The psychology of Nations by G.E. Partridge - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

CHAPTER VI

"CAUSES" AS PRINCIPLES AND ISSUES IN WAR

The causes for which wars are fought, or which are asserted to be the

causes, make one of the important psychological problems of war.

Sometimes these causes are elusive, sometimes they may give occasion

for cynicism and a pessimistic view of national morals; again we see

self-deception, again ideals seeking for light, peoples trying to find

something to live for or to die for. We see in the recent great war as

in other wars, a great variety of causes for which men are said to be

fighting. Some would say that the war was entirely a war of

principles; some take a purely political point of view and say that

principles are not involved at all, and others that nothing was

displayed at all of motives except primitive passions which are

equally devoid of moral issues or any principles.

It would be interesting from the psychological point of view to make,

if possible, a complete collection and classification of the causes

that have been brought forward as the fundamental things fought for in

the late war. Many widely different and divergent views are held. The

forms in which the issues of the war have been stated are almost

innumerable. New definitions and new statements of old conventional

ideas appear continuously. Every writer seems to see the war from a

different point of view from all others. Eventually, we may suppose,

all this will be clear, since these "causes" of the war will be one of

the great themes of future philosophical history. At present we can

only formulate such a view as may be suggestive with reference to

general interpretations of the place of principles and causes in war.

Let us examine a few of the opinions about the issues fought for in

the recent war. MacFall (56) says that the whole strategy of the

civilized world is bent upon creating permanent peace.

Many speak of

the war as a war to overcome war; we are told that one of the most

conscious motives of the soldiers in the field has been to make the

great war the last war the world should ever see.

Something of the

same idea is involved in the view each nation has that it was

attacked, and that the purpose of the war was to defeat and punish

aggressors. Apparently every nation and every army engaged in the war

has had the feeling that it was fighting in the interests of world

peace.

The German explanations of the war and of its issues have been very

numerous and widely varied. The German has had his own interpretation

of the "white man's burden," Tower (57) calls attention to the German

hybrid word "Sahibthum," expressing the mission of a people. Each

nation has its essence, which becomes a deep impulse.

The German's

impulse is translatable in the words "Be organized." The German has

been eager to organize the world. He-believed in all seriousness that

he was fighting the fight of order against chaos. It was the fight of

the spirit against that which is dead and inefficient.

The German

believed that the systematic exploitation of the world was his

peculiar mission. Ostwald is the great apostle of this view. He said

that the war was a battle of the higher life against the lower

instincts. Germany represents European civilization. The German

emperor said that Germany should do for Europe what Prussia had done

for Germany--organize it. In the German philosophy of life this

principle of order had become a serious principle. An inefficient and

disorderly world had need of Germany. Everywhere there was waste and

stupidity, and a want of reason in the world. System was to be the

cure. The fundamental fault in all this disorder the German mind

recognized as an excessive individualism. Individual instinct and the

social order were in eternal conflict, as Dietzel expressed the issue,

and Germany stood for the social order, for reason, since reason is

precisely the denial of the instincts and the desires of the

individual in the interest of a foreseen result.

Shortly after the beginning of the war, we remember, a manifesto

appeared signed by three thousand German university professors and

other teachers, saying that they, the signers, firmly believed that

the salvation of the whole of European civilization depended upon the

victory of German militarism. Hintze (49) said that Germany was

fighting for the freedom of everybody, meaning presumably according to

the German principle that freedom consists in voluntarily submitting

to order. This freedom is also in Hintze's view a principle of freedom

and equal rights for all nations, in so far as these nations have

reached the necessary stage of civilization. The mission of the coming

central management of mankind

(_Menschheitzentralverwaltung_) implied in the most ideal theory of Germany's mission is the true German

burden. Haeckel says that the work of the German people to assure and

develop civilization gives Germany the right to occupy the Balkans,

Asia Minor, Syria, and Mesopotamia, and to exclude from those

countries the races that occupy them. Schellendorf says that Germany

must not forget her civilizing task, which is to become the nucleus of

a future empire of the west. Koenig says that the spiritual life of

Europe is at stake, Germany's fight is the fight of civilization

against barbarism--against Russian barbarism he means.

This ought to

be the cause of all Western Europe, but England and France have

betrayed the western civilization into the hands of the East. This

belief gave to Germany's cause a deep impulsion (12).

Another way in which Germany's cause was frequently stated was that

Germany was a pure, virile and young race which was fighting the

older civilizations of the world. Vigor was assured of victory in any

case, but young life had a duty to perform--that of clearing the way

for new growth. This has found numerous forms of expression among

German writers, some of them highly dramatic and exaggerated; as, for

example, that the human race is divided into two species or kinds, the

male and the female, assuming that the German is the male among the

national spirits.

With these views of the nature of the German ideal or cause there have

gone, of course, interpretations of the conscious motives and

principles of other nations. In general other nations had no

principle. German writers have tended to believe that both England and

America were hypocritical and that their pretended democratic cause

was at heart only party and political aspiration. These nations, they

said, claimed to desire the world to enjoy the rights of democracy,

but each country assumed that it itself must be the controller of that

democratic principle. Another frequently expressed view of the

purposes of England and America is that they have purely sordid

interests, that they are capable of fighting only for advantage and

material gain.

Many of these German views of the war imply a principle that runs

through many fields of German thought--that values are something to be

determined objectively. It is a scientific principle.

Its conclusions

rest upon proof, rather than upon subjective principles of valuation.

There is another argument which is in part based upon an interpretation of scientific principles, but is in part also a

fatalistic doctrine--confidence in the issues of battle as a means of

testing the right and the validity of culture. The right will prevail,

on this theory, because the right is the stronger or because in some

sense strength _is_ the right, and because the method of selection of

the best by struggle is a basic principle, and may be applied to

everything that is living or is a product of life.

If the German interpretation of the German cause has been dominated by

an ideal of objective proof, we hear on the other side much about

subjective rights and subjective evaluations--the right, for example,

of every people to determine its own life, to have its own culture, to

decide upon its own nationality. The Allies have believed that they

were fighting to establish this principle throughout the world, and

that this principle is diametrically opposed to the German principle.

The thought of centralization, of a hierarchy of nations and the like,

is wholly foreign to this democratic principle. Bergson (17) finds in

the idea of industry the cause of the war and the principle of

opposition in it. The Allies, he says, have been fighting against

materialism with the forces of the spirit. Germany's forces are

material. A mechanism is fighting against a self-renewing spirit. The

ideal of force is met by the force of the ideal.

Boutroux (13) says that France, in the war, has had before her eyes

the idea of humanity; France was fighting for the recognition of the

rights of personality--rights of each nation to its own existence.

France is a champion of freedom; she wants all the legitimate

aspirations of peoples to be realized. Germanism, with its ideal of

force, is contrasted with the ideal of Greek and Christian culture and

philosophy. A cult of justice and modesty is contrasted with the cult

of power; in the former, sentiment and feeling have a place as

criteria of values; in the latter the appeal is to science and to

reason.

Hobhouse (34) says that the war is a conflict of the spirit of the

West against the spirit of the East (precisely the same as the German

view, we see, but with a very different identification of the

champions). Germany has never felt the spirit of the West. The war is

for something far deeper than national freedom; it is a war to justify

the primary rules of right. Burnet (18) thinks that the great conflict

was a conflict between Kultur as nationalistic, and humanism as

something international--that Germany, in recent years, had abandoned

an ideal of culture for that of specialization in the service of the

State. England's answer to the call was not to the specific need and

appeal of Belgium, but because England felt that there was something

in Germany incompatible with Western civilization.

Le Bon (42) says that we must always remember that the Teuton is the

irreconcilable enemy of the civilization of the French and of all it

stands for, and that he must always be kept at a distance. Durkheim's

view is that Germany's ambition and energy and will antagonize the

freedom of the rest of the world, and the rest of the world felt this

and the war was the consequence. Dillon (55) says that the future for

which Germany has been striving is a future incompatible with those

ideals which our race cherishes and reveres, and that we must make a

definite choice between our philosophy and religion and our code on

one side and those of the German on the other.

Drawbridge (19) says

that the war has been a conflict between the ideals of gentleness and

tact, on one side, and of brutality and ruthlessness on the other. It

is the Christian spirit against the Nietzschean.

Again we have been told that the war was simply a war of autocracy

against democracy, of mediævalism against modern life, of progress

against stagnation, of militarism and war against peace, of the

Napoleonic against the Christian spirit. Occasionally we hear more

personal and subjective notes. Redier (30) says that France was

fighting solely to retain mastery of her own genius, in order to draw

from it noble joys and just profits.

The American point of view has been expressed in several forms by the

President of the United States. For example, he has said that we are

one of the champions of the rights of mankind. The world must be made

safe for democracy. And again, that America is fighting for no selfish

purpose, but for the liberation of peoples everywhere from the

aggression of autocratic powers. This view that the war was remedial,

that it was in the interest of progress, to prevent that which is

belated in civilization from gaining the upper hand, and that it is on

the part of America a war of participation and aid in a cause which

though supremely good might otherwise be lost, is the prevailing idea.

That this spirit of the championship of causes and of justice to other

nations is a stronger motive in the Anglo-Saxon peoples than in others

appears to be an opinion that history on the whole can confirm.

It is relatively easy to obtain the opinion of philosophers about the

"causes" represented in the war; it would be of interest also to know

what the millions of men in the field think. Data are not altogether

wanting, but there appear to be no general studies. That many men, in

more than one army, have no clear knowledge of any cause for which

they have fought, except as these causes are nationalistic is certain.

That there is ignorance even among the men of our own army in regard

to the causes and purposes of the war has been made evident. Knowledge

and enlightenment can hardly have been greater elsewhere. German

soldiers are credited with believing that they are defending Germany

from attack. The French soldier was fighting for France.

The invasion

of his country left him no doubt and no choice. The English soldier

has often said that he was doing it for the women and the children,

and one writer says that the deepest motive of two thirds of the

British army was to make this war the last. The American soldier, from

the nature of the circumstances under which he himself entered the war

has been more conscious of a motive of helpfulness and of comradeship

with other peoples who are in distress and danger.

Probably the idea

of America's honor, and the more abstract idea still of the cause of

freedom, even though this idea has been, so to speak, our watchword,

have not been the most influential motives in the mind of the

individual. Germany was attacking people who were in distress, and

the American soldier went over to make the scales turn in the

direction of victory for the oppressed.

There is, of course, a literature of the war produced by the soldier

in the field, in which there are expressed high ideals, abstract

conceptions and firm principles. The French soldier has written about

liberty, the German soldier has had considerable to say about a Kultur

war. An American volunteer in the British army has written, "I find

myself among the millions of others in the great allied armies

fighting for all I believe right and civilized and humane against a

power which is evil and which threatens the existence of all the right

we prize and the freedom we enjoy" (24). But in general the

consciousness of the soldier, from all the evidence we have, was

concerned, as presumably was that of most of us, mainly with the most

obvious qualities of opposing forces, their concrete actions, and the

personal motives of rulers.

Leaving aside so far as one can one's own partisanship and mores

(which is not a very easy task), what causes can we say, with a

considerable degree of certainty, have actually been issues in the

present war? To some extent what one thinks these causes are will

remain matters of personal opinion and preference. Are there also

principles which, when once observed, will be accepted as the

fundamental "causes" of the war? There seem to be three at least which

characterize wide differences in the ideals and the civilization of

the opposing forces.

There is, first of all, an issue between the ideals of a relatively

autocratic form of government and a relatively more democratic form of

government. This was a cause of the intellectuals, but it was also a

popular cause. Men in general like the form of government under which

they live. From the standpoint of those who hold that a democratic

form of government is right, the war seemed to be a conflict between a

modern and progressive régime and an old and vicious one. So far as

this autocratic principle aimed to suppress the rights of individuals,

or to menace the liberties of small nations, so far as it was

aggressively militaristic and had imperial ambitions, which could be

achieved only by force, it stood clearly opposed to democracy.

Democracy and autocracy were plainly at war with one another, and yet

if we look closely we shall see that neither one can offer any actual

demonstration of its validity as the most superior or the final form

of government. In part they may appeal to the observable course of

history for their justification, but the final source of judgment

seems to rest in the mass of opinion in the world.

Questions of form

and taste are not wholly absent. But the believer in democracy and the

believer in autocracy will both assert that deep differences in

principle are involved. They will not admit that democracy and

autocracy are superficial forms, and are questions of taste, and they

will not agree with Munsterberg, who says that the two forms tend

inevitably toward a compromise, by a process of alternation in which

first one and-then the other is the dominant form in the world.

The war, in another aspect of it, has been a conflict between the idea

of nationalism and that of internationalism. It is a conflict between

an ideal of state, represented in the German philosophy of state by

the principle of complete autonomy of the individual nation, and one

which assumes that states, while retaining their rights of sovereignty

are to be governed by laws which regulate their conduct as functioning

members of a society of nations. The difference is that, relatively,

between a state of anarchy among nations and a state of order. To some

extent there has been a conflict between the idea of rights and the

idea of duties of nations. This internationalism is not merely a

sociological principle, something academic and scientific, as a theory

of state or society; it is an ethical principle, which contains some

recognition of justice as a subjective principle. It has some roots

in theory, but it is also based upon the immediate recognition of the

rights of peoples to their own individual lives. Its ideal is a world

containing many nations, coördinated by natural processes and not a

world in which a single nation or a few may hold the supreme place,

except as this supremacy might come by a process of natural

development.

The third conflict of the war was one which we may call a

psychological conflict. It was a conflict between two ideas of life,

one based upon a belief in the supremacy of reason, the other implying

that the final test of values in life remains in the sphere of the

feelings, or is a matter of appreciation. Germany, in her recent

history, has stood conspicuously for the belief that human society may

and indeed must be controlled and regulated by definite principles--principles that must be determined according to the

methods of science. These principles take the place, in this

philosophy of life, of certain typical human reactions that are

believed to be demonstrably irrational. In its visible and most

practical form the application of this principle is through

organization.

This characterization of German life reveals something very much like

a paradox in the principles of the war. We see a conflict in one

direction between a certain mediævalism in government and social forms

and a more modern and progressive type; we see also a conflict of a

modernism of an extreme form, represented by a scientific

civilization, united with this mediævalism, and in opposition to a

conception of life which is in some respects more naïve and more

primitive. The explanation of this paradox is that Germany offers an

illustration of a phenomenon of development that has been seen before

in history, of an excess of development and specialization in a

direction that appears to be off the main line of progress, or at

least is an anachronism. Germany has shown us the effects of

rationalism, some would say a morbid and hypertrophied reason. This

rationalism is certainly in part a product of systematic education and

propaganda, a conscious exploitation of science, and it is in part

temperamental. Such a result is always possible in a small state with

a highly centralized form of government. It is a notorious fact that

Germany's type of civilization can be spread neither by persuasion nor

by force. If we may apply a biological analogy we may say that German

Kultur in its modern form cannot survive. That this German

civilization has been felt by the world at large to be abnormal and of

the nature of a monstrosity we can hardly doubt, and that therefore to

some extent there has been a sense, on the part of the enemies of

Germany, of fighting to root out a dangerous and rank growth. Germany,

seeing in her own civilization only the appearance of modernism, has

been inclined to regard all other civilizations as decadent.

Germany, governed by the ideals of rationalism, has assumed that

history can be made, wars conducted, life regulated in accordance with

a program. On the other side we see a very general acceptance of a

philosophy of life in which many evils of disorder and waste and the

necessity of an experimental attitude toward life are accepted as

necessary consequences of the life of freedom. We see implied in this

philosophy of life a belief in a morality and a religion that are

based upon feeling rather than upon objective evidences, and a way of

judging conduct more or less naively and simply or according to

methods of appreciation that are essentially æsthetic, using the term

in a wide sense. This mode of life is accepted in the belief that

order in due season will come out of relative disorder, by a natural

process or by a gradually increasing organization and voluntary

adjustment. If we accept the validity of this attitude in life we

shall be inclined to regard rationalism as it is manifested to-day in

German life as an evil. We may believe that in the end the cure for

this rationalism will not be less reason but rather more, but we shall

see also that it is possible for reason to outstrip and pervert life,

and indeed involve life in an absurdity, simply because as a method of

dealing with the whole of life it cannot be sufficiently comprehensive.

Are these and all such issues that we find in war, causes of war? Do

nations fight for principles? Opinions certainly differ on this point.

Some think of wars, we say, as essentially conflicts of principles;

some interpret wars wholly in terms of political issues.

We should say

that the truth lies between these assertions or is the sum of their

half-truths. Wars are not in their origin wars of principle. The

political, the personal, the concrete aspects of the relations of

nations are always in the foreground in causing wars.

Wars become wars

of principle after they have been begun for other reasons. Sanctions

and motives appear after the fact. Fundamental differences of mores

which include the raw material, so to speak, of principles and causes

are factors in wars in so far as they create misunderstanding and

antipathy, but in so far as these differences of nature and of

principle do not enter into the sphere of politics and of national

honor, they do not as such cause wars Those deep moods