The psychology of Nations by G.E. Partridge - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

CHAPTER VII

PHILOSOPHICAL INFLUENCES

Philosophy, in the minds of many writers, must be given a high place

among the causes of war, and a considerable fraction of the literature

of the late war is devoted to the problem of discovering, in the field

of abstract thought, the influences that led to the great conflict.

Nietzsche, especially, seems to have been held responsible for the

European conflagration. As the philosopher of the New Germany, as the

chief expositor of the doctrine of force, the inventor of the

super-man and of the idea of the beyond-good, Nietzsche seems to stand

convicted of furnishing precisely the concepts that have become the

German's gospel of war; and since the German is prone to be guided by

abstractions, the evidence, even though circumstantial, seems to many

to be convincing.

Schopenhauer, also, as the great pessimist; Hegel, with his doctrine

of the supremacy of the State as the representative of the Idea on

earth; Kant, as the discoverer of the subjective moral principle;

English utilitarianism as the doctrine of the main chance; empiricism,

as the philosophy of inconsistency and dual principles of thought and

conduct; even the whole spirit of the English philosophy, which Wundt

says is nothing but an attempt to reconcile thought with the ideas of

peace and comfort--all these have been charged with being instigators

of the war.

Bergson (17) takes a different view. He says that the desire comes

first, the doctrine afterwards. Germany, determined upon war, invokes

Nietzsche or Hegel. Germany in a moral temper would appeal to Kant, or

in still a different mood to the Romanticists. Le Bon (42) says that

nations are pushed forward by forces which they cannot understand, and

that rational thoughts and desires play but a little part in war. That

appears to be true. We cannot say that philosophies do not enter at

all into the causes of war, but among these causes they must be

insignificant as compared with other causes that neither arise from

abstract thought nor are greatly modified by reason in any way.

Consider the influence of Napoleon (himself so little a product of any

philosophical influence), as compared with Hegel; or of Bismarck as

compared with Nietzsche, and this will be apparent.

There are in the

course of the centuries books and men that, as rational forces, do

exert profound effect upon the practical life, but they must be rarer

than is sometimes supposed. It is all too easy to assume a relation of

cause and effect when there is only a similarity between thought and

subsequent conduct. Rousseau may or may not have inspired the French

Revolution. Probably he did not. The recent great war, we might say,

has occurred in spite of philosophy, and if Nietzsche's influence

gravitated toward war, it can hardly be thought to have had any

deciding force in turning the scales already so overloaded by fate.

Philosophy failed to prevent war. Nietzsche's philosophy did not cause

it. His philosophy affords a convenient phraseology in which to

express a philosophy of war, granting sufficient misinterpretation of

his philosophy. Probably what influence he has had has been due rather

to his literary impressiveness than to his thought as a contribution

to philosophy.

Darwin, as the great force behind a new and varied development of

science, has had the fate to be, in some sense, a factor in the moods

and the new habits of life that led toward the final issue in the

great war. It is not so much that his principle, misapplied, or

applied uncritically may become a justification of war or even its

basic principle that has made him so great an influence, but

precisely because his thought, by becoming one of the great

coordinating principles of all the natural sciences has given power to

a movement which has had various practical consequences, not all of

them good, or at least not all yielding fruit for our own age.

Darwin's great influence as a force turning scholarly interest toward

naturalism and away from classicism, as a factor in modern materialism

and even pessimism, as a background, if no more, for the Haeckels and

Ostwalds of science is no inconsiderable factor in the scientific and

objective spirit of the day.

Facts must be faced. It is not such influences as that of

Schopenhauer, who expresses a logical or at least an abstract and we

might add literary form of pessimism, that in the generations just

past have transformed most of the conceptions of religion, with all

the effects upon the practical life that have followed, but the force

of our modern science combining with tendencies which it fosters but

perhaps does not create, giving momentum to industrialism and

specialization,--it is this change in the ideas of men that we must

suspect of being implicated in the present catastrophe of the world,

if any influence from the rational life is to be counted at all. Hegel

and Kant hover in the background. The author of the plan for universal

peace provides us with a subjective principle of morality which can be

distorted into a philosophy of moral independence and even of

independence from morality, and Hegel must have helped to establish

the German theory of the State, although with Treitschke and with the

practical state-makers like Frederick the Great and his followers, we

can hardly believe Hegel indispensable. The causes of war are too

general, too old and too fundamental to be greatly added to or

detracted from as yet by philosophy. Philosophy is the hope of the

world, it may be, and by no means a forlorn hope, but it is not yet

one of the great powers. When philosophy is a mere endorsement by

reason of some motive that has arisen in the practical life, or is a

literary expression of views about life, it may give the appearance

of being a profound force in the world. But this is not real

philosophy, in any case. Philosophy has not as yet shown itself highly

creative even in the calm fields of education and the moral life.

No! Philosophy is a factor in the motives of war rather by reason of

what it has not done, than because of its positive teachings. To-day

we ought no longer to be under illusions on that point.

Neither

Christianity nor philosophy can make or prevent wars as yet. They have

not been able to cope with the practical forces of the world which

make for nationalism, partisanship and personal interests. It would

require a greater amount both of religion and of philosophy than we

now can bring to bear upon the world to offset the influence of

Napoleon alone in the practical life of nations. It is the Napoleonic

spirit that still governs Europe. Philosophy has been thus far a

science of being an explanation of the world after the fact, and not

even to any great extent a science of its progress, except in so far

as, we may say, beginning with Hegel and with Spencer, there has been

some development of the methods and the most formal conceptions of

such a science. It is asking too much of philosophy, in its present

stage, to expect it to preach the gospel, or to teach school, or to

direct politics, and for the same reason it is unjust to charge

philosophy with having created the greatest catastrophe of history. If

philosophy cannot wield any great power now in those parts of life

that are by their nature presumably most amenable to reason, its

effect upon those events that express the supreme force of human

passions and the totality of life will not be very important. The

influences of philosophy are academic, and presumably any doctrine of

life that preaches achievement, virility and unmorality will include

in some degree war among the interests that it will affect, within the

limits of its academic nature. But youth is inherently warlike,

because above everything else it seeks to realize life in its

fullness, and war at least does symbolize this reality and abundance

of life. A philosophy which preached peace would hardly become a great

influence with youth. A philosophy advocating the cause of war would

form a natural background for the essential motives of youth. If the

scales were evenly balanced, it might turn them. It is hard at least

to see the relations of philosophy to the practical life in any other

light to-day. Philosophies are tenuous and adaptable things. We see

them used to support opposite causes, and they change color under the

influence of strong desires. Bosanquet (91) shows us how Hegel's noble

conception of the State, if we but substitute for its central thought

of welfare of the State, that of selfish interest, may be made to

change before our eyes into the meanest of maxims. This process is,

however, not unique in the history of the relations of thought and

life.

A detailed study of the relations of intellectual factors to war would

need to consider the effects of a great number of more or less

philosophical ideas which throw their weight on the side of war. So

far as these ideas are simple and clear, and especially if they can be

conveyed in the form of the phrase, their influence cannot wholly be

ignored. Some we have already referred to. The doctrine that might

makes right, the conception of state as supreme, the belief in the

divine right of kings, the belief in the ordained rights of

aristocracy, belief in militarism as a social institution, the

doctrine that life may be controlled by reason, all intellectual

pessimism, skepticism, any form of concept-worship, whether Hegelian

or other, acceptance of the methods of science and the results of

science as applicable to all the problems of life--all such principles

which inhabit the region, so to speak, between philosophy and the

practical life manifestly have some relation to the spirit of war. In

a very general way they may be counted as philosophical factors in

war. For the most part, however, those ideas that have been accused

of abetting war are exaggerations and perversions of philosophical

ideas. Nietzsche, Darwin and Hegel have all been exploited and made to

stand sponsor for specific philosophies of war. In the new philosophy

of life which Patten thinks has greatly influenced German conduct, and

which may be expressed in the words _Dienst_, _Ordnung_, and _Kraft_,

we can see both the effects of impulses that have grown out of the new

life itself, and the influences of formal philosophy.

That such ideas

have had relatively a greater influence in Germany than elsewhere must

be admitted, but that either this devotion to ideas or the ideas

themselves have been derived from philosophical interests and from

philosophies that have played any important part in the history of

thought we may well doubt. We should suspect that the same practical

interest that works unceasingly to distort and popularize philosophy

would help to create such pseudo-philosophy.

Von Bülow (65) says that the German people have a passion for logic,

and that this passion amounts to fanaticism:--that when an

intellectual form or system has been found for anything, they insist

with obstinate perseverance on fitting realities into the system.

Durkheim (16) says that the Germans' organized system of ideas is a

cause of war. It is also true, we should say, that the tendency to

organize ideas and even the fundamental ideas by which the Germans

have been guided are deeply rooted in temperament, in history and in

the social order of the past. Boutroux (13) says that the Germans

themselves regard the war as the culmination of their philosophy. We

should say on the contrary that the whole war philosophy of Europe is

almost wholly a product of strife and comes from impulses that arise

irresistibly in the practical life. Into these movements philosophy

fits or may be made to fit, and the presence of ideas in a society in

which the academic life has great prestige, ideas which coincide with

beliefs readily gives an illusion of an order governed by the higher

reason. The fact that Germany's recent wars had all been highly

successful, the fact that Germany had learned to depend upon her good

sword in time of need are the chief sources of Germany's doctrines of

war: the Hegelian background in the light of what we have learned in

recent times about the psychology of nations, must seem to be rather

of the nature of the ornamental. The ideal of the Prussian State to be

a power directed by intelligence suggests Hegel, but it seems highly

improbable, to say the least, that Hegelian philosophy has had much to

do with shaping this ideal. Behind all this is the necessity of

shaping German life in the form which it has taken--

necessity if we

accept, at least, Germany's national temperament itself as a

necessity. That other belief, widely held by German intellectuals and

officers that war is the testing of the validity of national cultures

would also probably never have appeared on the scene had not Germany

been secure in the belief that she herself had both the right and the

might on her side. It is possible, of course, that the war has

distorted our vision so that the relations of the practical life and

the life of reason have all been thrown out of focus, but when we see

what forces have been at work, and what they have done, it is

difficult to escape the conviction that we have been inclined to

believe too much in the power of mere ideas. This may be the great

lesson of the war. We may learn from it how to make ideas become the

power that hitherto they have failed to be.