Mysticism and logic by Bertrand Russel. - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

axioms is Euclid's; other equally good sets of axioms lead to other

results. Whether Euclid's axioms are true, is a question as to which

the pure mathematician is indifferent; and, what is more, it is a

question which it is theoretically impossible to answer with certainty

in the affirmative. It might possibly be shown, by very careful

measurements, that Euclid's axioms are false; but no measurements

could ever assure us (owing to the errors of observation) that they

are exactly true. Thus the geometer leaves to the man of science to

decide, as best he may, what axioms are most nearly true in the actual

world. The geometer takes any set of axioms that seem interesting, and

deduces their consequences. What defines Geometry, in this sense, is

that the axioms must give rise to a series of more than one dimension.

And it is thus that Geometry becomes a department in the study of

order.

In Geometry, as in other parts of mathematics, Peano and his disciples

have done work of the very greatest merit as regards principles.

Formerly, it was held by philosophers and mathematicians alike that

the proofs in Geometry depended on the figure; nowadays, this is known

to be false. In the best books there are no figures at all. The

reasoning proceeds by the strict rules of formal logic from a set of

axioms laid down to begin with. If a figure is used, all sorts of

things seem obviously to follow, which no formal reasoning can prove

from the explicit axioms, and which, as a matter of fact, are only

accepted because they are obvious. By banishing the figure, it becomes

possible to discover _all_ the axioms that are needed; and in this way

all sorts of possibilities, which would have otherwise remained

undetected, are brought to light.

One great advance, from the point of view of correctness, has been

made by introducing points as they are required, and not starting, as

was formerly done, by assuming the whole of space. This method is due

partly to Peano, partly to another Italian named Fano.

To those

unaccustomed to it, it has an air of somewhat wilful pedantry. In this

way, we begin with the following axioms: (1) There is a class of

entities called _points_. (2) There is at least one point. (3) If _a_

be a point, there is at least one other point besides _a_. Then we

bring in the straight line joining two points, and begin again with

(4), namely, on the straight line joining _a_ and _b_, there is at

least one other point besides _a_ and _b_. (5) There is at least one

point not on the line _ab_. And so we go on, till we have the means of

obtaining as many points as we require. But the word _space_, as Peano

humorously remarks, is one for which Geometry has no use at all.

The rigid methods employed by modern geometers have deposed Euclid

from his pinnacle of correctness. It was thought, until recent times,

that, as Sir Henry Savile remarked in 1621, there were only two

blemishes in Euclid, the theory of parallels and the theory of

proportion. It is now known that these are almost the only points in

which Euclid is free from blemish. Countless errors are involved in

his first eight propositions. That is to say, not only is it doubtful

whether his axioms are true, which is a comparatively trivial matter,

but it is certain that his propositions do not follow from the axioms

which he enunciates. A vastly greater number of axioms, which Euclid

unconsciously employs, are required for the proof of his propositions.

Even in the first proposition of all, where he constructs an

equilateral triangle on a given base, he uses two circles which are

assumed to intersect. But no explicit axiom assures us that they do

so, and in some kinds of spaces they do not always intersect. It is

quite doubtful whether our space belongs to one of these kinds or not.

Thus Euclid fails entirely to prove his point in the very first

proposition. As he is certainly not an easy author, and is terribly

long-winded, he has no longer any but an historical interest. Under

these circumstances, it is nothing less than a scandal that he should

still be taught to boys in England.[17] A book should have either

intelligibility or correctness; to combine the two is impossible, but

to lack both is to be unworthy of such a place as Euclid has occupied

in education.

The most remarkable result of modern methods in mathematics is the

importance of symbolic logic and of rigid formalism.

Mathematicians,

under the influence of Weierstrass, have shown in modern times a care

for accuracy, and an aversion to slipshod reasoning, such as had not

been known among them previously since the time of the Greeks. The

great inventions of the seventeenth century--Analytical Geometry and

the Infinitesimal Calculus--were so fruitful in new results that

mathematicians had neither time nor inclination to examine their

foundations. Philosophers, who should have taken up the task, had too

little mathematical ability to invent the new branches of mathematics

which have now been found necessary for any adequate discussion. Thus

mathematicians were only awakened from their "dogmatic slumbers" when

Weierstrass and his followers showed that many of their most cherished

propositions are in general false. Macaulay, contrasting the certainty

of mathematics with the uncertainty of philosophy, asks who ever heard

of a reaction against Taylor's theorem? If he had lived now, he

himself might have heard of such a reaction, for this is precisely one

of the theorems which modern investigations have overthrown. Such rude

shocks to mathematical faith have produced that love of formalism

which appears, to those who are ignorant of its motive, to be mere

outrageous pedantry.

The proof that all pure mathematics, including Geometry, is nothing

but formal logic, is a fatal blow to the Kantian philosophy. Kant,

rightly perceiving that Euclid's propositions could not be deduced

from Euclid's axioms without the help of the figures, invented a

theory of knowledge to account for this fact; and it accounted so

successfully that, when the fact is shown to be a mere defect in

Euclid, and not a result of the nature of geometrical reasoning,

Kant's theory also has to be abandoned. The whole doctrine of _a

priori_ intuitions, by which Kant explained the possibility of pure

mathematics, is wholly inapplicable to mathematics in its present

form. The Aristotelian doctrines of the schoolmen come nearer in

spirit to the doctrines which modern mathematics inspire; but the

schoolmen were hampered by the fact that their formal logic was very

defective, and that the philosophical logic based upon the syllogism

showed a corresponding narrowness. What is now required is to give the

greatest possible development to mathematical logic, to allow to the

full the importance of relations, and then to found upon this secure

basis a new philosophical logic, which may hope to borrow some of the

exactitude and certainty of its mathematical foundation.

If this can

be successfully accomplished, there is every reason to hope that the

near future will be as great an epoch in pure philosophy as the

immediate past has been in the principles of mathematics. Great

triumphs inspire great hopes; and pure thought may achieve, within our

generation, such results as will place our time, in this respect, on a

level with the greatest age of Greece.[18]

FOOTNOTES:

[11] This subject is due in the main to Mr. C.S. Peirce.

[12] I ought to have added Frege, but his writings were unknown to me

when this article was written. [Note added in 1917.]

[13] Professor of Mathematics in the University of Berlin. He died in

1897.

[14] [Note added in 1917.] Although some infinite numbers are greater

than some others, it cannot be proved that of any two infinite numbers

one must be the greater.

[15] Cantor was not guilty of a fallacy on this point.

His proof that

there is no greatest number is valid. The solution of the puzzle is

complicated and depends upon the theory of types, which is explained

in _Principia Mathematica_, Vol. I (Camb. Univ. Press, 1910). [Note

added in 1917.]

[16] This must not be regarded as a historically correct account of

what Zeno actually had in mind. It is a new argument for his

conclusion, not the argument which influenced him. On this point, see

e.g. C.D. Broad, "Note on Achilles and the Tortoise,"

_Mind_, N.S.,

Vol. XXII, pp. 318-19. Much valuable work on the interpretation of

Zeno has been done since this article was written. [Note added in

1917.]

[17] Since the above was written, he has ceased to be used as a

textbook. But I fear many of the books now used are so bad that the

change is no great improvement. [Note added in 1917.]

[18] The greatest age of Greece was brought to an end by the

Peloponnesian War. [Note added in 1917.]

VI

ON SCIENTIFIC METHOD IN PHILOSOPHY

When we try to ascertain the motives which have led men to the

investigation of philosophical questions, we find that, broadly

speaking, they can be divided into two groups, often antagonistic, and

leading to very divergent systems. These two groups of motives are, on

the one hand, those derived from religion and ethics, and, on the

other hand, those derived from science. Plato, Spinoza, and Hegel may

be taken as typical of the philosophers whose interests are mainly

religious and ethical, while Leibniz, Locke, and Hume may be taken as

representatives of the scientific wing. In Aristotle, Descartes,

Berkeley, and Kant we find both groups of motives strongly present.

Herbert Spencer, in whose honour we are assembled to-day, would

naturally be classed among scientific philosophers: it was mainly from

science that he drew his data, his formulation of problems, and his

conception of method. But his strong religious sense is obvious in

much of his writing, and his ethical pre-occupations are what make him

value the conception of evolution--that conception in which, as a

whole generation has believed, science and morals are to be united in

fruitful and indissoluble marriage.

It is my belief that the ethical and religious motives in spite of

the splendidly imaginative systems to which they have given rise, have

been on the whole a hindrance to the progress of philosophy, and ought

now to be consciously thrust aside by those who wish to discover

philosophical truth. Science, originally, was entangled in similar

motives, and was thereby hindered in its advances. It is, I maintain,

from science, rather than from ethics and religion, that philosophy

should draw its inspiration.

But there are two different ways in which a philosophy may seek to

base itself upon science. It may emphasise the most general _results_

of science, and seek to give even greater generality and unity to

these results. Or it may study the _methods_ of science, and seek to

apply these methods, with the necessary adaptations, to its own

peculiar province. Much philosophy inspired by science has gone astray

through preoccupation with the _results_ momentarily supposed to have

been achieved. It is not results, but _methods_ that can be

transferred with profit from the sphere of the special sciences to the

sphere of philosophy. What I wish to bring to your notice is the

possibility and importance of applying to philosophical problems

certain broad principles of method which have been found successful in

the study of scientific questions.

The opposition between a philosophy guided by scientific method and a

philosophy dominated by religious and ethical ideas may be illustrated

by two notions which are very prevalent in the works of philosophers,

namely the notion of _the universe_, and the notion of _good and

evil_. A philosopher is expected to tell us something about the nature

of the universe as a whole, and to give grounds for either optimism or

pessimism. Both these expectations seem to me mistaken.

I believe the

conception of "the universe" to be, as its etymology indicates, a

mere relic of pre-Copernican astronomy: and I believe the question of

optimism and pessimism to be one which the philosopher will regard as

outside his scope, except, possibly, to the extent of maintaining that

it is insoluble.

In the days before Copernicus, the conception of the

"universe" was

defensible on scientific grounds: the diurnal revolution of the

heavenly bodies bound them together as all parts of one system, of

which the earth was the centre. Round this apparent scientific fact,

many human desires rallied: the wish to believe Man important in the

scheme of things, the theoretical desire for a comprehensive

understanding of the Whole, the hope that the course of nature might

be guided by some sympathy with our wishes. In this way, an ethically

inspired system of metaphysics grew up, whose anthropocentrism was

apparently warranted by the geocentrism of astronomy.

When Copernicus

swept away the astronomical basis of this system of thought, it had

grown so familiar, and had associated itself so intimately with men's

aspirations, that it survived with scarcely diminished force--survived

even Kant's "Copernican revolution," and is still now the unconscious

premiss of most metaphysical systems.

The oneness of the world is an almost undiscussed postulate of most

metaphysics. "Reality is not merely one and self-consistent, but is a

system of reciprocally determinate parts"[19]--such a statement would

pass almost unnoticed as a mere truism. Yet I believe that it embodies

a failure to effect thoroughly the "Copernican revolution," and that

the apparent oneness of the world is merely the oneness of what is

seen by a single spectator or apprehended by a single mind. The

Critical Philosophy, although it intended to emphasise the subjective

element in many apparent characteristics of the world, yet, by

regarding the world in itself as unknowable, so concentrated attention

upon the subjective representation that its subjectivity was soon

forgotten. Having recognised the categories as the work of the mind,

it was paralysed by its own recognition, and abandoned in despair the

attempt to undo the work of subjective falsification. In part, no

doubt, its despair was well founded, but not, I think, in any absolute

or ultimate sense. Still less was it a ground for rejoicing, or for

supposing that the nescience to which it ought to have given rise

could be legitimately exchanged for a metaphysical dogmatism.

I

As regards our present question, namely, the question of the unity of

the world, the right method, as I think, has been indicated by William

James.[20] "Let us now turn our backs upon ineffable or unintelligible

ways of accounting for the world's oneness, and inquire whether,

instead of being a principle, the 'oneness' affirmed may not merely be

a name like 'substance' descriptive of the fact that certain _specific

and verifiable connections_ are found among the parts of the

experiential flux.... We can easily conceive of things that shall have

no connection whatever with each other. We may assume them to inhabit

different times and spaces, as the dreams of different persons do even

now. They may be so unlike and incommensurable, and so inert towards

one another, as never to jostle or interfere. Even now there may

actually be whole universes so disparate from ours that we who know

ours have no means of perceiving that they exist. We conceive their

diversity, however; and by that fact the whole lot of them form what

is known in logic as 'a universe of discourse.' To form a universe of

discourse argues, as this example shows, no further kind of connexion.

The importance attached by certain monistic writers to the fact that

any chaos may become a universe by merely being named, is to me

incomprehensible." We are thus left with two kinds of unity in the

experienced world; the one what we may call the epistemological unity,

due merely to the fact that my experienced world is what _one_

experience selects from the sum total of existence: the other that

tentative and partial unity exhibited in the prevalence of scientific

laws in those portions of the world which science has hitherto

mastered. Now a generalisation based upon either of these kinds of

unity would be fallacious. That the things which we experience have

the common property of being experienced by us is a truism from which

obviously nothing of importance can be deducible: it is clearly

fallacious to draw from the fact that whatever we experience is

experienced the conclusion that therefore everything must be

experienced. The generalisation of the second kind of unity, namely,

that derived from scientific laws, would be equally fallacious, though

the fallacy is a trifle less elementary. In order to explain it let us

consider for a moment what is called the reign of law.

People often

speak as though it were a remarkable fact that the physical world is

subject to invariable laws. In fact, however, it is not easy to see

how such a world could fail to obey general laws. Taking any arbitrary

set of points in space, there is a function of the time corresponding

to these points, i.e. expressing the motion of a particle which

traverses these points: this function may be regarded as a general law

to which the behaviour of such a particle is subject.

Taking all such

functions for all the particles in the universe, there will be

theoretically some one formula embracing them all, and this formula

may be regarded as the single and supreme law of the spatio-temporal

world. Thus what is surprising in physics is not the existence of

general laws, but their extreme simplicity. It is not the uniformity

of nature that should surprise us, for, by sufficient analytic

ingenuity, any conceivable course of nature might be shown to exhibit

uniformity. What should surprise us is the fact that the uniformity is

simple enough for us to be able to discover it. But it is just this

characteristic of simplicity in the laws of nature hitherto discovered

which it would be fallacious to generalise, for it is obvious that

simplicity has been a part cause of their discovery, and can,

therefore, give no ground for the supposition that other undiscovered

laws are equally simple.

The fallacies to which these two kinds of unity have given rise

suggest a caution as regards all use in philosophy of general

_results_ that science is supposed to have achieved. In the first

place, in generalising these results beyond past experience, it is

necessary to examine very carefully whether there is not some reason

making it more probable that these results should hold of all that has

been experienced than that they should hold of things universally. The

sum total of what is experienced by mankind is a selection from the

sum total of what exists, and any general character exhibited by this

selection may be due to the manner of selecting rather than to the

general character of that from which experience selects.

In the second

place, the most general results of science are the least certain and

the most liable to be upset by subsequent research. In utilizing these

results as the basis of a philosophy, we sacrifice the most valuable

and remarkable characteristic of scientific method, namely, that,

although almost everything in science is found sooner or later to

require some correction, yet this correction is almost always such as

to leave untouched, or only slightly modified, the greater part of the

results which have been deduced from the premiss subsequently

discovered to be faulty. The prudent man of science acquires a certain

instinct as to the kind of uses which may be made of present

scientific beliefs without incurring the danger of complete and utter

refutation from the modifications likely to be introduced by

subsequent discoveries. Unfortunately the use of scientific

generalisations of a sweeping kind as the basis of philosophy is just

that kind of use which an instinct of scientific caution would avoid,

since, as a rule, it would only lead to true results if the

generalisation upon which it is based stood in _no_ need of

correction.

We may illustrate these general considerations by means of two

examples, namely, the conservation of energy and the principle of

evolution.

(1) Let us begin with the conservation of energy, or, as Herbert

Spencer used to call it, the persistence of force. He says:[21]

"Before taking a first step in the rational interpretation of

Evolution, it is needful to recognise, not only the facts that

Matter is indestructible and Motion continuous, but also the fact

that Force persists. An attempt to assign the _causes_

of

Evolution would manifestly be absurd if that agency to which the

metamorphosis in general and in detail is due, could either come

into existence or cease to exist. The succession of phenomena

would in such case be altogether arbitrary, and deductive Science

impossible."

This paragraph illustrates the kind of way in which the philosopher is

tempted to give an air of absoluteness and necessity to empirical

generalisations, of which only the approximate truth in the regions

hitherto investigated can be guaranteed by the unaided methods of

science. It is very often said that the persistence of something or

other is a necessary presupposition of all scientific investigation,

and this presupposition is then thought to be exemplified in some

quantity which physics declares to be constant. There are here, as it

seems to me, three distinct errors. First, the detailed scientific

investigation of nature does not _presuppose_ any such general laws as

its results are found to verify. Apart from particular observations,

science need presuppose nothing except the general principles of

logic, and these principles are not laws of nature, for they are

merely hypothetical, and apply not only to the actual world but to

whatever is _possible_. The second error consists in the identification of a constant quantity with a persistent entity. Energy

is a certain function of a physical system, but is not a thing or

substance persisting throughout the changes of the system. The same is

true of mass, in spite of the fact that mass has often been defined as

_quantity of matter_. The whole conception of quantity, involving, as

it does, numerical measurement based largely upon conventions, is far

more artificial, far more an embodiment of mathematical convenience,

than is commonly believed by those who philosophise on physics. Thus

even if (which I cannot for a moment admit) the persistence of some

entity were among the necessary postulates of science, it would be a

sheer error to infer from this the constancy of any physical quantity,

or the _a priori_ necessity of any such constancy which may be

empirically discovered. In the third place, it has become more and