The Commonplace Book of Thoughts, Memories and Fantasies by Mrs. Jameson - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

ll my own experience of life teaches me the contempt of cunning, not

the fear. The phrase “profound cunning” has always seemed to me a

contradiction in terms. I never knew a cunning mind which was not

either shallow, or on some point diseased. People dissemble

sometimes who yet hate dissembling, but a “cunning mind”

emphatically delights in its own cunning, and is the ready prey of

cunning. That “pleasure in deceiving and aptness to be deceived”

usually go together, was one of the wise sayings of the wisest of

men.

81

93.

I

t was a saying of Paracelsus, that “Those who would understand the

course of the heavens above must first of all recognise the heaven in

man:” meaning, I suppose, that all pursuit of knowledge which is not

accompanied by praise of God and love of our fellow-creatures must

turn to bitterness, emptiness, foolishness. We must imagine him to

have come to this conclusion only late in life.

Browning, in that wonderful poem of Paracelsus,—a poem in which

there is such a profound far-seeing philosophy, set forth with such a

luxuriance of illustration and imagery, and such a wealth of glorious

eloquence, that I know nothing to be compared with it since Goethe

and Wordsworth,—represents his aspiring philosopher as at first

impelled solely by the appetite to know. He asks nothing of men, he

despises them; but he will serve them, raise them, after a sort of God-

like fashion,

82

independent of their sympathy, scorning their applause, using them

like instruments, cheating them like children,—all for their good; but it

will not do. In Aprile, “who would love infinitely, and be beloved,” is

figured the type of the poet-nature, desiring only beauty, resolving all

into beauty; while in Paracelsus we have the type of the reflecting,

the inquiring mind desiring only knowledge, resolving all into

knowledge, asking nothing more to crown his being. And both find out

their mistake; both come to feel that love without knowledge is blind

and weak, and knowledge without love barren and vain.

“I too have sought to know as thou to LOVE,

Excluding love as thou refused’st knowledge;

Still thou hast beauty and I power. We wake!

*

*

*

*

*

“Are we not halves of one dissever’d world,

Whom this strange chance unites once more? Part?—

Never!

Till thou, the lover, know, and I, the knower,

Love—until both are saved!”

After all, perhaps, only the same old world-renowned myth in another

form—the marriage of Cupid and Psyche; Love and Intelligence long

parted, long suffering, again embracing, and lighted on by Beauty to

an immortal union. But to return to our poet. Aprile, exhausted by his

own aimless, dazzling visions, expires on the bosom of him who

knows; and Paracelsus, who began with a self

83

sufficing scorn of his kind, dies a baffled and degraded man in the

arms of him who loves;—yet wiser in his fall than through his

aspirations, he dies trusting in the progress of humanity so long as

humanity is content to be human; to love as well as to know;—to fear,

to hope, to worship, as well as to aspire.

94.

L

ord Bacon says: “I like a plantation (in the sense of colony) in a pure

soil; that is, where people are not displanted to the end to plant in

others: for else it is rather an extirpation than a plantation.” (Bacon,

who wrote this, counselled to James I. the plantation of Ulster exactly

on the principle he has here deprecated.)

He adds, “It is a shameful and unblessed thing to take the scum of

people, and wicked condemned men, to be the people with whom

you plant” ( i. e. colonise). And it is only now that our politicians are

beginning to discover and act upon this great moral

84

truth and obvious fitness of things!—like Bacon, adopting practically,

and from mere motives of expediency, a principle they would

theoretically abjure!

95.

B

ecause in real life we cannot, or do not, reconcile the high theory with

the low practice, we use our wit to render the theory ridiculous, and

our reason to reconcile us to the practice. We ought to do just the

reverse.

Many would say, if they spoke the truth, that it had cost them a life-

long effort to unlearn what they had been taught.

For as the eye becomes blinded by fashion to positive deformity, so

through social conventionalism the conscience becomes blinded to

positive immorality.

It is fatal in any mind to make the moral standard for men high and

the moral standard for women low, or vice versâ. This has appeared

to me the very

85

commonest of all mistakes in men and women who have lived much

in the world, but fatal nevertheless, and in three ways; first, as

distorting the moral ideal, so far as it exists in the conscience;

secondly, as perplexing the bounds, practically, of right and wrong;

thirdly, as being at variance with the spirit and principles of

Christianity. Admit these premises, and it follows inevitably that such

a mistake is fatal in the last degree, as disturbing the consistency and

the elevation of the character, morally, practically, religiously.

Akin to this mistake, or identical with it, is the belief that there are

essential masculine and feminine virtues and vices. It is not, in fact,

the quality itself, but the modification of the quality, which is

masculine or feminine: and on the manner or degree in which these

are balanced and combined in the individual, depends the perfection

of that individual character—its approximation to that of Christ. I firmly

believe that as the influences of religion are extended, and as

civilisation advances, those qualities which are now admired as

essentially feminine will be considered as essentially human, such as

gentleness, purity, the more unselfish and spiritual sense of duty, and

the dominance of the affections over the passions. This is, perhaps,

what Buffon, speaking as a naturalist, meant, when he said that with

the

86

progress of humanity, “Les races se féminisent;” at least I understand

the phrase in this sense.

A man who requires from his own sex manly direct truth, and laughs

at the cowardly subterfuges and small arts of women as being

feminine;—a woman who requires from her own sex tenderness and

purity, and thinks ruffianism and sensuality pardonable in a man as

being masculine,—these have repudiated the Christian standard of

morals which Christ, in his own person, bequeathed to us—that

standard which we have accepted as Christians—theoretically at

least—and which makes no distinction between “the highest, holiest

manhood,” and the highest, holiest womanhood.

I might illustrate this position not only scripturally but philosophically,

by quoting the axiom of the Greek philosopher Antisthenes, the

disciple of Socrates,—“The virtue of the man and the woman is the

same;” which shows a perception of the moral truth, a sort of

anticipation of the Christian doctrine, even in the pagan times. But I

prefer an illustration which is at once practical and poetical, and plain

to the most prejudiced among men or women.

Every reader of Wordsworth will recollect, if he does not know by

heart, the poem entitled “The Happy Warrior.” It has been quoted

often as an

87

epitome of every manly, soldierly, and elevated quality. I have heard it

applied to the Duke of Wellington. Those who make the experiment of

merely substituting the word woman for the word warrior, and

changing the feminine for the masculine pronoun, will find that it

reads equally well; that almost from beginning to end it is literally as

applicable to the one sex as to the other. As thus:—

CHARACTER OF THE HAPPY WOMAN.

Who is the happy woman? Who is she

That every woman born should wish to be?

It is the generous spirit, who, when brought

Among the tasks of real life, had wrought

Upon the plan that pleased her childish thought;

Whose high endeavours are an inward light,

That make the path before her always bright:

Who, with a natural instinct to discern

What knowledge can perform, is diligent to learn;

Abides by this resolve, and stops not there,

But makes her moral being her prime care;

Who, doomed to go in company with Pain,

And Fear, and Sorrow, miserable train!

Turns that necessity to glorious gain;

In face of these doth exercise a power

Which is our human nature’s highest dower:

Controls them and subdues, transmutes,

bereaves

Of their bad influence, and their good receives;

By objects, which might force the soul to abate

Her feeling, rendered more compassionate;

Is placable—because occasions rise

So often that demand such sacrifice;

More skilful in self-knowledge, even more pure

As tempted more; more able to endure,

88

As more exposed to suffering and distress;

Thence, also, more alive to tenderness.

’Tis she whose law is reason; who depends

Upon that law as on the best of friends;

Whence in a state where men are tempted still

To evil for a guard against worse ill,

And what in quality or act is best,

Doth seldom on a right foundation rest,

She fixes good on good alone, and owes

To virtue every triumph that she knows.

Who, if she rise to station of command,

Rises by open means; and there will stand

On honourable terms, or else retire.

*

*

*

*

*

Who comprehends her trust, and to the same

Keeps faithful with a singleness of aim;

And therefore does not stoop, nor lie in wait

For wealth, or honours, or for worldly state;

Whom they must follow; on whose head must fall

Like showers of manna, if they come at all:

Whose powers shed round her in the common

strife

Or mild concerns of ordinary life,

A constant influence, a peculiar grace;

But who, if she be called upon to face

Some awful moment to which Heaven has joined

Great issue, good or bad for human kind,

Is happy as a lover; and attired

With sudden brightness, like to one inspired;

And, through the heat of conflict, keeps the law

In calmness made, and sees what she foresaw;

Or if an unexpected call succeed,

Come when it will, is equal to the need!

In all these fifty-six lines there is only one line which cannot be

feminised in its significance,—that which I have filled up with

asterisks, and which is totally at variance with our ideal of A Happy

Woman. It is the line—

89

“And in himself possess his own

desire.”

No woman could exist happily or virtuously in such complete

independence of all external affections as these words express. “Her

desire is to her husband,”—this is the sort of subjection prophesied

for the daughters of Eve. A woman doomed to exist without this

earthly rest for her affections, does not “in herself possess her own

desire;” she turns towards God; and if she does not make her life a

life of worship, she makes it a life of charity, (which in itself is

worship,) or she dies a spiritual and a moral death. Is it much better

with the man who concentrates his aspirations in himself? I should

think not.

Swift, as a man and a writer, is one of those who had least sympathy

with women; and I have sometimes thought that the exaggeration,

even to morbidity, of the coarse and the cruel in his character, arose

from this want of sympathy; but his strong sense showed him the one

great moral truth as regards the two sexes, and gave him the courage

to avow it.

He says, “I am ignorant of any one quality that is amiable in a woman

which is not equally so in a man. I do not except even modesty and

gentleness of nature; nor do I know one vice or folly which is

90

not equally detestable in both.” Then, remarking that cowardice is an

infirmity generally allowed to women, he wonders that they should

fancy it becoming or graceful, or think it worth improving by

affectation, particularly as it is generally allied to cruelty.

Here is a passage from one of Humboldt’s letters, which I have seen

quoted with sympathy and admiration, as applied to the manly

character only:—

“Masculine independence of mind I hold to be in reality the first

requisite for the formation of a character of real manly worth. The

man who suffers himself to be deceived and carried away by his own

weakness, may be a very amiable person in other respects, but

cannot be called a good man; such beings should not find favour in

the eyes of a woman, for a truly beautiful and purely feminine nature

should be attracted only by what is highest and noblest in the

character of man.”

Now we will take this bit of moral philosophy, and, without the

slightest alteration of the context, apply it to the female character.

“Feminine independence of mind I hold to be in reality the first

requisite for the formation of a character of real feminine worth. The

woman who allows herself to be deceived and carried away by

91

her own weakness may be a very amiable person in other respects,

but cannot be called a good woman; such beings should not find

favour in the eyes of a man, for the truly beautiful and purely manly

nature should be attracted only by what is highest and noblest in the

character of woman.”

After reading the above extracts, does it not seem clear, that by the

exclusive or emphatic use of certain phrases and epithets, as more

applicable to one sex than to the other, we have introduced a most

un-christian confusion into the conscience, and have prejudiced it

early against the acceptance of the larger truth?

It might seem, that where we reject the distinction between masculine

and feminine virtues, one and the same type of perfection should

suffice for the two sexes; yet it is clear that the moment we come to

consider the personality, the same type will not suffice: and it is worth

consideration that when we place before us the highest type of

manhood, as exemplified in Christ, we do not imagine him as the

father, but as the son; and if we think of the most perfect type of

womanhood, we never can exclude the mother.

Montaigne deals with the whole question in his own homely

straightforward fashion:—

92

“Je dis que les mâles et les fémelles sont jettés en même moule; sauf

l’institution et l’usage la différence n’y est pas grande. Platon appelle

indifféremment les uns et les autres à la société de touts études,

exercises, charges, et vocations guerrières et paisibles en sa

république, et le philosophe Antisthènes ôtait toute distinction entre

leur vertu et la nôtre. Il est bien plus aisé d’accuser un sexe que

d’excuser l’autre: c’est ce qu’on dit, ‘le fourgon se moque de la

poële.’”

Not that I agree with Plato,—rather would leave all the fighting,

military and political, if there must be fighting, to the men.

Among the absurdities talked about women, one hears, perhaps,

such an aphorism as the following quoted with a sort of ludicrous

complacency,—“The woman’s strength consists in her weakness!” as

if it were not the weakness of a woman which makes her in her

violence at once so aggravating and so contemptible, in her

dissimulation at once so shallow and so dangerous, and in her

vengeance at once so cowardly and so cruel.

I should not say, from my experience of my own sex, that a woman’s

nature is flexible and impressible,

93

though her feelings are. I know very few instances of a very inferior

man ruling the mind of a superior woman, whereas I know twenty—

fifty—of a very inferior woman ruling a superior man. If he love her,

the chances are that she will in the end weaken and demoralise him.

If a superior woman marry a vulgar or inferior man he makes her

miserable, but he seldom governs her mind, or vulgarises her nature,

and if there be love on his side the chances are that in the end she

will elevate and refine him.

The most dangerous man to a woman is a man of high intellectual

endowments morally perverted; for in a woman’s nature there is such

a necessity to approve where she admires, and to believe where she

loves,—a devotion compounded of love and faith is so much a part of

her being,—that while the instincts remain true and the feelings

uncorrupted, the conscience and the will may both be led far astray.

Thus fell “our general mother,”—type of her sex,—overpowered,

rather than deceived, by the colossal intellect,—half serpent, half

angelic.

Coleridge speaks, and with a just indignant scorn, of those who

consider chastity as if it were a thing—a thing which might be lost or

kept by external accident—a thing of which one might be

94

robbed, instead of a state of being. According to law and custom, the

chastity of Woman is as the property of Man, to whom she is

accountable for it, rather than to God and her own conscience.

Whatever people may say, such is the common, the social, the legal

view of the case. It is a remnant of Oriental barbarism. It tends to

much vice, or, at the best, to a low standard of morality, in both sexes.

This idea of property in the woman survives still in our present social

state, particularly among the lower orders, and is one cause of the ill

treatment of wives. All those who are particularly acquainted with the

manners and condition of the people will testify to this; namely, that

when a child or any weaker individual is ill treated, those standing by

will interfere and protect the victim; but if the sufferer be the wife of

the oppressor, it is a point of etiquette to look on, to take no part in

the fray, and to leave the brute man to do what he likes “with his

own.” Even the victim herself, if she be not pummelled to death,

frequently deprecates such an interference with the dignity and the

rights of her owner. Like the poor woman in the “Médecin malgré

lui:”—“Voyez un peu cet impertinent qui vent empêcher les maris de

battre leurs femmes!—et si je veux qu’il me batte, moi?”—and so

ends by giving her defender a box on the ear.

95

“Au milieu de tous les obstacles que la nature et la société out semés

sur les pas de la femme, la seule condition de repos pour elle est de

s’entourer de barrières que les passions ne puissent franchir;

incapable de s’approprier l’existence, elle est toujours semblable a la

Chinoise dont les pieds ont été mutilés et pour laquelle toute liberté

est un leurre, toute espace ouverte une cause de chute. En attendant

que l’éducation ait donné aux femmes leur véritable place, malheur à

celles qui brisent les lisses accoutumées! pour elles l’indépendance

ne sera, comme la gloire, qu’un deuil éclatant du bonheur!”— B.

Constant.

This also is one of those common-places of well-sounding eloquence,

in which a fallacy is so wrapt up in words we have to dig it out. If this

be true, it is true only so long as you compress the feet and compress

the intellect,—no longer.

Here is another:—

“L’expérience lui avait appris que quel que fut leur âge, ou leur

caractère, toutes les femmes vivaient avec le même rêve, et qu’elles

avaient toutes au fond du cœur un roman commencé dont elles

attendaient jusqu’à la mort le héros, comme les juifs attendent le

Messie.”

This “roman commencé,” (et qui ne finit jamais), is true as regards

women who are idle, and who have not replaced dreams by duties.

And what are the

96

“barrières” which passion cannot overleap, from the moment it has

subjugated the will? How fine, how true that scene in Calderon’s

“Magico Prodigioso,” where Justina conquers the fiend only by not

consenting to ill!

——“This agony

Of passion which afflicts my heart and

soul

May sweep imagination in its storm;

The will is firm.”

And the baffled demon shrinks back,—

“Woman, thou hast subdued me

Only by not owning thyself

subdued!”

A friend of mine was once using some mincing elegancies of

language to describe a high degree of moral turpitude, when a man

near her interposed, with stern sarcasm, “Speak out! Give things their

proper names! Half words are the perdition of women!

“I observe,” said Sydney Smith, “that generally about the age of forty,

women get tired of being

97

virtuous and men of being honest.” This was said and received with a

laugh as one of his good things; but, like many of his good things,

how dreadfully true! And why? because, generally, education has

made the virtue of the woman and the honesty of the man a matter of

external opinion, not a law of the inward life.

Dante, in his lowest hell