Mysticism and logic by Bertrand Russel. - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

"CAUSE AND EFFECT. (1) Cause and effect ... are correlative terms

denoting any two distinguishable things, phases, or aspects of

reality, which are so related to each other that whenever the

first ceases to exist the second comes into existence

immediately after, and whenever the second comes into existence

the first has ceased to exist immediately before."

Let us consider these three definitions in turn. The first, obviously,

is unintelligible without a definition of "necessary."

Under this

head, Baldwin's _Dictionary_ gives the following:--

"NECESSARY. That is necessary which not only is true, but would

be true under all circumstances. Something more than brute

compulsion is, therefore, involved in the conception; there is

a general law under which the thing takes place."

The notion of cause is so intimately connected with that of necessity

that it will be no digression to linger over the above definition,

with a view to discovering, if possible, _some_ meaning of which it is

capable; for, as it stands, it is very far from having any definite

signification.

The first point to notice is that, if any meaning is to be given to

the phrase "would be true under all circumstances," the subject of it

must be a propositional function, not a proposition.[35]

A

proposition is simply true or false, and that ends the matter: there

can be no question of "circumstances." "Charles I's head was cut off"

is just as true in summer as in winter, on Sundays as on Mondays. Thus

when it is worth saying that something "would be true under all

circumstances," the something in question must be a propositional

function, i.e. an expression containing a variable, and becoming a

proposition when a value is assigned to the variable; the varying

"circumstances" alluded to are then the different values of which the

variable is capable. Thus if "necessary" means "what is true under all

circumstances," then "if _x_ is a man, _x_ is mortal" is necessary,

because it is true for any possible value of _x_. Thus we should be

led to the following definition:--

"NECESSARY is a predicate of a propositional function, meaning

that it is true for all possible values of its argument or

arguments."

Unfortunately, however, the definition in Baldwin's _Dictionary_ says

that what is necessary is not only "true under all circumstances" but

is also "true." Now these two are incompatible. Only propositions can

be "true," and only propositional functions can be "true under all

circumstances." Hence the definition as it stands is nonsense. What is

meant seems to be this: "A proposition is necessary when it is a value

of a propositional function which is true under all circumstances,

i.e. for all values of its argument or arguments." But if we adopt

this definition, the same proposition will be necessary or contingent

according as we choose one or other of its terms as the argument to

our propositional function. For example, "if Socrates is a man,

Socrates is mortal," is necessary if Socrates is chosen as argument,

but not if _man_ or _mortal_ is chosen. Again, "if Socrates is a man,

Plato is mortal," will be necessary if either Socrates or _man_ is

chosen as argument, but not if Plato or _mortal_ is chosen. However,

this difficulty can be overcome by specifying the constituent which is

to be regarded as argument, and we thus arrive at the following

definition:

"A proposition is _necessary_ with respect to a given constituent if

it remains true when that constituent is altered in any way compatible

with the proposition remaining significant."

We may now apply this definition to the definition of causality quoted

above. It is obvious that the argument must be the time at which the

earlier event occurs. Thus an instance of causality will be such as:

"If the event [Math: e_{1}] occurs at the time [Math: t_{1}], it will

be followed by the event [Math: e_{2}]." This proposition is intended

to be necessary with respect to [Math: t_{1}], i.e. to remain true

however [Math: t_{1}] may be varied. Causality, as a universal law,

will then be the following: "Given any event [Math: t_{1}], there is

an event [Math: e_{2}] such that, whenever [Math: t_{1}]

occurs,

[Math: e_{2}] occurs later." But before this can be considered

precise, we must specify how much later [Math: e_{2}] is to occur.

Thus the principle becomes:--

"Given any event [Math: e_{1}], there is an event [Math: e_{2}] and a

time-interval τ such that, whenever [Math: e_{1}]

occurs, [Math:

e_{2}] follows after an interval τ."

I am not concerned as yet to consider whether this law is true or

false. For the present, I am merely concerned to discover what the law

of causality is supposed to be. I pass, therefore, to the other

definitions quoted above.

The second definition need not detain us long, for two reasons. First,

because it is psychological: not the "thought or perception" of a

process, but the process itself, must be what concerns us in

considering causality. Secondly, because it is circular: in speaking

of a process as "taking place in consequence of" another process, it

introduces the very notion of cause which was to be defined.

The third definition is by far the most precise; indeed as regards

clearness it leaves nothing to be desired. But a great difficulty is

caused by the temporal contiguity of cause and effect which the

definition asserts. No two instants are contiguous, since the

time-series is compact; hence either the cause or the effect or both

must, if the definition is correct, endure for a finite time; indeed,

by the wording of the definition it is plain that both are assumed to

endure for a finite time. But then we are faced with a dilemma: if the

cause is a process involving change within itself, we shall require

(if causality is universal) causal relations between its earlier and

later parts; moreover, it would seem that only the later parts can be

relevant to the effect, since the earlier parts are not contiguous to

the effect, and therefore (by the definition) cannot influence the

effect. Thus we shall be led to diminish the duration of the cause

without limit, and however much we may diminish it, there will still

remain an earlier part which might be altered without altering the

effect, so that the true cause, as defined, will not have been

reached, for it will be observed that the definition excludes

plurality of causes. If, on the other hand, the cause is purely

static, involving no change within itself, then, in the first place,

no such cause is to be found in nature, and in the second place, it

seems strange--too strange to be accepted, in spite of bare logical

possibility--that the cause, after existing placidly for some time,

should suddenly explode into the effect, when it might just as well

have done so at any earlier time, or have gone on unchanged without

producing its effect. This dilemma, therefore, is fatal to the view

that cause and effect can be contiguous in time; if there are causes

and effects, they must be separated by a finite time-interval τ, as

was assumed in the above interpretation of the first definition.

What is essentially the same statement of the law of causality as the

one elicited above from the first of Baldwin's definitions is given by

other philosophers. Thus John Stuart Mill says:--

"The Law of Causation, the recognition of which is the main pillar of

inductive science, is but the familiar truth, that invariability of

succession is found by observation to obtain between every fact in

nature and some other fact which has preceded it."[36]

And Bergson, who has rightly perceived that the law as stated by

philosophers is worthless, nevertheless continues to suppose that it

is used in science. Thus he says:--

"Now, it is argued, this law [the law of causality]

means that every

phenomenon is determined by its conditions, or, in other words, that

the same causes produce the same effects."[37]

And again:--

"We perceive physical phenomena, and these phenomena obey laws. This

means: (1) That phenomena _a_, _b_, _c_, _d_, previously perceived,

can occur again in the same shape; (2) that a certain phenomenon P,

which appeared after the conditions _a_, _b_, _c_, _d_, and after

these conditions only, will not fail to recur as soon as the same

conditions are again present."[38]

A great part of Bergson's attack on science rests on the assumption

that it employs this principle. In fact, it employs no such principle,

but philosophers--even Bergson--are too apt to take their views on

science from each other, not from science. As to what the principle

is, there is a fair consensus among philosophers of different schools.

There are, however, a number of difficulties which at once arise. I

omit the question of plurality of causes for the present, since other

graver questions have to be considered. Two of these, which are forced

on our attention by the above statement of the law, are the

following:--

(1) What is meant by an "event"?

(2) How long may the time-interval be between cause and effect?

(1) An "event," in the statement of the law, is obviously intended to

be something that is likely to recur since otherwise the law becomes

trivial. It follows that an "event" is not a particular, but some

universal of which there may be many instances. It follows also that

an "event" must be something short of the whole state of the universe,

since it is highly improbable that this will recur. What is meant by

an "event" is something like striking a match, or dropping a penny

into the slot of an automatic machine. If such an event is to recur,

it must not be defined too narrowly: we must not state with what

degree of force the match is to be struck, nor what is to be the

temperature of the penny. For if such considerations were relevant,

our "event" would occur at most once, and the law would cease to give

information. An "event," then, is a universal defined sufficiently

widely to admit of many particular occurrences in time being instances

of it.

(2) The next question concerns the time-interval.

Philosophers, no

doubt, think of cause and effect as contiguous in time, but this, for

reasons already given, is impossible. Hence, since there are no

infinitesimal time-intervals, there must be some finite lapse of time

τ between cause and effect. This, however, at once raises insuperable

difficulties. However short we make the interval τ, something may

happen during this interval which prevents the expected result. I put

my penny in the slot, but before I can draw out my ticket there is an

earthquake which upsets the machine and my calculations.

In order to

be sure of the expected effect, we must know that there is nothing in

the environment to interfere with it. But this means that the supposed

cause is not, by itself, adequate to insure the effect.

And as soon as

we include the environment, the probability of repetition is

diminished, until at last, when the whole environment is included, the

probability of repetition becomes almost _nil_.

In spite of these difficulties, it must, of course, be admitted that

many fairly dependable regularities of sequence occur in daily life.

It is these regularities that have suggested the supposed law of

causality; where they are found to fail, it is thought that a better

formulation could have been found which would have never failed. I am

far from denying that there may be such sequences which in fact never

do fail. It may be that there will never be an exception to the rule

that when a stone of more than a certain mass, moving with more than a

certain velocity, comes in contact with a pane of glass of less than

a certain thickness, the glass breaks. I also do not deny that the

observation of such regularities, even when they are not without

exceptions, is useful in the infancy of a science: the observation

that unsupported bodies in air usually fall was a stage on the way to

the law of gravitation. What I deny is that science assumes the

existence of invariable uniformities of sequence of this kind, or that

it aims at discovering them. All such uniformities, as we saw, depend

upon a certain vagueness in the definition of the

"events." That

bodies fall is a vague qualitative statement; science wishes to know

how fast they fall. This depends upon the shape of the bodies and the

density of the air. It is true that there is more nearly uniformity

when they fall in a vacuum; so far as Galileo could observe, the

uniformity is then complete. But later it appeared that even there the

latitude made a difference, and the altitude.

Theoretically, the

position of the sun and moon must make a difference. In short, every

advance in a science takes us farther away from the crude uniformities

which are first observed, into greater differentiation of antecedent

and consequent, and into a continually wider circle of antecedents

recognised as relevant.

The principle "same cause, same effect," which philosophers imagine to

be vital to science, is therefore utterly otiose. As soon as the

antecedents have been given sufficiently fully to enable the

consequent to be calculated with some exactitude, the antecedents have

become so complicated that it is very unlikely they will ever recur.

Hence, if this were the principle involved, science would remain

utterly sterile.

The importance of these considerations lies partly in the fact that

they lead to a more correct account of scientific procedure, partly in

the fact that they remove the analogy with human volition which makes

the conception of cause such a fruitful source of fallacies. The

latter point will become clearer by the help of some illustrations.

For this purpose I shall consider a few maxims which have played a

great part in the history of philosophy.

(1) "Cause and effect must more or less resemble each other." This

principle was prominent in the philosophy of occasionalism, and is

still by no means extinct. It is still often thought, for example,

that mind could not have grown up in a universe which previously

contained nothing mental, and one ground for this belief is that

matter is too dissimilar from mind to have been able to cause it. Or,

more particularly, what are termed the nobler parts of our nature are

supposed to be inexplicable, unless the universe always contained

something at least equally noble which could cause them.

All such

views seem to depend upon assuming some unduly simplified law of

causality; for, in any legitimate sense of "cause" and

"effect,"

science seems to show that they are usually very widely dissimilar,

the "cause" being, in fact, two states of the whole universe, and the

"effect" some particular event.

(2) "Cause is analogous to volition, since there must be an

intelligible _nexus_ between cause and effect." This maxim is, I

think, often unconsciously in the imaginations of philosophers who

would reject it when explicitly stated. It is probably operative in

the view we have just been considering, that mind could not have

resulted from a purely material world. I do not profess to know what

is meant by "intelligible"; it seems to mean "familiar to

imagination." Nothing is less "intelligible," in any other sense, than

the connection between an act of will and its fulfilment. But

obviously the sort of nexus desired between cause and effect is such

as could only hold between the "events" which the supposed law of

causality contemplates; the laws which replace causality in such a

science as physics leave no room for any two events between which a

nexus could be sought.

(3) "The cause _compels_ the effect in some sense in which the effect

does not compel the cause." This belief seems largely operative in the

dislike of determinism; but, as a matter of fact, it is connected with

our second maxim, and falls as soon as that is abandoned. We may

define "compulsion" as follows: "Any set of circumstances is said to

compel A when A desires to do something which the circumstances

prevent, or to abstain from something which the circumstances cause."

This presupposes that some meaning has been found for the word

"cause"--a point to which I shall return later. What I want to make

clear at present is that compulsion is a very complex notion,

involving thwarted desire. So long as a person does what he wishes to

do, there is no compulsion, however much his wishes may be calculable

by the help of earlier events. And where desire does not come in,

there can be no question of compulsion. Hence it is, in general,

misleading to regard the cause as compelling the effect.

A vaguer form of the same maxim substitutes the word

"determine" for

the word "compel"; we are told that the cause _determines_ the effect

in a sense in which the effect does not _determine_ the cause. It is

not quite clear what is meant by "determining"; the only precise

sense, so far as I know, is that of a function or one-many relation.

If we admit plurality of causes, but not of effects, that is, if we

suppose that, given the cause, the effect must be such and such, but,

given the effect, the cause may have been one of many alternatives,

then we may say that the cause determines the effect, but not the

effect the cause. Plurality of causes, however, results only from

conceiving the effect vaguely and narrowly and the cause precisely and

widely. Many antecedents may "cause" a man's death, because his death

is vague and narrow. But if we adopt the opposite course, taking as

the "cause" the drinking of a dose of arsenic, and as the "effect" the

whole state of the world five minutes later, we shall have plurality

of effects instead of plurality of causes. Thus the supposed lack of

symmetry between "cause" and "effect" is illusory.

(4) "A cause cannot operate when it has ceased to exist, because what

has ceased to exist is nothing." This is a common maxim, and a still

more common unexpressed prejudice. It has, I fancy, a good deal to do

with the attractiveness of Bergson's "_durée_": since the past has

effects now, it must still exist in some sense. The mistake in this

maxim consists in the supposition that causes "operate"

at all. A

volition "operates" when what it wills takes place; but nothing can

operate except a volition. The belief that causes

"operate" results

from assimilating them, consciously or unconsciously, to volitions. We

have already seen that, if there are causes at all, they must be

separated by a finite interval of time from their effects, and thus

cause their effects after they have ceased to exist.

It may be objected to the above definition of a volition

"operating"

that it only operates when it "causes" what it wills, not when it

merely happens to be followed by what it wills. This certainly

represents the usual view of what is meant by a volition

"operating,"

but as it involves the very view of causation which we are engaged in

combating, it is not open to us as a definition. We may say that a

volition "operates" when there is some law in virtue of which a

similar volition in rather similar circumstances will usually be

followed by what it wills. But this is a vague conception, and

introduces ideas which we have not yet considered. What is chiefly

important to notice is that the usual notion of

"operating" is not

open to us if we reject, as I contend that we should, the usual notion

of causation.

(5) "A cause cannot operate except where it is." This maxim is very

widespread; it was urged against Newton, and has remained a source of

prejudice against "action at a distance." In philosophy it has led to

a denial of transient action, and thence to monism or Leibnizian

monadism. Like the analogous maxim concerning temporal contiguity, it

rests upon the assumption that causes "operate," i.e.

that they are in

some obscure way analogous to volitions. And, as in the case of

temporal contiguity, the inferences drawn from this maxim are wholly

groundless.

I return now to the question, What law or laws can be found to take

the place of the supposed law of causality?

First, without passing beyond such uniformities of sequence as are

contemplated by the traditional law, we may admit that, if any such

sequence has been observed in a great many cases, and has never been

found to fail, there is an inductive probability that it will be found

to hold in future cases. If stones have hitherto been found to break

windows, it is probable that they will continue to do so. This, of

course, assumes the inductive principle, of which the truth may

reasonably be questioned; but as this principle is not our present

concern, I shall in this discussion treat it as indubitable. We may

then say, in the case of any such frequently observed sequence, that

the earlier event is the _cause_ and the later event the _effect_.

Several considerations, however, make such special sequences very

different from the traditional relation of cause and effect. In the

first place, the sequence, in any hitherto unobserved instance, is no

more than probable, whereas the relation of cause and effect was

supposed to be necessary. I do not mean by this merely that we are not

sure of having discovered a true case of cause and effect; I mean

that, even when we have a case of cause and effect in our present

sense, all that is meant is that on grounds of observation, it is

probable that when one occurs the other will also occur.

Thus in our

present sense, A may be the cause of B even if there actually are

cases where B does not follow A. Striking a match will be the cause of

its igniting, in spite of the fact that some matches are damp and fail

to ignite.

In the second place, it will not be assumed that _every_

event has

some antecedent which is its cause in this sense; we shall only

believe in causal sequences where we find them, without any

presumption that they always are to be found.

In the third place, _any_ case of sufficiently frequent sequence will

be causal in our present sense; for example, we shall not refuse to

say that night is the cause of day. Our repugnance to saying this

arises from the ease with which we can imagine the sequence to fail,

but owing to the fact that cause and effect must be separated by a

finite interval of time, _any_ such sequence _might_

fail through the

interposition of other circumstances in the interval.

Mill, discussing

this instance of night and day, says:--