The making of religion by Andrew Lang. - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION

'The only begetter' of this work is Monsieur Lefebure, author of 'Les

Yeux d'Horus,' and other studies in Egyptology. He suggested the writing

of the book, but is in no way responsible for the opinions expressed.

The author cannot omit the opportunity of thanking Mr. Frederic Myers for

his kindness in reading the proof sheets of the earlier chapters and

suggesting some corrections of statement. Mr. Myers, however, is probably

not in agreement with the author on certain points; for example, in

the chapter on 'Possession.' As the second part of the book differs

considerably from the opinions which have recommended themselves to most

anthropological writers on early Religion, the author must say here, as he says later, that no harm can come of trying how facts look from a new

point of view, and that he certainly did not expect them to fall into the

shape which he now presents for criticism.

ST. ANDREWS: _April 3, 1898._

CONTENTS

I. INTRODUCTORY CHAPTER

II. SCIENCE AND 'MIRACLES'

III. ANTHROPOLOGY AND RELIGION

IV. 'OPENING THE GATES OF DISTANCE'

V. CRYSTAL VISIONS, SAVAGE AND CIVILISED

VI. ANTHROPOLOGY AND HALLUCINATIONS

VII. DEMONIACAL POSSESSION

VIII. FETISHISM AND SPIRITUALISM

IX. EVOLUTION OF THE IDEA OF GOD

X. HIGH GODS OF LOW RACES

XI. SUPREME GODS NOT NECESSARILY DEVELOPED OUT OF 'SPIRITS'

XII. SAVAGE SUPREME BEINGS

XIII. MORE SAVAGE SUPREME BEINGS

XIV. AHONE. TI-RA-WA. NA-PI. PACHACAMAC. TUI LAGA. TAA-ROA

XV. THE OLD DEGENERATION THEORY

XVI. THEORIES OF JEHOVAH

XVII. CONCLUSION

APPENDICES.

A. OPPOSITIONS OF SCIENCE

B. THE POLTERGEIST AND HIS EXPLAINERS

C. CRYSTAL-GAZING

D. CHIEFS IN AUSTRALIA

INDEX

* * * * *

THE MAKING OF RELIGION

I

_INTRODUCTORY CHAPTER_

The modern Science of the History of Religion has attained conclusions

which already possess an air of being firmly established. These

conclusions may be briefly stated thus: Man derived the conception of

'spirit' or 'soul' from his reflections on the phenomena of sleep, dreams, death, shadow, and from the experiences of trance and hallucination.

Worshipping first the departed souls of his kindred, man later extended

the doctrine of spiritual beings in many directions. Ghosts, or other

spiritual existences fashioned on the same lines, prospered till they

became gods. Final y, as the result of a variety of processes, one of

these gods became supreme, and, at last, was regarded as the one only God.

Meanwhile man retained his belief in the existence of his own soul,

surviving after the death of the body, and so reached the conception of

immortality. Thus the ideas of God and of the soul are the result of early fal acious reasonings about misunderstood experiences.

It may seem almost wanton to suggest the desirableness of revising a

system at once so simple, so logical, and apparently so wel bottomed on

facts. But there can never be any real harm in studying masses of evidence from fresh points of view. At worst, the failure of adverse criticism must help to establish the doctrines assailed. Now, as we shal show, there are two points of view from which the evidence as to religion in its early

stages has not been steadily contemplated. Therefore we intend to ask,

first, what, if anything, can be ascertained as to the nature of the

'visions' and hal ucinations which, according to Mr. Tylor in his

celebrated work 'Primitive Culture,' lent their aid to the formation of

the idea of 'spirit.' Secondly, we shall col ect and compare the accounts

which we possess of the High Gods and creative beings worshipped or

believed in, by the most backward races. We shall then ask whether these

relatively Supreme Beings, so conceived of by men in very rudimentary

social conditions, can be, as anthropology declares, mere developments

from the belief in ghosts of the dead.

We shall end by venturing to suggest that the savage theory of the soul

may be based, at least in part, on experiences which cannot, at present,

be made to fit into any purely materialistic system of the universe. We

shal also bring evidence tending to prove that the idea of God, in its

earliest known shape, need not logically be derived from the idea of

spirit, however that idea itself may have been attained or evolved. The

conception of God, then, need not be evolved out of reflections on dreams

and 'ghosts.'

If these two positions can be defended with any success, it is obvious

that the whole theory of the Science of Religion will need to be

reconsidered. But it is no less evident that our two positions do not

depend on each other. The first may be regarded as fantastic, or

improbable, or may be 'masked' and left on one side. But the strength of

the second position, derived from evidence of a different character, will

not, therefore, be in any way impaired. Our first position can only be

argued for by dint of evidence highly unpopular in character, and, as a

general rule, condemned by modern science. The evidence is obtained by

what is, at all events, a legitimate anthropological proceeding. We may

fol ow Mr. Tylor's example, and collect savage _beliefs_ about visions,

hal ucinations, 'clairvoyance,' and the acquisition of knowledge

apparently not attainable through the normal channels of sense. We may

then compare these savage beliefs with attested records of similar

_experiences_ among living and educated civilised men. Even if we attain

to no conclusion, or a negative conclusion, as to the actuality and

supernormal character of the alleged experiences, still to compare data of savage and civilised psychology, or even of savage and civilised illusions and fables, is decidedly part, though a neglected part, of the function of anthropological science. The results, whether they do or do not strengthen our first position, must be curious and instructive, if only as a chapter

in the history of human error. That chapter, too, is concerned with no

mean topic, but with what we may cal the X region of our nature. Out of

that region, out of miracle, prophecy, vision, have certainly come forth

the great religions, Christianity and Islam; and the great religious

innovators and leaders, our Lord Himself, St. Francis, John Knox, Jeanne

d'Arc, down to the founder of the new faith of the Sioux and Arapahoe. It

cannot, then, be unscientific to compare the barbaric with the civilised

beliefs and experiences about a region so dimly understood, and so fertile in potent influences. Here the topic will be examined rather by the method of anthropology than of psychology. We may conceivably have something to

learn (as has been the case before) from the rough observations and hasty

inferences of the most backward races.

We may illustrate this by an anecdote:

'The Northern Indians cal the _Aurora Borealis_ "Edthin," that is "Deer."

Their ideas in this respect are founded on a principle one would not

imagine. Experience has shown them that when a hairy deer-skin is briskly

stroked with the hand on a dark night, it will emit many sparks of

electrical fire.'

So says Hearne in his 'Journey,' published in 1795 (p. 346).

This observation of the Red Men is a kind of parable representing a part

of the purport of the fol owing treatise. The Indians, making a hasty

inference from a trivial phenomenon, arrived unawares at a probably

correct conclusion, long unknown to civilised science. They connected the

Aurora Borealis with electricity, supposing that multitudes of deer

in the sky rubbed the sparks out of each other! Meanwhile, even in

the last century, a puzzled populace spoke of the phenomenon as 'Lord

Derwentwater's Lights.' The cosmic pomp and splendour shone to welcome the loyal Derwentwater into heaven, when he had given his life for his exiled

king.

Now, my purpose in the earlier portion of this essay is to suggest that

certain phenomena of human nature, apparently as trivial as the sparks

rubbed out of a deer's hide in a dark night, may indicate, and may be

allied to a force or forces, which, like the Aurora Borealis, may shine

from one end of the heavens to the other, strangely illumining the

darkness of our destiny. Such phenomena science has ignored, as it so long ignored the sparks from the stroked deer-skin, and the attractive power of rubbed amber. These trivial things were not known to be al ied to the

lightning, or to indicate a force which man could tame and use. But just

as the Indians, by a rapid careless inference, attributed the Aurora

Borealis to electric influences, so (as anthropology assures us) savages

everywhere have inferred the existence of soul or spirit, intelligence

that

'Does not know the bond of Time,

Nor wear the manacles of Space,'

in part from certain apparently trivial phenomena of human faculty. These

phenomena, as Mr. Tylor says, 'the great intellectual movement of the last two centuries has simply thrown aside as worthless.'[1] I refer to al eged experiences, merely odd, sporadic, and, for commercial purposes, useless,

such as the transference of thought from one mind to another by no known

channel of sense, the occurrence of hallucinations which, _prima facie_,

correspond coincidental y with unknown events at a distance, all that is

called 'second sight,' or 'clairvoyance,' and other things even more

obscure. Reasoning on these real or al eged phenomena, and on other quite

normal and accepted facts of dream, shadow, sleep, trance, and death,

savages have inferred the existence of spirit or soul, exactly as the

Indians arrived at the notion of electricity (not so called by them, of

course) as the cause of the Aurora Borealis. But, just as the Indians

thought that the cosmic lights were caused by the rubbing together of

crowded deer in the heavens (a theory quite childishly absurd), so the

savage has expressed, in rude fantastic ways, his conclusion as to the

existence of spirit. He believes in wandering separable souls of men,

surviving death, and he has peopled with his dreams the whole inanimate

universe.

My suggestion is that, in spite of his fantasies, the savage had possibly

drawn from his premises an inference not wholly, or not demonstrably

erroneous. As the sparks of the deer-skin indicated electricity, so the

strange lights in the night of human nature may indicate faculties which

science, till of late and in a few instances, has laughed at, ignored,

'thrown aside as worthless.'

It should be observed that I am not speaking of 'spiritualism,' a word of

the worst associations, inextricably entangled with fraud, bad logic, and

the blindest credulity. Some of the phenomena al uded to have, however,

been claimed as their own province by 'spiritists,' and need to be rescued from them. Mr. Tylor writes:

'The issue raised by the comparison of savage, barbaric, and civilised

spiritualism is this: Do the Red Indian medicine-man, the Tatar

necromancer, the Highland ghost-seer, and the Boston medium, share the

possession of belief and knowledge of the highest truth and import,

which, nevertheless, the great intellectual movement of the last two

centuries has simply thrown aside as worthless?'

_Distinguo!_ That does not seem to me to be the issue. In my opinion the

issue is: 'Have the Red Indian, the Tatar, the Highland seer, and the

Boston medium (the least reputable of the menagerie) observed, and

reasoned wildly from, and counterfeited, and darkened with imposture,

certain genuine by-products of human faculty, which do not _prima facie_

deserve to be thrown aside?'

That, I venture to think, is the real issue. That science may toss aside

as worthless some valuable observations of savages is now universally

admitted by people who know the facts. Among these observations is the

whole topic of Hypnotism, with the use of suggestion for healing purposes, and the phenomena, no longer denied, of 'alternating personalities.' For

the truth of this statement we may appeal to one of the greatest of

Continental anthropologists, Adolf Bastian.[2] The missionaries, like

Livingstone, usual y supposed that the savage seer's declared ignorance--

after his so-called fit of inspiration--of what occurred in that state,

was an imposture. But nobody now doubts the similar oblivion of what has

passed that sometimes fol ows the analogous hypnotic sleep. Of a

remarkable cure, which the school of the Salpetriere or Nancy would

ascribe, with probable justice, to 'suggestion,' a savage example will be

given later.

Savage hypnotism and 'suggestion,' among the Sioux and Arapahoe, has been

thought worthy of a whole volume in the Reports of the Ethnological Bureau of the Smithsonian Institute (Washington, U.S., 1892-98). Republican

Governments publish scientific matter 'regardless of expense,' and the

essential points might have been put more shortly. They illustrate the

fact that only certain persons can hypnotise others, and throw light on

some peculiarities of _rapport._[3] In brief, savages anticipated us in

the modern science of experimental psychology, as is frankly acknowledged

by the Society for Experimental Psychology of Berlin. 'That many mystical

phenomena are much more common and prominent among savages than among

ourselves is familiar to everyone acquainted with the subject. The

_ethnological_ side of our inquiry demands penetrative study.'[4]

That study I am about to try to sketch. My object is to examine some

'superstitious practices' and beliefs of savages by aid of the comparative method. I shal compare, as I have already said, the ethnological evidence for savage usages and beliefs analogous to thought-transference,

coincidental hallucinations, alternating personality, and so forth, with

the best attested modern examples, experimental or spontaneous. This

raises the question of our evidence, which is al -important. We proceed to defend it. The savage accounts are on the level of much anthropological

evidence; they may, that is, be dismissed by adversaries as 'travel ers'

tales.' But the best testimony for the truth of the reports as to actual

belief in the facts is the undesigned coincidence of evidence from al

ages and quarters.[5] When the stories brought by travel ers, ancient and

modern, learned and unlearned, pious or sceptical, agree in the main, we

have al the certainty that anthropology can offer. Again, when we find

practical y the same strange neglected sparks, not only rumoured of

in European popular superstition, but attested in many hundreds of

depositions made at first hand by respectable modern witnesses, educated

and responsible, we cannot honestly or safely dismiss the coincidence of

report as indicating a mere 'survival' of savage superstitious belief, and nothing more.

We can no longer do so, it is agreed, in the case of hypnotic phenomena. I hope to make it seem possible that we should not do so in the matter of

the hallucinations provoked by gazing in a smooth deep, usual y styled

'crystal-gazing.' Ethnologically, this practice is at least as old as

classical times, and is of practically world-wide distribution. I shal

prove its existence in Australia, New Zealand, North America, South

America, Asia, Africa, Polynesia, and among the Incas, not to speak of

the middle and recent European ages. The universal idea is that such

visions may be 'clairvoyant.' To take a Polynesian case, 'resembling the

Hawaiian _wai harru_.' When anyone has been robbed, the priest, after

praying, has a hole dug in the floor of the house, and filled with water.

Then he gazes into the water, 'over which the god is supposed to place the spirit of the thief.... The image of the thief was, according to their

account, reflected in the water, and being perceived by the priest, he

named the individual, or the parties.'[6] Here the statement about the

'spirit' is a mere savage philosophical explanation. But the fact that

hal ucinatory pictures can really be seen by a fair percentage of educated Europeans, in water, glass bal s, and so forth, is now confirmed by

frequent experiment, and accepted by opponents, 'non-mystical writers,'

like Dr. Parish of Munich.[7] I shal bring evidence to suggest that the

visions may correctly reflect, as it were, persons and places absolutely

unknown to the gazer, and that they may even reveal details unknown to

every one present. Such results among savages, or among the superstitious, would be, and are, explained by the theory of 'spirits.' Modern science

has still to find an explanation consistent with recognised laws of

nature, but 'spirits' we shall not invoke.

In the same way I mean to examine al or most of the 'so-called mystical

phenomena of savage life.' I then compare them with the better vouched for modern examples. To return to the question of evidence, I confess that I

do not see how the adverse anthropologist, psychologist, or popular

agnostic is to evade the fol owing dilemma: To the anthropologist we say,

'The evidence we adduce is your own evidence, that of books of travel in

all lands and countries. If _you_ may argue from it, so may we. Some

of it is evidence to unusual facts, more of it is evidence to singular

beliefs, which we think not necessarily without foundation. As raising a

presumption in favour of that opinion, we cite examples in which savage

observations of abnormal and once rejected facts, are now admitted by

science to have a large residuum of truth, we argue that what is admitted

in some cases may come to be admitted in more. No _a priori_ line can here be drawn.'

To the psychologist who objects that our modern instances are mere

anecdotes, we reply by asking, 'Dear sir, what are _your_ modern

instances? What do you know of "Mrs. A.," whom you still persistently cite as an example of morbid recurrent hallucinations? Name the German

servant girl who, in a fever, talked several learned languages, which she

had heard her former master, a scholar, declaim! Where did she live? Who

vouches for her, who heard her, who understood her? There is, you know, no evidence at al ; the anecdote is told by Coleridge: the phenomena are said by him to have been observed "in a Roman Catholic town in Germany, a year or two before my arrival at Goettingen.... Many eminent physiologists and

psychologists visited the town." Why do you not name a few out of the distinguished crowd?'[8] This anecdote, a rumour of a rumour of a

Protestant explanation of a Catholic marvel, was told by Coleridge at

least twenty years after the possible date. The psychologists copy it,[9]

one after the other, as a flock of sheep jump where their leader has

jumped. An example by way of anecdote may be permitted.

According to the current anthropological theory, the idea of soul or

spirit was suggested to early men by their experiences in dreams. They

seemed, in sleep, to visit remote places; therefore, they argued,

something within them was capable of leaving the body and wandering about.

This something was the soul or spirit. Now it is obvious that this opinion of early men would be confirmed if they ever chanced to acquire, in

dreams, knowledge of places which they had never visited, and of facts as

to which, in their waking state, they could have no information. This

experience, indeed, would suggest problems even To Mr. Herbert Spencer, if it occurred to him.

Conversing on this topic with a friend of acknowledged philosophical

eminence, I illustrated my meaning by a story of a dream. It was reported

to me by the dreamer, with whom I am well acquainted, was of very recent

occurrence, and was corroborated by the evidence of another person, to

whom the dream was narrated, before its fulfilment was discovered. I am

not at liberty to publish the details, for good reasons, but the essence

of the matter was this: A. and B. (the dreamer) had common interests. A.

had taken certain steps about which B. had only a surmise, and a vague

one, that steps had probably been taken. A. then died, and B. in an

extremely vivid dream (a thing unfamiliar to him) seemed to read a mass of unknown facts, culminating in two definite results, capable of being

stated in figures. These results, by the very nature of the case, could

not be known to A., so that, before he was placed out of B.'s reach by

death, he could not have stated them to him, and, afterwards, had

assuredly no means of doing so.

The dream, two days after its occurrence, and after it had been told to

C., proved to be literally correct. Now I am not asking the reader's

belief for this anecdote (for that could only be yielded in virtue of

knowledge of the veracity of B. and C.), but I invite his attention to the psychological explanation. My friend suggested that A. had told B. al

about the affair, that B. had not listened (though his interests were

vital y concerned), and that the crowd of curious details, natural y

unfamiliar to B., had reposed in his subconscious memory, and had been

revived in the dream.

Now B.'s dream was a dream of reading a mass of minute details, including

names of places entirely unknown to him. It may be admitted, in accordance with the psychological theory, that B. might have received al this

information from A., but, by dint of inattention--'the malady of not

marking'--might never have been _consciously_ aware of what he heard. Then B.'s subconscious memory of what he did not _consciously_ know might break upon him in his dream. Instances of similar mental phenomena are not

uncommon. But the general result of the combined details was one which

could not possibly be known to A. before his death; nor to B. could it be

known at all. Yet B.'s dream represented this general result with perfect

accuracy, which cannot be accounted for by the revival of subconscious

memory in sleep. Neither asleep nor awake can a man remember what it is

impossible for him to have known. The dream contained no _prediction_ for

the results were now fixed; but (granting the good faith of the narrator)

the dream did contain information not normal y accessible.

However, by way of psychological explanation of the dream, my friend cited Coleridge's legend, as to the German girl and her unconscious knowledge of certain learned languages. 'And what is the evidence for the truth of

Coleridge's legend?' Of course, there is none, or none known to al the

psychologists who quote it from Coleridge. Neither, if true, was the

legend to the point. However, psychology will accept such unauthenticated

narratives, and yet will scoff at first baud, duly corroborated testimony

from living and honourable people, about recent events.

Only a great force of prejudice can explain this acceptance, by

psychologists, of one kind of marvel ous tale on no evidence, and this

rejection of another class of marvel ous tale, when supported by first

hand, signed and corroborated evidence, of living witnesses. I see only

one escape for psychologists from this dilemma. Their marvel ous tales are _possible_, though unvouched for, because they have always heard them and

repeated them in lectures, and read and repeated them in books. _Our_

marvel ous tales are impossible, because the psychologists know that they

are impossible, which means that they have not been familiar with them,

from youth upwards, in lectures and manuals. But man has no right to have

'clear ideas of the possible and impossible,' like Faraday, _a priori_,

except in the exact sciences. There are other instances of weak evidence

which satisfies psychologists.

Hamilton has an anecdote, borrowed from Monboddo, who got it from Mr. Hans Stanley, who, 'about twenty-six years ago,' heard it from the subject of

the story, Madame de Laval. 'I have the memorandum somewhere in my

papers,' says Mr. Stanley, vaguely. Then we have two American anecdotes by Dr. Flint and Mr. Rush; and such is Sir William Hamilton's equipment of

odd facts for discussing the unconscious or subconscious. The least

credible and worst attested of these narratives still appears in popular

works on psychology. Moreover, al psychology, except experimental

psychology, is based on anecdotes which people tel about their own

subjective experiences. Mr. Galton, whose original researches are wel

known, even offered rewards in money for such narratives about visualised

rows of coloured figures, and so on.

Clearly the psychologist, then, has no _prima facie_ right to object to

our anecdotes of experiences, which he regards as purely subjective. As

evidence, we only accept them at first hand, and, when possible, the

witnesses have been cross-examined personal y. Our evidence then, where it consists of travellers' tales, is on a level with that which satisfies the anthropologist. Where it consists of modern statements of personal

experience, our evidence is often infinitely better than much which is

accepted by the nonexperimental psychologist. As for the agnostic writer

on the No