The Human Condition by Hannah Arendt - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

by a promise made only to himself; forgiving and promising en-

acted in solitude or isolation remain without reality and can signify

no more than a role played before one's self.

Since these faculties correspond so closely to the human condi-

tion of plurality, their role in politics establishes a diametrically

different set of guiding principles from the "moral" standards in-

herent in the Platonic notion of rule. For Platonic rulership, whose

legitimacy rested upon the domination of the self, draws its guiding

principles—those which at the same time justify and limit power

over others—from a relationship established between me and my-

self, so that the right and wrong of relationships with others are

[ 237 ]

The Human Condition

determined by attitudes toward one's self, until the whole of the

public realm is seen in the image of "man writ large," of the right

order between man's individual capacities of mind, soul, and body.

The moral code, on the other hand, inferred from the faculties of

forgiving and of. making promises, rests on experiences which no-

body could ever have with himself, which, on the contrary, are

entirely based on the presence of others. And just as the extent and

modes of self-rule justify and determine rule over others—how one

rules himself, he will rule others—thus the extent and modes of

being forgiven and being promised determine the extent and modes

in which one may be able to forgive himself or keep promises

concerned only with himself.

Because the remedies against the enormous strength and resili-

ency inherent in action processes can function only under the con-

dition of plurality, it is very dangerous to use this faculty in any

but the realm of human affairs. Modern natural science and tech-

nology, which no longer observe or take material from or imitate

processes of nature but seem actually to act into it, seem, by the

same token, to have carried irreversibility and human unpredicta-

bility into the natural realm, where no remedy can be found to

undo what has been done. Similarly, it seems that one of the great

dangers of acting in the mode of making and within its categorical

framework of means and ends lies in the concomitant self-depriva-

tion of the remedies inherent only in action, so that one is bound

not only to do with the means of violence necessary for all fabrica-

tion, but also to undo what he has done as he undoes an unsuccessful

object, by means of destruction. Nothing appears more manifest in

these attempts than the greatness of human power, whose source

lies in the capacity to act, and which without action's inherent

remedies inevitably begins to overpower and destroy not man

himself but the conditions under which life was given to him.

The discoverer of the role of forgiveness in the realm of human

affairs was Jesus of Nazareth. The fact that he made this discovery

in a religious context and articulated it in religious language is no

reason to take it any less seriously in a strictly secular sense. It has

been in the nature of our tradition of political thought (and for

reasons we cannot explore here) to be highly selective and to ex-

clude from articulate conceptualization a great variety of authentic

[ 23S ]

Action

political experiences, among which we need not be surprised to

find some of an even elementary nature. Certain aspects of the

teaching of Jesus of Nazareth which are not primarily related to

the Christian religious message but sprang from experiences in the

small and closely knit community of his followers, bent on chal-

lenging the public authorities in Israel, certainly belong among

them, even though they have been neglected because of their al-

legedly exclusively religious nature. The only rudimentary sign of

an awareness that forgiveness may be the necessary corrective for

the inevitable damages resulting from action may be seen in the

Roman principle to spare the vanquished (parcere subiectis)—a wis-

dom entirely unknown to the Greeks—or in the right to commute

the death sentence, probably also of Roman origin, which is the

prerogative of nearly all Western heads of state.

It is decisive in our context that Jesus maintains against the

"scribes and pharisees" first that it is not true that only God has

the power to forgive,76 and second that this power does not derive

from God—as though God, not men, would forgive through the

medium of human beings—but on the contrary must be mobilized

by men toward each other before they can hope to be forgiven by

Crod also. Jesus' formulation is even more radical. Man in the

gospel is not supposed to forgive because God forgives and he

must do "likewise," but "if ye from your hearts forgive," God

shall do "likewise."77 The reason for the insistence on a duty to

forgive is clearly "for they know not what they do" and it does

not apply to the extremity of crime and willed evil, for then it

would not have been necessary to teach: "And if he trespass

76. This is seated emphatically in Luke 5:21-24 (cf. Matt. 9:4—6 or Mark

12:7-10), where Jesus performs a miracle to prove that "the Son of man hath

power upon earth to forgive sins," the emphasis being on "upon earth." It is his insistence on the "power to forgive," even more than his performance of miracles, that shocks the people, so that "they that sat at meat with him began to say

within themselves, Who is this that forgives sins also?" (Luke 7:49).

77. Matt. 18:35; cf. Mark 11;25; "And when ye stand praying, forgive, . . .

that your Father also which is in heaven may forgive you your trespasses." Or:

"If ye forgive men their trespasses, your heavenly Father will also forgive you: But if ye forgive not men their trespasses, neither will your Father forgive your

trespasses" (Matt. 6:14-15). In all these instances, the power to forgive is primarily a human power: God forgives "us our debts, as we forgive our debtors."

[ 239 ]

The Human Condition

against thee seven times a day, and seven times in a day turn again

to thee, saying, I repent; thou shalt forgive him."78 Crime and

willed evil are rare, even rarer perhaps than good deeds; according

to Jesus, they will be taken care of by God in the Last Judgment,

which plays no role whatsoever in life on earth, and the Last Judg-

ment is not characterized by forgiveness but by just retribution

(apodounai) ,79 But trespassing is an everyday occurrence which is in

the very nature of action's constant establishment of new relation-

ships within a web of relations, and it needs forgiving, dismissing,

in order to make it possible for life to go on by constantly releasing

men from what they have done unknowingly.80 Only through this

constant mutual release from what they do can men remain free

agents, only by constant willingness to change their minds and

start again can they be trusted with so great a power as that to

begin something new.

In this respect, forgiveness is the exact opposite of vengeance,

which acts in the form of re-acting against an original trespassing,

whereby far from putting an end to the consequences of the first

misdeed, everybody remains bound to the process, permitting the

chain reaction contained in every action to take its unhindered

78. Luke 17 : 3^4. It is important to keep in mind that the three key words of

the text— aphienai, metanoein, and hamartanein—carry certain connotations even in New Testament Greek which the translations fail to render fully. The original

meaning of aphienai is "dismiss" and "release" rather than "forgive"; metanoein means "change of mind" and—since it serves also to render the Hebrew shuv

"return," "trace back one's steps," rather than "repentance" with its psychological emotional overtones; what is required is: change your mind and "sin no

more," which is almost the opposite of doing penance. Hamartanein, finally, is indeed very well rendered by "trespassing" in so far as it means rather "to miss,"

"fail and go astray," than "to sin" (see Heinrich Ebeling, Griechisch-deutsches Worterbuch zum Neuen Testamente [1923]). The verse which I quote in the standard translation could also be rendered as follows: "And if he trespass against

thee . . . and . . . turn again to thee, saying, / changed my mind; thou shalt release him."

79. Matt. 16:27.

80. This interpretation seems justified by the context (Luke 17:1-5): Jesus

introduces his words by pointing to the inevitability of "offenses" (skandala) which are unforgivable, at least on earth; for "woe unto him, through whom they come! It were better for him that a millstone were hanged about his neck, and he

cast into the sea"; and then continues by teaching forgiveness for "trespassing"

(hamartanein).

[ 240 )

Action

course. In contrast to revenge, which is the natural, automatic re-

action to transgression and which because of the irreversibility of

the action process can be expected and even calculated, the act of

forgiving can never be predicted; it is the only reaction that acts in

an unexpected way and thus retains, though being a reaction, some-

thing of the original character of action. Forgiving, in other words,

is the only reaction which does not merely re-act but acts anew and

unexpectedly, unconditioned by the act which provoked it and

therefore freeing from its consequences both the one who forgives

and the one who is forgiven. The freedom contained in Jesus' teach-

ings of forgiveness is the freedom from vengeance, which incloses

both doer and sufferer in the relentless automatism of the action

process, which by itself need never come to an end.

The alternative to forgiveness, but by no means its opposite, is

punishment, and both have in common that they attempt to put an

end to something that without interference could go on endlessly.

It is therefore quite significant, a structural element in the realm of

human affairs, that men are unable to forgive what they cannot

punish and that they are unable to punish what has turned out to be

unforgivable. This is the true hallmark of those offenses which,

since Kant, we call "radical evil" and about whose nature so little

is known, even to us who have been exposed to one of their rare

outbursts on the public scene. All we know is that we can neither

punish nor forgive such offenses and that they therefore transcend

the realm of human affairs and the potentialities of human power,

both of which they radically destroy wherever they make their

appearance. Here, where the deed itself dispossesses us of all

power, we can indeed only repeat with Jesus: "It were better for

him that a millstone were hanged about his neck, and he cast into

the sea."

Perhaps the most plausible argument that forgiving and acting

are as closely connected as destroying and making comes from that

aspect of forgiveness where the undoing of what was done seems

to show the same revelatory character as the deed itself. Forgiving

and the relationship it establishes is always an eminently personal

(though not necessarily individual or private) affair in which what

was done is forgiven for the sake of who did it. This, too, was

clearly recognized by Jesus ("Her sins which are many are for-

[ 241 ]

The Human Condition

given; for she loved much: but to whom little is forgiven, the

same loveth little"), and it is the reason for the current conviction

that only love has the power to forgive. For love, although it is one

of the rarest occurrences in human lives,81 indeed possesses an

unequaled power of self-revelation and an unequaled clarity of

vision for the disclosure of who, precisely because it is uncon-

cerned to the point of total unworldliness with what the loved per-

son may be, with his qualities and shortcomings no less than with

his achievements, failings, and transgressions. Love, by reason of

its passion, destroys the in-between which relates us to and sepa-

rates us from others. As long as its spell lasts, the only in-between

which can insert itself between two lovers is the child, love's own

product. The child, this in-between to which the lovers now are

related and which they hold in common, is representative of the

world in that it also separates them; it is an indication that they

will insert a new world into the existing world.82 Through the

child, it is as though the lovers return to the world from which

their love had expelled them. But this new worldliness, the pos-

sible result and the only possibly happy ending of a love affair, is,

in a sense, the end of love, which must either overcome the partners

anew or be transformed into another mode of belonging together.

Love, by its very nature, is unworldly, and it is for this reason

rather than its rarity that it is not only apolitical but antipolitical,

perhaps the most powerful of all antipolitical human forces.

If it were true, therefore, as Chrsitianity assumed, that only love

can forgive because only love is fully receptive to who somebody

81. The common prejudice that love is as common as "romance" may be due

to the fact that we all learned about it first through poetry. But the poets fool us; they are the only ones to whom love is not only a crucial, but an indispensable

experience, which entitles them to mistake it for a universal one.

82. This world-creating faculty of love is not the same as fertility, upon which

most creation myths are based. The following mythological tale, on the contrary,

draws its imagery clearly from the experience of love: the sky is seen as a gigantic goddess who still bends down upon the earth god, from whom she is being separated by the air god who was born between them and is now lifting her up. Thus

a world space composed of air comes into being and inserts itself between earth

and sky. See H. A. Frankfort, The Intellectual Adventure of Ancient Man

(Chicago, 1946), p. 18, and Mircea Eliade, Traite d'Histoire des Religions (Paris, 1953), p. 212.

[ 242 ]

Action

is, to the point of being always willing to forgive him whatever he

may have done, forgiving would have to remain altogether outside

our considerations. Yet what love is in its own, narrowly circum-

scribed sphere, respect is in the larger domain of human affairs.

Respect, not unlike the Aristotelian philia politike, is a kind of

"friendship" without intimacy and without closeness; it is a regard

for the person from the distance which the space of the world puts

between us, and this regard is independent of qualities which we

may admire or of achievements which we may highly esteem.

Thus, the modern loss of respect, or rather the conviction that re-

spect is due only where we admire or esteem, constitutes a clear

symptom of the increasing depersonalization of public and social

life. Respect, at any rate, because it concerns only the person, is

quite sufficient to prompt forgiving of what a person did, for the

sake of the person. But the fact that the same who, revealed in

action and speech, remains also the subject of forgiving is the deep-

est reason why nobody can forgive himself; here, as in action and

speech generally, we are dependent upon others, to whom we ap-

pear in a distinctness which we ourselves are unable to perceive.

Closed within ourselves, we would never be able to forgive our-

selves any failing or transgression because we would lack the ex-

perience of the person for the sake of whom one can forgive.

34

U N P R E D I C T A B I L I T Y

AND T H E

P O W E R O F P R O M I S E

In contrast to forgiving, which—perhaps because of its religious

context, perhaps because of the connection with love attending its

discovery—has always been deemed unrealistic and inadmissible

in the public realm, the power of stabilization inherent in the fac-

ulty of making promises has been known throughout our tradition.

We may trace it back to the Roman legal system, the inviolability

of agreements and treaties (pacta sunt servanda); or we may see its

discoverer in Abraham, the man from Ur, whose whole story, as

the Bible tells it, shows such a passionate drive toward making

covenants that it is as though he departed from his country for no

other reason than to try out the power of mutual promise in the

[ 243 }

The Human Condition

wilderness of the world, until eventually God himself agreed to

make a Covenant with him. At any rate, the great variety of con-

tract theories since the Romans attests to the fact that the power of

making promises has occupied the center of political thought over

the centuries.

The unpredictability which the act of making promises at least

partially dispels is of a twofold nature: it arises simultaneously out

of the "darkness of the human heart," that is, the basic unreliability

of men who never can guarantee today who they will be tomorrow,

and out of the impossibility of foretelling the consequences of an

act within a community of equals where everybody has the same

capacity to act. Man's inability to rely upon himself or to have

complete faith in himself (which is the same thing) is the price

human beings pay for freedom; and the impossibility of remaining

unique masters of what they do, of knowing its consequences and

relying upon the future, is the price they pay for plurality and

reality, for the joy of inhabiting together with others a world

whose reality is guaranteed for each by the presence of all.

The function of the faculty of promising is to master this two-

fold darkness of human affairs and is, as such, the only alternative

to a mastery which relies on domination of one's self and rule over

others; it corresponds exactly to the existence of a freedom which

was given under the condition of non-sovereignty. The danger and

the advantage inherent in all bodies politic that rely on contracts

and treaties is that they, unlike those that rely on rule and sov-

ereignty, leave the unpredictability of human affairs and the unre-

liability of men as they are, using them merely as the medium, as

it were, into which certain islands of predictability are thrown and

in which certain guideposts of reliability are erected. The moment

promises lose their character as isolated islands of certainty in an

ocean of uncertainty, that is, when this faculty is misused to cover

the whole ground of the future and to map out a path secured in all

directions, they lose their binding power and the whole enterprise

becomes self-defeating.

We mentioned before the power generated when people gather

together and "act in concert," which disappears the moment they

depart. The force that keeps them together, as distinguished from

the space of appearances in which they gather and the power which

[ 244 )

Action

keeps this public space in existence, is the force of mutual promise

or contract. Sovereignty, which is always spurious if claimed by an

isolated single entity, be it the individual entity of the person or the

collective entity of a nation, assumes, in the case of many men

mutually bound by promises, a certain limited reality. The sov-

ereignty resides in the resulting, limited independence from the

incalculability of the future, and its limits are the same as those

inherent in the faculty itself of making and keeping promises. The

sovereignty of a body of people bound and kept together, not by an

identical will which somehow magically inspires them all, but by

an agreed purpose for which alone the promises are valid and bind-

ing, shows itself quite clearly in its unquestioned superiority over

those who are completely free, unbound by any promises and

unkept by any purpose. This superiority derives from the capacity

to dispose of the future as though it were the present, that is, the

enormous and truly miraculous enlargement of the very dimension

in which power can be effective. Nietzsche, in his extraordinary

sensibility to moral phenomena, and despite his modern prejudice

to see the source of all power in the will power of the isolated indi-

vidual, saw in the faculty of promises (the "memory of the will," as

he called it) the very distinction which marks off human from ani-

mal life.83 If sovereignty is in the realm of action and human affairs

what mastership is in the realm of making and the world of things,

then their chief distinction is that the one can only be achieved by

the many bound together, whereas the other is conceivable only in

isolation.

In so far as morality is more than the sum total of mores, of cus-

toms and standards of behavior solidified through tradition and

valid on the ground of agreements, both of which change with

time, it has, at least politically, no more to support itself than the

good will to counter the enormous risks of action by readiness to

forgive and to be forgiven, to make promises and to keep them.

83. Nietzsche saw with unequaled clarity the connection between human

sovereignty and the faculty of making promises, which led him to a unique insight

into the relatedness of human pride and human conscience. Unfortunately, both

insights remained unrelated with and without effect upon his chief concept, the

"will to power," and therefore are frequently overlooked even by Nietzsche scholars. They are to be found in the first two aphorisms of the second treatise in

Zur Genealogie der Moral.

[ 245 ]

The Human Condition

These moral precepts are the only ones that are not applied to ac-

tion from the outside, from some supposedly higher faculty or from

experiences outside action's own reach. They arise, on the con-

trary, directly out of the will to live together with others in the

mode of acting and speaking, and thus they are like control mecha-

nisms built into the very faculty to start new and unending proc-

esses. If without action and speech, without the articulation of

natality, we would be doomed to swing forever in the ever-recur-

ring cycle of becoming, then without the faculty to undo what we

have done and to control at least partially the processes we have

let loose, we would be the victims of an automatic necessity bear-

ing all the marks of the inexorable laws which, according to the

natural sciences before our time, were supposed to constitute the

outstanding characteristic of natural processes. We have seen be-

fore that to mortal beings this natural fatality, though it swings in

itself and may be eternal, can only spell doom. If it were true that

fatality is the inalienable mark of historical processes, then it

would indeed be equally true that everything done in history is

doomed.

And to a certain extent this is true. If left to themselves, human

affairs can only follow the law of mortality, which is the most cer-

tain and the only reliable law of a life spent between birth and

death. It is the faculty of action that interferes with this law be-

cause it interrupts the inexorable automatic course of daily life,

which in its turn, as we saw, interrupted and interfered with the

cycle of the biological life process. The life span of man running