Mysticism and logic by Bertrand Russel. - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

If this view seems at first sight disappointing, we may remind

ourselves that a similar change has been found necessary in all the

other sciences. The physicist or chemist is not now required to prove

the ethical importance of his ions or atoms; the biologist is not

expected to prove the utility of the plants or animals which he

dissects. In pre-scientific ages this was not the case.

Astronomy, for

example, was studied because men believed in astrology: it was thought

that the movements of the planets had the most direct and important

bearing upon the lives of human beings. Presumably, when this belief

decayed and the disinterested study of astronomy began, many who had

found astrology absorbingly interesting decided that astronomy had too

little human interest to be worthy of study. Physics, as it appears in

Plato's Timæus for example, is full of ethical notions: it is an

essential part of its purpose to show that the earth is worthy of

admiration. The modern physicist, on the contrary, though he has no

wish to deny that the earth is admirable, is not concerned, as

physicist, with its ethical attributes: he is merely concerned to find

out facts, not to consider whether they are good or bad.

In

psychology, the scientific attitude is even more recent and more

difficult than in the physical sciences: it is natural to consider

that human nature is either good or bad, and to suppose that the

difference between good and bad, so all-important in practice, must be

important in theory also. It is only during the last century that an

ethically neutral psychology has grown up; and here too, ethical

neutrality has been essential to scientific success.

In philosophy, hitherto, ethical neutrality has been seldom sought and

hardly ever achieved. Men have remembered their wishes, and have

judged philosophies in relation to their wishes. Driven from the

particular sciences, the belief that the notions of good and evil must

afford a key to the understanding of the world has sought a refuge in

philosophy. But even from this last refuge, if philosophy is not to

remain a set of pleasing dreams, this belief must be driven forth. It

is a commonplace that happiness is not best achieved by those who

seek it directly; and it would seem that the same is true of the good.

In thought, at any rate, those who forget good and evil and seek only

to know the facts are more likely to achieve good than those who view

the world through the distorting medium of their own desires.

We are thus brought back to our seeming paradox, that a philosophy

which does not seek to impose upon the world its own conceptions of

good and evil is not only more likely to achieve truth, but is also

the outcome of a higher ethical standpoint than one which, like

evolutionism and most traditional systems, is perpetually appraising

the universe and seeking to find in it an embodiment of present

ideals. In religion, and in every deeply serious view of the world and

of human destiny, there is an element of submission, a realisation of

the limits of human power, which is somewhat lacking in the modern

world, with its quick material successes and its insolent belief in

the boundless possibilities of progress. "He that loveth his life

shall lose it"; and there is danger lest, through a too confident love

of life, life itself should lose much of what gives it its highest

worth. The submission which religion inculcates in action is

essentially the same in spirit as that which science teaches in

thought; and the ethical neutrality by which its victories have been

achieved is the outcome of that submission.

The good which it concerns us to remember is the good which it lies in

our power to create--the good in our own lives and in our attitude

towards the world. Insistence on belief in an external realisation of

the good is a form of self-assertion, which, while it cannot secure

the external good which it desires, can seriously impair the inward

good which lies within our power, and destroy that reverence towards

fact which constitutes both what is valuable in humility and what is

fruitful in the scientific temper.

Human beings cannot, of course, wholly transcend human nature;

something subjective, if only the interest that determines the

direction of our attention, must remain in all our thought. But

scientific philosophy comes nearer to objectivity than any other human

pursuit, and gives us, therefore, the closest constant and the most

intimate relation with the outer world that it is possible to achieve.

To the primitive mind, everything is either friendly or hostile; but

experience has shown that friendliness and hostility are not the

conceptions by which the world is to be understood.

Scientific

philosophy thus represents, though as yet only in a nascent condition,

a higher form of thought than any pre-scientific belief or

imagination, and, like every approach to self-transcendence, it brings

with it a rich reward in increase of scope and breadth and

comprehension. Evolutionism, in spite of its appeals to particular

scientific facts, fails to be a truly scientific philosophy because of

its slavery to time, its ethical preoccupations, and its predominant

interest in our mundane concerns and destiny. A truly scientific

philosophy will be more humble, more piecemeal, more arduous, offering

less glitter of outward mirage to flatter fallacious hopes, but more

indifferent to fate, and more capable of accepting the world without

the tyrannous imposition of our human and temporary demands.

FOOTNOTES:

[1] All the above quotations are from Burnet's _Early Greek

Philosophy_, (2nd ed., 1908), pp. 146-156.

[2] _Republic_, 514, translated by Davies and Vaughan.

[3] This section, and also one or two pages in later sections, have

been printed in a course of Lowell lectures _On our knowledge of the

external world_, published by the Open Court Publishing Company. But I

have left them here, as this is the context for which they were

originally written.

[4] _Introduction to Metaphysics_, p. 1.

[5] Whinfield's translation of the _Masnavi_ (Trübner, 1887), p. 34.

[6] _Ethics_, Bk. IV, Prop. LXII.

[7] Ib., Pt. IV, Df. I.

[8] _Ethics_. Pt. II. Df. VI.

II

THE PLACE OF SCIENCE IN A LIBERAL EDUCATION

I

Science, to the ordinary reader of newspapers, is represented by a

varying selection of sensational triumphs, such as wireless telegraphy

and aeroplanes, radio-activity and the marvels of modern alchemy. It is

not of this aspect of science that I wish to speak.

Science, in this

aspect, consists of detached up-to-date fragments, interesting only

until they are replaced by something newer and more up-to-date,

displaying nothing of the systems of patiently constructed knowledge

out of which, almost as a casual incident, have come the practically

useful results which interest the man in the street. The increased

command over the forces of nature which is derived from science is

undoubtedly an amply sufficient reason for encouraging scientific

research, but this reason has been so often urged and is so easily

appreciated that other reasons, to my mind quite as important, are apt

to be overlooked. It is with these other reasons, especially with the

intrinsic value of a scientific habit of mind in forming our outlook

on the world, that I shall be concerned in what follows.

The instance of wireless telegraphy will serve to illustrate the

difference between the two points of view. Almost all the serious

intellectual labour required for the possibility of this invention is

due to three men--Faraday, Maxwell, and Hertz. In alternating layers

of experiment and theory these three men built up the modern theory of

electromagnetism, and demonstrated the identity of light with

electromagnetic waves. The system which they discovered is one of

profound intellectual interest, bringing together and unifying an

endless variety of apparently detached phenomena, and displaying a

cumulative mental power which cannot but afford delight to every

generous spirit. The mechanical details which remained to be adjusted

in order to utilise their discoveries for a practical system of

telegraphy demanded, no doubt, very considerable ingenuity, but had

not that broad sweep and that universality which could give them

intrinsic interest as an object of disinterested contemplation.

From the point of view of training the mind, of giving that

well-informed, impersonal outlook which constitutes culture in the

good sense of this much-misused word, it seems to be generally held

indisputable that a literary education is superior to one based on

science. Even the warmest advocates of science are apt to rest their

claims on the contention that culture ought to be sacrificed to

utility. Those men of science who respect culture, when they associate

with men learned in the classics, are apt to admit, not merely

politely, but sincerely, a certain inferiority on their side,

compensated doubtless by the services which science renders to

humanity, but none the less real. And so long as this attitude exists

among men of science, it tends to verify itself: the intrinsically

valuable aspects of science tend to be sacrificed to the merely

useful, and little attempt is made to preserve that leisurely,

systematic survey by which the finer quality of mind is formed and

nourished.

But even if there be, in present fact, any such inferiority as is

supposed in the educational value of science, this is, I believe, not

the fault of science itself, but the fault of the spirit in which

science is taught. If its full possibilities were realised by those

who teach it, I believe that its capacity of producing those habits of

mind which constitute the highest mental excellence would be at least

as great as that of literature, and more particularly of Greek and

Latin literature. In saying this I have no wish whatever to disparage

a classical education. I have not myself enjoyed its benefits, and my

knowledge of Greek and Latin authors is derived almost wholly from

translations. But I am firmly persuaded that the Greeks fully deserve

all the admiration that is bestowed upon them, and that it is a very

great and serious loss to be unacquainted with their writings. It is

not by attacking them, but by drawing attention to neglected

excellences in science, that I wish to conduct my argument.

One defect, however, does seem inherent in a purely classical

education--namely, a too exclusive emphasis on the past.

By the study

of what is absolutely ended and can never be renewed, a habit of

criticism towards the present and the future is engendered. The

qualities in which the present excels are qualities to which the study

of the past does not direct attention, and to which, therefore, the

student of Greek civilisation may easily become blind.

In what is new

and growing there is apt to be something crude, insolent, even a

little vulgar, which is shocking to the man of sensitive taste;

quivering from the rough contact, he retires to the trim gardens of a

polished past, forgetting that they were reclaimed from the wilderness

by men as rough and earth-soiled as those from whom he shrinks in his

own day. The habit of being unable to recognise merit until it is

dead is too apt to be the result of a purely bookish life, and a

culture based wholly on the past will seldom be able to pierce through

everyday surroundings to the essential splendour of contemporary

things, or to the hope of still greater splendour in the future.

"My eyes saw not the men of old;

And now their age away has rolled.

I weep--to think I shall not see

The heroes of posterity."

So says the Chinese poet; but such impartiality is rare in the more

pugnacious atmosphere of the West, where the champions of past and

future fight a never-ending battle, instead of combining to seek out

the merits of both.

This consideration, which militates not only against the exclusive

study of the classics, but against every form of culture which has

become static, traditional, and academic, leads inevitably to the

fundamental question: What is the true end of education?

But before

attempting to answer this question it will be well to define the sense

in which we are to use the word "education." For this purpose I shall

distinguish the sense in which I mean to use it from two others, both

perfectly legitimate, the one broader and the other narrower than the

sense in which I mean to use the word.

In the broader sense, education will include not only what we learn

through instruction, but all that we learn through personal

experience--the formation of character through the education of life.

Of this aspect of education, vitally important as it is, I will say

nothing, since its consideration would introduce topics quite foreign

to the question with which we are concerned.

In the narrower sense, education may be confined to instruction, the

imparting of definite information on various subjects, because such

information, in and for itself, is useful in daily life.

Elementary

education--reading, writing, and arithmetic--is almost wholly of this

kind. But instruction, necessary as it is, does not _per se_

constitute education in the sense in which I wish to consider it.

Education, in the sense in which I mean it, may be defined as _the

formation, by means of instruction, of certain mental habits and a

certain outlook on life and the world_. It remains to ask ourselves,

what mental habits, and what sort of outlook, can be hoped for as the

result of instruction? When we have answered this question we can

attempt to decide what science has to contribute to the formation of

the habits and outlook which we desire.

Our whole life is built about a certain number--not a very small

number--of primary instincts and impulses. Only what is in some way

connected with these instincts and impulses appears to us desirable or

important; there is no faculty, whether "reason" or

"virtue" or

whatever it may be called, that can take our active life and our hopes

and fears outside the region controlled by these first movers of all

desire. Each of them is like a queen-bee, aided by a hive of workers

gathering honey; but when the queen is gone the workers languish and

die, and the cells remain empty of their expected sweetness. So with

each primary impulse in civilised man: it is surrounded and protected

by a busy swarm of attendant derivative desires, which store up in its

service whatever honey the surrounding world affords.

But if the

queen-impulse dies, the death-dealing influence, though retarded a

little by habit, spreads slowly through all the subsidiary impulses,

and a whole tract of life becomes inexplicably colourless. What was

formerly full of zest, and so obviously worth doing that it raised no

questions, has now grown dreary and purposeless: with a sense of

disillusion we inquire the meaning of life, and decide, perhaps, that

all is vanity. The search for an outside meaning that can _compel_ an

inner response must always be disappointed: all

"meaning" must be at

bottom related to our primary desires, and when they are extinct no

miracle can restore to the world the value which they reflected upon

it.

The purpose of education, therefore, cannot be to create any primary

impulse which is lacking in the uneducated; the purpose can only be to

enlarge the scope of those that human nature provides, by increasing

the number and variety of attendant thoughts, and by showing where the

most permanent satisfaction is to be found. Under the impulse of a

Calvinistic horror of the "natural man," this obvious truth has been

too often misconceived in the training of the young;

"nature" has been

falsely regarded as excluding all that is best in what is natural, and

the endeavour to teach virtue has led to the production of stunted and

contorted hypocrites instead of full-grown human beings.

From such

mistakes in education a better psychology or a kinder heart is

beginning to preserve the present generation; we need, therefore,

waste no more words on the theory that the purpose of education is to

thwart or eradicate nature.

But although nature must supply the initial force of desire, nature is

not, in the civilised man, the spasmodic, fragmentary, and yet violent

set of impulses that it is in the savage. Each impulse has its

constitutional ministry of thought and knowledge and reflection,

through which possible conflicts of impulses are foreseen, and

temporary impulses are controlled by the unifying impulse which may be

called wisdom. In this way education destroys the crudity of

instinct, and increases through knowledge the wealth and variety of

the individual's contacts with the outside world, making him no longer

an isolated fighting unit, but a citizen of the universe, embracing

distant countries, remote regions of space, and vast stretches of past

and future within the circle of his interests. It is this simultaneous

softening in the insistence of desire and enlargement of its scope

that is the chief moral end of education.

Closely connected with this moral end is the more purely intellectual

aim of education, the endeavour to make us see and imagine the world

in an objective manner, as far as possible as it is in itself, and not

merely through the distorting medium of personal desire.

The complete

attainment of such an objective view is no doubt an ideal,

indefinitely approachable, but not actually and fully realisable.

Education, considered as a process of forming our mental habits and

our outlook on the world, is to be judged successful in proportion as

its outcome approximates to this ideal; in proportion, that is to say,

as it gives us a true view of our place in society, of the relation of

the whole human society to its non-human environment, and of the

nature of the non-human world as it is in itself apart from our

desires and interests. If this standard is admitted, we can return to

the consideration of science, inquiring how far science contributes to

such an aim, and whether it is in any respect superior to its rivals

in educational practice.

II

Two opposite and at first sight conflicting merits belong to science

as against literature and art. The one, which is not inherently

necessary, but is certainly true at the present day, is hopefulness

as to the future of human achievement, and in particular as to the

useful work that may be accomplished by any intelligent student. This

merit and the cheerful outlook which it engenders prevent what might

otherwise be the depressing effect of another aspect of science, to my

mind also a merit, and perhaps its greatest merit--I mean the

irrelevance of human passions and of the whole subjective apparatus

where scientific truth is concerned. Each of these reasons for

preferring the study of science requires some amplification. Let us

begin with the first.

In the study of literature or art our attention is perpetually riveted

upon the past: the men of Greece or of the Renaissance did better than

any men do now; the triumphs of former ages, so far from facilitating

fresh triumphs in our own age, actually increase the difficulty of

fresh triumphs by rendering originality harder of attainment; not only

is artistic achievement not cumulative, but it seems even to depend

upon a certain freshness and _naïveté_ of impulse and vision which

civilisation tends to destroy. Hence comes, to those who have been

nourished on the literary and artistic productions of former ages, a

certain peevishness and undue fastidiousness towards the present, from

which there seems no escape except into the deliberate vandalism which

ignores tradition and in the search after originality achieves only

the eccentric. But in such vandalism there is none of the simplicity

and spontaneity out of which great art springs: theory is still the

canker in its core, and insincerity destroys the advantages of a

merely pretended ignorance.

The despair thus arising from an education which suggests no

pre-eminent mental activity except that of artistic creation is wholly

absent from an education which gives the knowledge of scientific

method. The discovery of scientific method, except in pure

mathematics, is a thing of yesterday; speaking broadly, we may say

that it dates from Galileo. Yet already it has transformed the world,

and its success proceeds with ever-accelerating velocity. In science

men have discovered an activity of the very highest value in which

they are no longer, as in art, dependent for progress upon the

appearance of continually greater genius, for in science the

successors stand upon the shoulders of their predecessors; where one

man of supreme genius has invented a method, a thousand lesser men can

apply it. No transcendent ability is required in order to make useful

discoveries in science; the edifice of science needs its masons,

bricklayers, and common labourers as well as its foremen,

master-builders, and architects. In art nothing worth doing can be

done without genius; in science even a very moderate capacity can

contribute to a supreme achievement.

In science the man of real genius is the man who invents a new method.

The notable discoveries are often made by his successors, who can

apply the method with fresh vigour, unimpaired by the previous labour

of perfecting it; but the mental calibre of the thought required for

their work, however brilliant, is not so great as that required by the

first inventor of the method. There are in science immense numbers of

different methods, appropriate to different classes of problems; but

over and above them all, there is something not easily definable,

which may be called _the_ method of science. It was formerly customary

to identify this with the inductive method, and to associate it with

the name of Bacon. But the true inductive method was not discovered by

Bacon, and the true method of science is something which includes

deduction as much as induction, logic and mathematics as much as

botany and geology. I shall not attempt the difficult task of stating

what the scientific method is, but I will try to indicate the temper

of mind out of which the scientific method grows, which is the second

of the two merits that were mentioned above as belonging to a

scientific education.

The kernel of the scientific outlook is a thing so simple, so obvious,

so seemingly trivial, that the mention of it may almost excite

derision. The kernel of the