is often unconscious; a just taste is always conscious. A good taste
may be lowered or spoilt; a just taste can only go on refining more
and more.
140.
A
rtists are interesting to me as men. Their work, as the product of
mind, should lead us to a knowledge of their own being; else, as I
have often said and written, our admiration of art is a species of
atheism. To forget the soul in its highest manifestation is like
forgetting God in his creation.
141.
“L
es images peints du corps humain, dans les figures où domine par
trop le savoir anatomique, en révèlant trop clairement à l’homme les
secrets de sa
324
structure, lui en découvrent aussi par trop ce qu’on pourrait appeler le
point de vue matériel, ou, si l’on veut, animal.”
This is the fault of Michal-Angelo; yet I have sometimes thought that
his very materialism, so grand, and so peculiar in character, may
have arisen out of his profound religious feeling, his stern morality, his
lofty conceptions of our mortal, as well as immortal destinies. He
appears to have beheld the human form only in a pure and sublime
point of view; not as the animal man, but as the habitation, fearfully
and wondrously constructed, for the spirit of man,—
“The outward shape,
And unpolluted temple of the
mind.”
This is the reason that Michal-Angelo’s materialism affects us so
differently from that of Rubens. In the first, the predominance of form
attains almost a moral sublimity. In the latter, the predominance of
flesh and blood is debased into physical grossness. Michal-Angelo
believed in the resurrection of THE BODY, emphatically; and in his
Last Judgment the dead rise like Titans, strong to contend and mighty
to suffer. It is the apotheosis of form. In Ruben’s picture of the same
subject (at Munich) the bodily presence of resuscitated life is
revolting, reminding us of the text of St. Paul—“Flesh and blood shall
not inherit the kingdom of God.” Both pictures are
325
æsthetically false, but artistically miracles, and should thus be
considered and appreciated.
I have never looked on those awful figures in the Medici Chapel
without thinking what stupendous intellects must inhabit such
stupendous forms—terrible in their quietude; but they are
supernatural, rather than divine.
“Heidnische Ruhe und Christliche Milde, sie bleiben Dir
fremde;
Alt-testamentisch bist Du, Zürnender, wie ist Dein Gott!”
John Edward Taylor, in his profound and beautiful essay “Michael-
Angelo, a Poet,” says truly that “Dante worshipped the philosophy of
religion, and Michael-Angelo adored the philosophy of art.” The
religion of the one and the art of the other were evolved in a strange
combination of mysticism, materialism, and moral grandeur. The two
men were congenial in character and in genius.
326
A FRAGMENT ON SCULPTURE.
AND ON CERTAIN CHARACTERS IN HISTORY AND POETRY CONSIDERED
AS SUBJECTS OF MODERN ART.
1848.
I Should begin by admitting the position laid down by Frederick
Schlegel, that art and nature are not identical. “Men,” he says,
“traduce nature, who falsely give her the epithet of artistic;” for though
nature comprehends all art, art cannot comprehend all nature.
Nature, in her sources of pleasures and contemplation is infinite; and
art, as her reflection in human works, finite. Nature is boundless in
her powers, exhaustless in her variety; the powers of art and its
capabilities of variety in production are bounded on every side.
Nature herself, the infinite,
327
has circumscribed the bounds of finite art; the one is the divinity; the
other, the priestess. And if poetic art in the interpreting of nature
share in her infinitude, yet in representing nature through material,
form, and colour, she is,—oh, how limited!
If each of the forms of poetic art has its law of limitation as
determined as the musical scale, narrowest of all are the limitations of
sculpture, to which, notwithstanding, we give the highest place; and it
is in regard to sculpture, we find most frequently those mistakes
which arise from a want of knowledge of the true principles of art.
Admitting, then, as necessary and immutable, the limitations of the art
of sculpture as to the management of the material in giving form and
expression; its primal laws of repose and simplicity; its rejection of the
complex and conventional; its bounded capabilities as to choice of
subject; must we also admit, with some of the most celebrated critics
of art, that there is but one style of sculpture, the Greek? And that
every deviation from pure Greek art must be regarded as a
depravation and perversion of the powers and subjects of sculpture? I
do not see that this follows.
It is absolute that Greek art reached long ago the term of its
development. In so far as regards the
328
principles of beauty and execution, it can go no farther. We may
stand and look at the relics of the Parthenon in awe and in despair;
we can do neither more, nor better. But we have not done with Greek
sculpture. What in it is purely ideal, is eternal; what is conventional, is
in accordance with the primal conditions of all imitative art. Therefore
though it may have reached the point at which development stops,
and though its capability of adaptation be limited by necessary laws;
still its all-beautiful, its immortal imagery is ever near us and around
us; still “doth the old feeling bring back the old names,” and with the
old names, the forms; still, in those old familiar forms we continue to
clothe all that is loveliest in visible nature; still, in all our associations
with Greek art—
“’Tis Jupiter who brings whate’er is great,
And Venus who brings every thing that’s
fair.”
That the supreme beauty of Greek art—that the majestic significance
of the classical myths—will ever be to the educated mind and eye as
things indifferent and worn out, I cannot believe.
But on the other hand it may well be doubted whether the
impersonation of the Greek allegories in the purest forms of Greek art
will ever give intense pleasure to the people, or ever speak home
329
to the hearts of the men and women of these times. And this not from
the want of an innate taste and capacity in the minds of the masses—
not because ignorance has “frozen the genial current in their souls”—
not merely through a vulgar preference for mechanical imitation of
common and familiar forms; but from other causes not transient—not
accidental. A classical education is not now, as heretofore, the only
education given; and through an honest and intense sympathy with
the life of their own experience, and through a dislike to vicious
associations, though clothed in classical language and classical
forms, thence is it that the people have turned with a sense of relief
from gods and goddesses, Ledas and Antiopes, to shepherds and
shepherdesses, groups of Charity, and young ladies in the character
of Innocence,—harmless, picturesque inanities, bearing the same
relation to classical sculpture that Watts’s hymns bear to Homer and
Sophocles.
Classical attainments of any kind are rare in our English sculptors;
therefore it is, that we find them often quite familiar with the
conventional treatment and outward forms of the usual subjects of
Greek art, without much knowledge of the original poetical
conception, its derivation, or its significance; and equally without any
real appreciation of the idea of which the form is but the vehicle.
Hence they do
330
not seem to be aware how far this original conception is capable of
being varied, modified, animated as it were, with an infusion of fresh
life, without deviating from its essential truth, or transgressing those
narrow limits, within which all sculpture must be bounded in respect
to action and attitude. To express character within these limits is the
grand difficulty. We must remember that too much value given to the
head as the seat of mind, too much expression given to the features
as the exponents of character, must diminish the importance of those
parts of the form on which sculpture mainly depends for its effect on
the imagination. To convey the idea of a complete individuality in a
single figure, and under these restrictions, is the problem to be solved
by the sculptor who aims at originality, yet feels his aspirations
restrained by a fine taste and circumscribed by certain inevitable
associations.
It is therefore a question open to argument and involving
considerations of infinite delicacy and moment, in morals and in art,
whether the old Greek legends, endued as they are with an
imperishable vitality derived from their abstract youth, may not be
susceptible of a treatment in modern art analogous to that which they
have received in modern poetry, where the significant myth, or the
ideal character, without losing its classic grace, has been
331
animated with a purer sentiment, and developed into a higher
expressiveness. Wordsworth’s Dion and Laodomia; Shelley’s version
of the Hymn to Mercury; Goethe’s Iphigenia; Lord Byron’s
Prometheus; Keats’s Hyperion; Barry Cornwall’s Proserpina; are
instances of what I mean in poetry. To do the same thing in art,
requires that our sculptors should stand in the same relation to
Phidias and Praxiteles, that our greatest poets bear to Homer or
Euripides; that they should be themselves poets and interpreters, not
mere translators and imitators.
Further, we all know, that there is often a necessity for conveying
abstract ideas in the forms of art. We have then recourse to allegory;
yet allegorical statues are generally cold and conventional and
addressed to the intellect merely. Now there are occasions, in which
an abstract quality or thought is far more impressively and intelligibly
conveyed by an impersonation than by a personification. I mean, that
Aristides might express the idea of justice; Penelope, that of conjugal
faith; Jonathan and David (or Pylades and Orestes), friendship;
Rizpah, devotion to the memory of the dead; Iphigenia, the voluntary
sacrifice for a good cause; and so of many others; and such figures
would have this advantage, that with the significance of a symbol they
would combine all the powers of a sympathetic reality.
332
HELEN.
I
have never seen any statue of Helen, ancient or modern. Treated in
the right spirit, I can hardly conceive a diviner subject for a sculptor. It
would be a great mistake to represent the Greek Helen merely as a
beautiful and alluring woman. This, at least, is not the Homeric
conception of the character, which has a wonderful and fascinating
individuality, requiring the utmost delicacy and poetic feeling to
comprehend, and rare artistic skill to realise. The oft-told story of the
Grecian painter, who, to create a Helen, assembled some twenty of
the fairest models he could find, and took from each a limb or a
feature, in order to compose from their separate beauties an ideal of
perfection,—this story, if it were true, would only prove that even
Zeuxis could make a great mistake. Such a combination of
heterogeneous elements would be psychologically and artistically
false, and would never give us a Helen.
She has become the ideal type of a fatal, faithless, dissolute woman;
but according to the Greek myth,
333
she is predestined,—at once the instrument and the victim of that fiat
of the gods which had long before decreed the destruction of Troy,
and her to be the cause. She must not only be supremely beautiful,—
“a daughter of the gods, divinely tall, and most divinely fair!”—but as
the offspring of Zeus (the title by which she is so often designated in
the Iliad), as the sister of the great twin demi-gods Castor and Pollux,
she should have the heroic lineaments proper to her Olympian
descent, touched with a pensive shade; for she laments the
calamities which her fatal charms have brought on all who have loved
her, all whom she has loved:—
“Ah! had I died ere to these shores I
fled,
False to my country and my nuptial
bed!”
She shrinks from the reproachful glances of those whom she has
injured; and yet, as it is finely intimated, wherever she appears her
resistless loveliness vanquishes every heart, and changes curses into
blessings. Priam treats her with paternal tenderness; Hector with a
sort of chivalrous respect.
“If some proud brother eyed me with
disdain,
Or scornful sister with her sweeping train,
Thy gentle accents softened all my pain;
Nor was it e’er my fate from thee to find
A deed ungentle or a word unkind.”
Helen, standing on the walls of Troy, and looking sadly over the battle
plain, where the heroes of her
334
forfeited country, her kindred and her friends, are assembled to fight
and bleed for her sake, brings before us an image full of melancholy
sweetness as well as of consummate beauty. Another passage in
which she upbraids Venus as the cause of her fault—not as a mortal
might humbly expostulate with an immortal, but almost on terms of
equality, and even with bitterness,—is yet more characteristic. “For
what,” she asks, tauntingly, “am I reserved? To what new countries
am I destined to carry war and desolation? For what new lover must I
break a second vow? Let me go hence! and if Paris lament my
absence, let Venus console him, and for his sake ascend the skies no
more!” A regretful pathos should mingle with her conscious beauty
and her half-celestial dignity; and, to render her truly, her Greek
elegance should be combined with a deeper and more complex
sentiment than Greek art has usually sought to express.
I am speaking here of Homer’s Helen—the Helen of the Iliad, not the
Helen of the tragedians—not the Helen who for two thousand years
has merely served “to point a moral;” and an artist who should think
to realise the true Homeric conception, should beware of counterfeits,
for such are abroad.2
335
There is a wild Greek myth that it was not the real Helen, but the
phantom of Helen, who fled with Paris, and who caused the
destruction of Troy; while Helen herself was leading, like Penelope, a
pattern life at Memphis. I must confess I prefer the proud humility, the
pathetic elegance of Homer’s Helen, to such jugglery.
It may flatter the pride of virtue, or it may move our religious
sympathies, to look on the forlorn abasement of the Magdalene as
the emblem of penitence; but there are associations connected with
Helen—“sad Helen,” as she calls herself, and as I conceive the
character,—which have a deep tragic significance; and surely there
are localities for which the impersonation of classical art would be
better fitted than that of sacred art.
I do not know of any existing statue of Helen. Nicetas mentions
among the relics of ancient art destroyed when Constantinople was
sacked by the Latins in 1202, a bronze statue of Helen, with long hair
flowing to the waist; and there is mention of an Etruscan figure of her,
with wings (expressive of her celestial origin, for the Etruscans gave
all their gods and demi-gods wings): in Müller I find these two only.
There are likewise busts; and the story of Helen, and the various
events of her life, occur perpetually on the antique gems, bas-reliefs,
and painted vases. The most frequent subject is her
336
abduction by Paris. A beautiful subject for a bas-relief, and one I
believe not yet treated, would be Helen and Priam mourning over the
lifeless form of Hector; yet the difficulty of preserving the simple
sculptural treatment, and at the same time discriminating between
this and other similar funereal groups, would render it perhaps a
better subject for a picture, as admitting then of such scenery and
accessories as would at once determine the signification.
PENELOPE. ALCESTIS. LAODAMIA.
Statues of Penelope and Helen might stand in beautiful and
expressive contrast; but it is a contrast which no profane or prosaic
hand should attempt to realise. Penelope is all woman in her
tenderness and her truth; Helen, half a goddess in the midst of error
and remorse.
Nor is Penelope the only character which might stand as a type of
conjugal fidelity in contrasted companionship with Helen: Alcestis,
who died for
337
her husband; or, better still, Laodamia, whose intense love and
longing recalled hers from the shades below, are susceptible of the
most beautiful statuesque treatment; only we must bear in mind that
the leading motif in the Alcestis is duty, in the Laodamia, love.
I remember a bas-relief in the Vatican, which represents Hermes
restoring Protesilaus to his mourning wife. The interview was granted
for three hours only; and when the hero was taken from her a second
time, she died on the threshhold of her palace. This is a frequent and
appropriate subject for sarcophagi and funereal vases. But there
exists, I believe, no single statue commemorative of the wife’s
passionate devotion.
The modern sculptor should penetrate his fancy with the sentiment of
Wordsworth’s Laodamia.
While the pen is in my hand I may remark that two of the stanzas in
the Laodamia have been altered, and, as it seems to me, not
improved, since the first edition. Originally the poem opened thus:
“With sacrifice, before the rising morn
Perform’d, my slaughter’d lord have I
required;
And in thick darkness, amid shades forlorn,
Him of the infernal Gods have I desired:
Celestial pity I again implore;
Restore him to my sight—great Jove,
restore!”
338
Altered thus, and comparatively flat:—
“With sacrifice before the rising morn
Vows have I made, by fruitless hope
inspired;
And from the infernal Gods, mid shades
forlorn
Of night, my slaughtered lord have I
required:
Celestial pity I again implore;
Restore him to my sight—great Jove,
restore!”
In the early edition the last stanza but one stood thus:—
“Ah! judge her gently who so deeply loved!
Her who, in reason’s spite, yet without
crime,
Was in a trance of passion thus removed;
Delivered from the galling yoke of time,
And these frail elements,—to gather
flowers
Of blissful quiet ’mid unfading bowers!”
In the later editions thus altered, and, to my taste, spoiled:—
“By no weak pity might the Gods be
moved;
She who thus perish’d not without the
crime
Of lovers that in Reason’s spite have
loved,
Was doomed to wander in a grosser clime
Apart from happy ghosts, that gather
flowers
Of blissful quiet ’mid unfading bowers.”
Altered, probably, because Virgil has introduced the shade of
Laodamia among the criminal and unhappy lovers,—an instance of
extraordinary bad taste in the Roman poet; whatever may have been
her faults, she surely deserved to be placed in better company than
Phædra and Pasiphäe. Wordsworth’s
339
intuitive feeling and taste were true in the first instance, and he might
have trusted to them. In my own copy of Wordsworth I have been
careful to mark the original reading in justice to the original Laodamia.
HIPPOLYTUS. NEOPTOLEMUS.
I have never met with a statue, ancient or modern, of Hippolytus; the
finest possible ideal of a Greek youth, touched with some individual
characteristics which are peculiarly fitted for sculpture. He is a hunter,
not a warrior; a tamer of horses, not a combatant with spear and
shield. He should have the slight, agile build of a young Apollo, but
nothing of the God’s effeminacy; on the contrary, there should be an
infusion of the severe beauty of his Amazonian mother, with that
sedateness and modesty which should express the votary and
companion of Diana;
340
while, as the fated victim of Venus, whom he had contemned, and of
his stepmother Phædra, whom he had repulsed, there should be a
kind of melancholy in his averted features. A hound and implements
of the chase would be the proper accessories, and the figure should
be undraped, or nearly so.
A sculptor who should be tempted to undertake this fine, and, as I
think, untried subject—at least as a single figure—must begin by
putting Racine out of his mind, whose “Seigneur Hippolyte” makes
sentimental love to the “Princesse Aricie,” and must penetrate his
fancy with the conception of Euripides.
I find in Schlegel’s “Essais littéraires,” a few lines which will assist the
fancy of the artist, in representing the person and character of
Hippolytus.
“Quant à l’Hippolyte d’Euripide il a une teinte si divine que pour le
sentir dignement il faut, pour ainsi dire, être initié dans les mystères
de la beauté, avoir respiré l’air de la Grèce. Rappelez vous ce que
l’antiquité nous a transmis de plus accompli parmi les images d’une
jeunesse héroïque, les Dioscures de Monte-Cavallo, le Méléagre et
l’Apollon du Vatican. Le caractère d’Hippolyte occupe dans la poësie
à peu près la même place que ces statues dans la sculpture.” “On
peut remarquer dans plusieurs beautés idéales de l’antique que les