The Commonplace Book of Thoughts, Memories and Fantasies by Mrs. Jameson - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

now in all the impunity of conventional forbearance, dealing in oracles

and sentimentalisms, performing great things, teaching good things,

you are set up as one of the lights of the

273

world:—Lo! another time comes; the torch is taken out of your hand,

and held up to your face. What! is it a mask, and not a face? “Off, off

ye lendings!” O God! how much wiser, as well as better, not to study

how to seem, but how to be! How much wiser and better, not to have

to shudder before the truth as it oozes out from a thousand

unguessed, unguarded apertures, staining your lawn or your ermine;

not to have to tremble at the thought of that future Thackeray, who

“shall pluck out the heart of your mystery,” and shall anatomise you,

and deliver lectures upon you, to illustrate the standard of morals and

manners in Queen Victoria’s reign!

In these lectures, some fine and feeling and discriminative passages

on character, make amends for certain offences and inconsistencies

in the novels; I mean especially in regard to the female portraits. No

woman resents his Rebecca—inimitable Becky!—no woman but feels

and acknowledges with a shiver the completeness of that wonderful

and finished artistic creation; but every woman resents the selfish

inane Amelia, and would be inclined to quote and to apply the

author’s own words when speaking of ‘Tom Jones:’—“I can’t say that

I think Amelia a virtuous character. I can’t say but I think Mr.

Thackeray’s evident liking and admiration for his Amelia shows that

the great humourist’s moral sense was blunted by his life, and that

here in art and

274

ethics there is a great error. If it be right to have a heroine whom we

are to admire, let us take care at least that she is admirable.”

Laura, in ‘Pendennis,’ is a yet more fatal mistake. She is drawn with

every generous feeling, every good gift. We do not complain that she

loves that poor creature Pendennis, for she loved him in her

childhood. She grew up with that love in her heart; it came between

her and the perception of his faults; it is a necessity indivisible from

her nature. Hallowed, through its constancy, therein alone would lie

its best excuse, its beauty and its truth. But Laura, faithless to that

first affection; Laura, waked up to the appreciation of a far more

manly and noble nature, in love with Warrington, and then going back

to Pendennis, and marrying him! Such infirmity might be true of some

women, but not of such a woman as Laura; we resent the

inconsistency, the indelicacy of the portrait.

And then Lady Castlewood,—so evidently a favourite of the author,

what shall we say of her? The virtuous woman, par excellence, who

“never sins and never forgives,” who never resents, nor relents, nor

repents; the mother, who is the rival of her daughter; the mother, who

for years is the confidante of a man’s delirious passion for her own

child, and then consoles him by marrying him herself! O Mr.

Thackeray! this will never do! such women may

275

exist, but to hold them up as examples of excellence, and fit objects

of our best sympathies, is a fault, and proves a low standard in ethics

and in art. “When an author presents to us a heroine whom we are

called upon to admire, let him at least take care that she is

admirable.” If in these, and in some other instances, Thackeray has

given us cause of offence, in the lectures we may thank him for some

amends: he has shown us what he conceives true womanhood and

true manliness ought to be; so with this expression of gratitude, and a

far deeper debt of gratitude left unexpressed, I close his book, and

say, good night!

276

Notes on Art.

96.

S

ometimes, in thoughtful moments, I am struck by those beautiful

analogies between things apparently dissimilar—those awful

approximations between things apparently far asunder—which many

people would call fanciful and imaginary, but they seem to bring all

God’s creation, spiritual and material, into one comprehensive whole;

they give me, thus associated, a glimpse, a perception of that over

277

whelming unity which we call the universe, the multitudinous ONE.

Thus the principle of the highest ideal in art, as conceived by the

Greeks, and unsurpassed in its purity and beauty, lay in considering

well the characteristics which distinguish the human form from the

brute form; and then, in rendering the human form, the first aim was

to soften down, or, if possible, throw out wholly, those characteristics

which belong to the brute nature, or are common to the brute and the

man; and the next, to bring into prominence and even enlarge the

proportions of those manifestations of forms which distinguish

humanity; till, at last, the human merged into the divine, and the God

in look, in limb, in feature, stood revealed.

Let us now suppose this broad principle which the Greeks applied to

form, ethically carried out, and made the basis of all education—the

training of men as a race. Suppose we started with the general axiom

that all propensities which we have in common with the lower animals

are to be kept subordinate, and so far as is consistent with the truth of

nature refined away; and that all the qualities which elevate, all the

aspirations which ally us with the spiritual, are to be cultivated and

rendered more and more prominent, till at last the human being, in

faculties as well as form, approaches the God-like—I only say—

suppose?—

278

Again: it has been said of natural philosophy (Zoology) that in order to

make any real progress in the science, as such, we must more and

more disregard differences, and more and more attend to the

obscured but essential conditions which are revealed in

resemblances, in the constant and similar relations of primitive

structure. Now if the same principle were carried out in theology, in

morals, in art, as well as in science, should we not come nearer to the

essential truth in all?

97.

“T

here is an instinctive sense of propriety and reality in every mind; and

it is not true, as some great authority has said, that in art we are

satisfied with contemplating the work without thinking of the artist. On

the contrary, the artist himself is one great object in the work. It is as

embodying the energies and excellences of the human mind, as

exhibiting the efforts of genius, as symbolising high feeling, that we

most value the creations of art; without design the representations of

art are merely fantastical, and without the thought of a design act

279

ing upon fixed principles in accordance with a high standard of

goodness and truth, half the charm of design is lost.”

98.

“A

rt, used collectively for painting, sculpture, architecture, and music, is

the mediatress between, and reconciler of, nature and man. It is,

therefore, the power of humanising nature, of infusing the thoughts

and passions of man into everything which is the object of his

contemplation. Colour, form, motion, sound, are the elements which it

combines, and it stamps them into unity in the mould of a moral idea.”

This is Coleridge’s definition:—Art then is nature, humanised; and in

proportion as humanity is elevated by the interfusion into our life of

noble aims and pure affections will art be spiritualised and moralised.

99.

I

f faith has elevated art, superstition has everywhere debased it.

280

100.

Goethe observes that there is no patriotic art and no patriotic

science—that both are universal.

There is, however, national art, but not national science: we say

“national art,” “natural science.”

101.

“V

erse is in itself music, and the natural symbol of that union of passion

with thought and pleasure, which constitutes the essence of all poetry

as contradistinguished from history civil or natural.”— Coleridge.

In the arts of design, colour is to form what verse is to prose—a more

harmonious and luminous vehicle of the thought.

281

102.

S

ubjects and representations in art not elevated nor interesting in

themselves, become instructive and interesting to higher minds from

the manner in which they have been treated; perhaps because they

have passed through the medium of a higher mind in taking form.

This is one reason, though we are not always conscious of it, that the

Dutch pictures of common and vulgar life give us a pleasure apart

from their wonderful finish and truth of detail. In the mind of the artist

there must have been the power to throw himself into a sphere above

what he represents. Adrian Brouwer, for instance, must have been

something far better than a sot; Ostade something higher than a

boor; though the habits of both led them into companionship with sots

and boors. In the most farcical pictures of Jan Steen there is a depth

of feeling and observation which remind me of the humour of

Goldsmith; and Teniers, we know, was in his habits a refined

gentleman; the brilliant elegance of his pencil contrasting with the

grotesque vulgarity of his subjects. To a thinking mind, some of these

Dutch pictures of character are full of material for thought, pathetic

even where least sympathetic: no doubt, because of a latent

sympathy with the artist, apart from his subject.

282

103.

C

oleridge says,—“Every human feeling is greater and larger than the

exciting cause.” (A philosophical way of putting Rochefoucauld’s

neatly expressed apophthegm: “Nous ne sommes jamais ni si

heureux ni si malheureux que nous l’imaginons.”) “A proof,” he

proceeds, “that man is designed for a higher state of existence; and

this is deeply implied in music, in which there is always something

more and beyond the immediate expression.”

But not music only, every production of art ought to excite emotions

greater and thoughts larger than itself. Thoughts and emotions which

never perhaps were in the mind of the artist, never were anticipated,

never were intended by him—may be strongly suggested by his work.

This is an important part of the morals of art, which we must never

lose sight of. Art is not only for pleasure and profit, but for good and

for evil.

Goethe (in the Dichtung und Wahrheit) describes the reception of

Marie Antoinette at Strasbourg, where she passed the frontier to enter

her new kingdom. She was then a lovely girl of sixteen. He

283

relates that on visiting before her arrival the reception room on the

bridge over the Rhine, where her German attendants were to deliver

her into the hands of the French authorities, he found the walls hung

with tapestries representing the ominous story of Jason and Medea—

of all the marriages on record the most fearful, the most tragic in its

consequences. “What!” he exclaims, his poetical imagination struck

with the want of moral harmony, “was there among these French

architects and decorators no man who could perceive that pictures

represent things,—that they have a meaning in themselves,—that

they can impress sense and feeling,—that they can awaken

presentiments of good or evil?” But, as he tells us, his exclamations

of horror were met by the mockery of his French companions, who

assured him that it was not everybody’s concern to look for

significance in pictures.

These self-same tapestries of the story of Jason and Medea were

after the Restoration presented by Louis XVIII. to George IV., and at

present they line the walls of the Ball-room in Windsor Castle. We

might repeat, with some reason, the question of Goethe; for if

pictures have a significance, and speak to the imagination, what has

the tragedy of Jason and Medea to do in a ball-room?

Goethe, who thus laid down the principle that works

284

of art speak to the feelings and the conscience, and can awaken

associations tending to good and evil, by some strange inconsistency

places art and artists out of the sphere of morals. He speaks

somewhere with contempt and ridicule of those who take their

conscience and their morality with them to an opera or a picture

gallery. Yet surely he is wrong. Why should we not? Are our

conscience and our morals like articles of dress which we can take off

and put on again as we fancy it convenient or expedient?—shut up in

a drawer and leave behind us when we visit a theatre or a gallery of

art? or are they not rather a part of ourselves—our very life—to

graduate the worth, to fix the standard of all that mingles with our life?

The idea that what we call taste in art has something quite distinctive

from conscience, is one cause that the popular notions concerning

the productions of art are abandoned to such confusion and

uncertainty; that simple people regard taste as something forensic,

something to be learned, as they would learn a language, and

mastered by a study of rules and a dictionary of epithets; and they

look up to a professor of taste, just as they would look up to a

professor of Greek or of Hebrew. Either they listen to judgments

lightly and confidently promulgated with a sort of puzzled faith and a

surrender of their own moral sense, which are pitiable;

285

as if art also had its infallible church and its hierarchy of dictators!—or

they fly into the opposite extreme, and seeing themselves deceived

and misled, fall away into strange heresies. All from ignorance of a

few laws simple in their form, yet infinite in their application;— natural

laws we must call them, though here applied to art.

In my younger days I have known men conspicuous for their want of

elevated principle, and for their dissipated habits, held up as arbiters

and judges of art; but it was to them only another form of epicurism

and self-indulgence; and I have seen them led into such absurd and

fatal mistakes for want of the power to distinguish and to generalise,

that I have despised their judgment, and have come to the conclusion

that a really high standard of taste and a low standard of morals are

incompatible with each other.

104.

“T

he fact of the highest artistic genius having manifested itself in a

polytheistic age, and among a people whose moral views were

essentially degraded, has, we think, fostered the erroneous notion

286

that the sphere of art has no connection with that of morality. The

Greeks, with penetrative insight, dilated the essential characteristics

of man’s organism as a vehicle of superior intelligence, while their

intense sympathy with physical beauty made them alive to its most

subtle manifestations; and reproducing their impressions through the

medium of art, they have given birth to models of the human form,

which reveal its highest possibilities, and the excellence of which

depends upon their being individual expressions of ideal truth. Thus,

too, in their descriptions of nature, instead of multiplying insignificant

details, they seized instinctively upon the characteristic features of

her varying aspects, and not unfrequently embodied a finished picture

in one comprehensive and harmonious word. In association with their

marvellous genius, however, we find a cruelty, a treachery, and a

licence which would be revolting if it were not for the historical interest

which attaches to every genuine record of a bygone age. Their low

moral standard cannot excite surprise when we consider the

debasing tendency of their worship, the objects of their adoration

being nothing more than their own degraded passions invested with

some of the attributes of deity. Now, among the modifications of

thought introduced by Christianity, there is perhaps none more

pregnant with important results than the harmony which it

287

has established between religion and morality. The great law of right

and wrong has acquired a sacred character, when viewed as an

expression of the divine will; it takes its rank among the eternal

verities, and to ignore it in our delineations of life, or to represent sin

otherwise than as treason against the supreme ruler, is to retain in

modern civilisation one of the degrading elements of heathenism.

Conscience is as great a fact of our inner life as the sense of beauty,

and the harmonious action of both these instinctive principles is

essential to the highest enjoyment of art, for any internal dissonance

disturbs the repose of the mind, and thereby shatters the image

mirrored in its depths.”— A. S.

105.

“M

ais vous autres artistes, vous ne considerez pour la plupart dans les

œuvres que la beauté ou la singularité de l’exécution, sans vous

pénétrer de l’idée dont cet œuvre est la forme; ainsi votre intelligence

adore souvent l’expression d’un sentiment que votre cœur

repousserait s’il en avait la conscience.”— George Sand.

288

106.

L

avater told Goethe that on a certain occasion when he held the velvet

bag in the church as collector of the offerings, he tried to observe only

the hands; and he satisfied himself that in every individual, the shape

of the hand and of the fingers, the action and sentiment in dropping

the gift into the bag, were distinctly different and individually

characteristic.

What then shall we say of Van Dyck, who painted the hands of his

men and women, not from individual nature, but from a model hand—

his own very often?—and every one who considers for a moment will

see in Van Dyck’s portraits, that, however well painted and elegant

the hands, they in very few instances harmonise with the

personalité;—that the position is often affected, and as if intended for

display,—the display of what is in itself a positive fault, and from

which some little knowledge of comparative physiology would have

saved him.

There are hands of various character; the hand to catch, and the

hand to hold; the hand to clasp, and

289

the hand to grasp. The hand that has worked or could work, and the

hand that has never done anything but hold itself out to be kissed,

like that of Joanna of Arragon in Raphael’s picture.

Let any one look at the hands in Titian’s portrait of old Paul IV.:

though exquisitely modelled, they have an expression which reminds

us of claws; they belong to the face of that grasping old man, and

could belong to no other.

107.

M

ozart and Chopin, though their genius was differently developed,

were alike in some things: in nothing more than this, that the artistic

element in both minds wholly dominated over the social and practical,

and that their art was the element in which they moved and lived,

through which they felt and thought. I doubt whether either of them

could have said, “D’abord je suis homme et puis je suis artiste;”

whereas this could have been said with truth by Mendelsohn and by

Litzst. In Mendelsohn the enormous creative power was modified by

the intellect

290

and the conscience. Litzst has no creative power.

Liszt has thus drawn the character of Chopin:—“Rien n’était plus pur

et plus exalté en même temps que ses pensées; rien n’était plus

tenace, plus exclusif, et plus minutieusement dévoué que ses

affections. Mais cet être ne comprenait que ce qui était identique à

lui-même:—le reste n’existait pour lui que comme une sorte de rêve

fâcheux, auquel il essayait de se soustraire en vivant au milieu du

monde. Toujours perdu dans ses rêveries, la réalité lui deplaisait.

Enfant il ne pouvait toucher à un instrument tranchant sans se

blesser; homme il ne pouvait se trouver en face d’un homme différent

de lui, sans se heurter contre cette contradiction vivante.”

“Ce qui le préservait d’un antagonisme perpétuel c’était l’habitude

volontaire et bientôt invétérée de ne point voir, de ne pas entendre ce

qui lui deplaisait: en général sans toucher à ses affections

personelles, les êtres qui ne pensaient pas comme lui devenaient à

ses yeux comme des espèces de fantômes; et comme il était d’une

politesse charmante, on pouvait prendre pour une bienveillance

courtoise ce qui n’était chez lui qu’un froid dédain—une aversion

insurmontable.”

108.

T

he father of Mozart was a man of high and strict religious principle.

He had a conviction—in his

291

case more truly founded than is usual—that he was the father of a

great, a surpassing genius, and consequently of a being unfortunate

in this, that he must be in advance of his age, exposed to error, to

envy, to injustice, to strife; and to do his duty to his son demanded

large faith and large firmness. But because he did estimate this

sacred trust as a duty to be discharged, not only with respect to his

gifted son, but to the God who had so endowed him; so, in spite of

many mistakes, the earnest straightforward endeavour to do right in

the parent seems to have saved Mozart’s moral life, and to have

given that completeness to the productions of his genius, which the

harmony of the moral and creative faculties alone can bestow.

“The modifying power of circumstances on Mozart’s style, is an

interesting consideration. Whatever of striking, of new or beautiful he

met with in the works of others left its impression on him; and he

often reproduced these efforts, not servilely,