the first (poëtical) and the second

(metaphysical) books as these to each other. While at first it was

maintained that all representation is subject to the principle of

sufficient reason, we are now told that, besides causal cognition, there is

a higher knowledge, one which is free from the control of this principle,

viz., aesthetic and philosophical intuition. If, before, it was said that

the intellect is the creature and servant of the will, we now learn that in

favored individuals it gains the power to throw off the yoke of slavery,

and not only to raise itself to the blessedness of contemplation free from

all desire, but even to enter on a victorious conflict with the tyrant,

to slay the will. The source of this power--is not revealed. R. Haym _(A.

Schopenhauer_, 1864, reprinted from the _Preussische Jahrbücher_) was not

far wrong in characterizing Schopenhauer's philosophy as a clever novel,

which entertains the reader by its rapid vicissitudes.

The contemplation which is free from causality and will is the essence of

aesthetic life; the partial and total sublation, the quieting and negation

of the will, that of ethical life. It is but seldom, and only in the

artistic and philosophical genius, that the intellect succeeds in freeing

itself from the supremacy of the will, and, laying aside the question of

the _why_ and _wherefore_, _where_ and _when_, in sinking itself completely

in the pure _what_ of things. While with the majority of mankind, as with

animals, the intellect always remains a prisoner in the service of the will

to live, of self-preservation, of personal interests, in gifted men,

in artists and thinkers, it strips off all that is individual, and, in

disinterested vision of the Ideas, becomes pure, timeless subject, freed

from the will. Art removes individuality from the subject as well as from

the object; its comforting and cheering influence depends on the fact that

it elevates those enjoying it to the stand-point--raised above all pain

of desire--of a fixed, calm, completely objective contemplation of the

unchangeable essence, of the eternal types of things.

For aesthetic

intuition the object is not a thing under relations of space, time, and

cause, but only an expression, an exemplification, a representative of

the Idea. Poetry, which presents--most perfectly in tragedy--the Idea of

humanity, stands higher than the plastic arts. The highest rank, however,

belongs to music, since it does not, like the other arts, represent single

Ideas, but--as an unconscious metaphysic, nay, a second, ideal world above

the material world--the will itself. In view of this high appreciation

of their art, it is not surprising that musicians have contributed a

considerable contingent to the band of Schopenhauer worshipers. A different

source of attraction for the wider circle of readers was supplied by the

piquant spice of pessimism.

If the purposiveness of the phenomena of nature points to the unity of the

primal will, the unspeakable misery of life, which Schopenhauer sets forth

with no less of eloquence, proves the blindness and irrationality of the

world-ground. To live is to suffer; the world contains incomparably more

pain than pleasure; it is the worst possible world. In the world of

sub-animal nature aimless striving; in the animal world an insatiable

impulse after enjoyment--while the will, deceiving itself with fancied

happiness to come, which always remains denied it, and continually

tossed to and fro between necessity and _ennui_, never attains complete

satisfaction. The pleasure which it pursues is nothing but the removal of

a dissatisfaction, and vanishes at once when the longing is stilled, to

be replaced by fresh wants, that is, by new pains. In view of the

indescribable misery in the world, to favor optimism is evidence not so

much of folly and blindness as of a wanton disposition.

The old saying is

true: Non-existence is better than existence. The misery, however, is the

just punishment for the original sin of the individual, which gave itself

its particular existence by an act of intelligible freedom. Redemption from

the sin and misery of existence is possible only through a second act

of transcendental freedom, which, since it consists in the complete

transformation of our being, and since it is supernatural in its origin,

the Church is right in describing as a new birth and work of grace.

Morality presupposes pessimistic insight into the badness of the world and

the fruitlessness of all desire, and pantheistic discernment of the untruth

of individual existence and the identity in essence of all individuals

from a metaphysical standpoint. Man is able to free himself from egoistic

self-affirmation only when he perceives the two truths, that all striving

is vain and the longed-for pleasure unattainable, and that all individuals

are at bottom one, viz. manifestations of the same primal will. This is

temporarily effected in sympathy, which, as the only counterpoise to

natural selfishness, is the true moral motive and the source of all love

and justice. The sympathizer sees himself in others and feels their

suffering as his own. The entire negation of the will, however, inspiring

examples of which have been furnished by the Christian ascetics and

Oriental penitents, stands higher than the vulgar virtue of sympathy with

the sufferings of others. Here knowledge, turned away from the individual

and vain to the whole and genuine, ceases to be a motive for the will and

becomes a means of stilling it; the intellect is transformed from a motive

into a quietive, and brings him who gives himself up to the All safely

out from the storm of the passions into the peace of deliverance from

existence. Absence of will, resignation, is holiness and blessedness in

one. For him who has slain the will in himself the motley deceptive dream

of phenomena has vanished, he lives in the ether of true reality, which for

our knowledge is an empty nothingness ("Nirvana"), yet (as the ultimate,

incomprehensible _per se_, which remains after the annulling of the will)

only a relative nothingness--relative to the phenomenon.

Schopenhauer disposes of the sense of responsibility and the reproofs of

conscience, which are inconvenient facts for his determinism, by making

them both refer, not to single deeds and the empirical character, but to

the indivisible act of the intelligible character.

Conscience does not

blame me because I have acted as I must act with my character and the

motives given, but for being what in these actions I reveal myself to be.

_Operari sequitur esse_. My action follows from my being, my being was my

own free choice, and a new act of freedom is alone capable of transforming

it.

If Schopenhauer is fond of referring to the agreement of his views with the

oldest and most perfect religions, the idea lies in the background that

religion,--which springs from the same metaphysical needs as philosophy,

and, for the great multitude, who lack the leisure and the capacity for

philosophical thought, takes the place of the former,--

as the metaphysics

of the people, clothes the same fundamental truths which the philosopher

offers in conceptual form and supports by rational grounds in the garb of

myth and allegory, and places them under the protection of an external

authority. When this character of religion is overlooked, and that which

is intended to be symb