A Treatise of Human Nature by David Hume, - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

Those political writers, who have had recourse to a promise, or original

contract, as the source of our allegiance to government, intended to

establish a principle, which is perfectly just and reasonable; though

the reasoning, upon which they endeavoured to establish it, was

fallacious and sophistical. They would prove, that our submission to

government admits of exceptions, and that an egregious tyranny in the

rulers is sufficient to free the subjects from all ties of allegiance.

Since men enter into society, say they, and submit themselves to

government, by their free and voluntary consent, they must have in view

certain advantages, which they propose to reap from it, and for which

they are contented to resign their native liberty. There is, therefore,

something mutual engaged on the part of the magistrate, viz, protection

and security; and it is only by the hopes he affords of these

advantages, that he can ever persuade men to submit to him. But

when instead of protection and security, they meet with tyranny and

oppression, they are freeed from their promises, (as happens in all

conditional contracts) and return to that state of liberty, which

preceded the institution of government. Men would never be so foolish as

to enter into such engagements as should turn entirely to the advantage

of others, without any view of bettering their own condition. Whoever

proposes to draw any profit from our submission, must engage himself,

either expressly or tacitly, to make us reap some advantage from his

authority; nor ought he to expect, that without the performance of his

part we will ever continue in obedience.

I repeat it: This conclusion is just, though the principles be

erroneous; and I flatter myself, that I can establish the same

conclusion on more reasonable principles. I shall not take such a

compass, in establishing our political duties, as to assert, that men

perceive the advantages of government; that they institute government

with a view to those advantages; that this institution requires a

promise of obedience; which imposes a moral obligation to a certain

degree, but being conditional, ceases to be binding, whenever the other

contracting party performs not his part of the engagement. I perceive,

that a promise itself arises entirely from human conventions, and is

invented with a view to a certain interest. I seek, therefore, some such

interest more immediately connected with government, and which may be

at once the original motive to its institution, and the source of our

obedience to it. This interest I find to consist in the security and

protection, which we enjoy in political society, and which we can never

attain, when perfectly free and independent. As interest, therefore, is

the immediate sanction of government, the one can have no longer being

than the other; and whenever the civil magistrate carries his oppression

so far as to render his authority perfectly intolerable, we are no

longer bound to submit to it. The cause ceases; the effect must cease

also.

So far the conclusion is immediate and direct, concerning the natural

obligation which we have to allegiance. As to the moral obligation, we

may observe, that the maxim would here be false, that when the cause

ceases, the effect must cease also. For there is a principle of human

nature, which we have frequently taken notice of, that men are mightily

addicted to general rules, and that we often carry our maxims beyond

those reasons, which first induced us to establish them.

Where cases

are similar in many circumstances, we are apt to put them on the same

footing, without considering, that they differ in the most material

circumstances, and that the resemblance is more apparent than real. It

may, therefore, be thought, that in the case of allegiance our moral

obligation of duty will not cease, even though the natural obligation of

interest, which is its cause, has ceased; and that men may be bound by

conscience to submit to a tyrannical government against their own and

the public interest. And indeed, to the force of this argument I so far

submit, as to acknowledge, that general rules commonly extend beyond

the principles, on which they are founded; and that we seldom make any

exception to them, unless that exception have the qualities of a general

rule, and be founded on very numerous and common instances. Now this I

assert to be entirely the present case. When men submit to the authority

of others, it is to procure themselves some security against the

wickedness and injustice of men, who are perpetually carried, by their

unruly passions, and by their present and immediate interest, to the

violation of all the laws of society. But as this imperfection is

inherent in human nature, we know that it must attend men in all their

states and conditions; and that these, whom we chuse for rulers, do not

immediately become of a superior nature to the rest of mankind, upon

account of their superior power and authority. What we expect from them

depends not on a change of their nature but of their situation, when

they acquire a more immediate interest in the preservation of order and

the execution of justice. But besides that this interest is only more

immediate in the execution of justice among their subjects; besides

this, I say, we may often expect, from the irregularity of human nature,

that they will neglect even this immediate interest, and be transported

by their passions into all the excesses of cruelty and ambition.. Our

general knowledge of human nature, our observation of the past history

of mankind, our experience of present times; all these causes must

induce us to open the door to exceptions, and must make us conclude,

that we may resist the more violent effects of supreme power, without

any crime or injustice.

Accordingly we may observe, that this is both the general practice and

principle of mankind, and that no nation, that coued find any remedy,

ever yet suffered the cruel ravages of a tyrant, or were blamed for

their resistance. Those who took up arms against Dionysius or Nero, or

Philip the second, have the favour of every reader in the perusal of

their history: and nothing but the most violent perversion of common

sense can ever lead us to condemn them. It is certain, therefore, that

in all our notions of morals we never entertain such an absurdity as

that of passive obedience, but make allowances for resistance in the

more flagrant instances of tyranny and oppression. The general opinion

of mankind has some authority in all cases; but in this of morals it

is perfectly infallible. Nor is it less infallible, because men cannot

distinctly explain the principles, on which it is founded. Few persons

can carry on this train of reasoning: Government is a mere human invention for the interest of society. Where

the tyranny of the governor removes this interest, it also removes the

natural obligation to obedience. The moral obligation is founded on the

natural, and therefore must cease where that ceases; especially where

the subject is such as makes us foresee very many occasions wherein the

natural obligation may cease, and causes us to form a kind of general

rule for the regulation of our conduct in such occurrences.

But though this train of reasoning be too subtile for the vulgar, it is

certain, that all men have an implicit notion of it, and are sensible,

that they owe obedience to government merely on account of the public

interest; and at the same time, that human nature is so subject to

frailties and passions, as may easily pervert this institution, and

change their governors into tyrants and public enemies.

If the sense of

common interest were not our original motive to obedience, I would fain

ask, what other principle is there in human nature capable of subduing

the natural ambition of men, and forcing them to such a submission?

Imitation and custom are not sufficient. For the question still recurs,

what motive first produces those instances of submission, which we

imitate, and that train of actions, which produces the custom? There

evidently is no other principle than public interest; and if interest

first produces obedience to government, the obligation to obedience

must cease, whenever the interest ceases, in any great degree, and in a

considerable number of instances.

SECT. X OF THE OBJECTS OF ALLEGIANCE

But though, on some occasions, it may be justifiable, both in sound

politics and morality, to resist supreme power, it is certain, that in

the ordinary course of human affairs nothing can be more pernicious

and criminal; and that besides the convulsions, which always attend

revolutions, such a practice tends directly to the subversion of all

government, and the causing an universal anarchy and confusion among

mankind. As numerous and civilized societies cannot subsist without

government, so government is entirely useless without an exact

obedience. We ought always to weigh the advantages, which we reap from

authority, against the disadvantages; and by this means we shall become

more scrupulous of putting in practice the doctrine of resistance. The

common rule requires submission; and it is only in cases of grievous

tyranny and oppression, that the exception can take place.

Since then such a blind submission is commonly due to magistracy, the

next question is, to whom it is due, and whom we are to regard as our

lawful magistrates? In order to answer this question, let us recollect

what we have already established concerning the origin of government and

political society. When men have once experienced the impossibility

of preserving any steady order in society, while every one is his own

master, and violates or observes the laws of society, according to his

present interest or pleasure, they naturally run into the invention of

government, and put it out of their own power, as far as possible, to

transgress the laws of society. Government, therefore, arises from the

same voluntary conversation of men; and it is evident, that the same

convention, which establishes government, will also determine the

persons who are to govern, and will remove all doubt and ambiguity in

this particular. And the voluntary consent of men must here have the

greater efficacy, that the authority of the magistrate does at first

stand upon the foundation of a promise of the subjects, by which they

bind themselves to obedience; as in every other contract or engagement.

The same promise, then, which binds them to obedience, ties them down to

a particular person, and makes him the object of their allegiance.

But when government has been established on this footing for some

considerable time, and the separate interest, which we have in

submission, has produced a separate sentiment of morality, the case

is entirely altered, and a promise is no longer able to determine the

particular magistrate since it is no longer considered as the foundation

of government. We naturally suppose ourselves born to submission; and

imagine, that such particular persons have a right to command, as we on

our part are bound to obey. These notions of right and obligation are

derived from nothing but the advantage we reap from government, which

gives us a repugnance to practise resistance ourselves, and makes us

displeased with any instance of it in others. But here it is remarkable,

that in this new state of affairs, the original sanction of government,

which is interest, is not admitted to determine the persons, whom we are

to obey, as the original sanction did at first, when affairs were on

the footing of a promise. A promise fixes and determines the persons,

without any uncertainty: But it is evident, that if men were to regulate

their conduct in this particular, by the view of a peculiar interest,

either public or private, they would involve themselves in endless

confusion, and would render all government, in a great measure,

ineffectual. The private interest of every one is different; and though

the public interest in itself be always one and the same, yet it becomes

the source of as great dissentions, by reason of the different opinions

of particular persons concerning it. The same interest, therefore,

which causes us to submit to magistracy, makes us renounce itself in

the choice of our magistrates, and binds us down to a certain form of

government, and to particular persons, without allowing us to aspire to

the utmost perfection in either. The case is here the same as in that

law of nature concerning the stability of possession. It is highly

advantageous, and even absolutely necessary to society, that possession

should be stable; and this leads us to the establishment of such a rule:

But we find, that were we to follow the same advantage, in assigning

particular possessions to particular persons, we should disappoint

our end, and perpetuate the confusion, which that rule is intended to

prevent. We must, therefore, proceed by general rules, and regulate

ourselves by general interests, in modifying the law of nature

concerning the stability of possession. Nor need we fear, that our

attachment to this law will diminish upon account of the seeming

frivolousness of those interests, by which it is determined. The impulse

of the mind is derived from a very strong interest; and those other more

minute interests serve only to direct the motion, without adding

any thing to it, or diminishing from it. It is the same case with

government. Nothing is more advantageous to society than such an

invention; and this interest is sufficient to make us embrace it with

ardour and alacrity; though we are obliged afterwards to regulate and

direct our devotion to government by several considerations, which are

not of the same importance, and to chuse our magistrates without having

in view any particular advantage from the choice.

The first of those principles I shall take notice of, as a foundation of

the right of magistracy, is that which gives authority to all the most

established governments of the world without exception: I mean, long

possession in any one form of government, or succession of princes. It

is certain, that if we remount to the first origin of every nation,

we shall find, that there scarce is any race of kings, or form of a

commonwealth, that is not primarily founded on usurpation and rebellion,

and whose title is not at first worse than doubtful and uncertain. Time

alone gives solidity to their right; and operating gradually on the

minds of men, reconciles them to any authority, and makes it seem just

and reasonable. Nothing causes any sentiment to have a greater influence

upon us than custom, or turns our imagination more strongly to any

object. When we have been long accustomed to obey any set of men,

that general instinct or tendency, which we have to suppose a moral

obligation attending loyalty, takes easily this direction, and chuses

that set of men for its objects. It is interest which gives the general

instinct; but it is custom which gives the particular direction.

And here it is observable, that the same length of time has a different

influence on our sentiments of morality, according to its different

influence on the mind. We naturally judge of every thing by comparison;

and since in considering the fate of kingdoms and republics, we embrace

a long extent of time, a small duration has not in this case a like

influence on our sentiments, as when we consider any other object. One

thinks he acquires a right to a horse, or a suit of cloaths, in a very

short time; but a century is scarce sufficient to establish any

new government, or remove all scruples in the minds of the subjects

concerning it. Add to this, that a shorter period of time will suffice

to give a prince a title to any additional power he may usurp, than will

serve to fix his right, where the whole is an usurpation. The kings of

France have not been possessed of absolute power for above two reigns;

and yet nothing will appear more extravagant to Frenchmen than to

talk of their liberties. If we consider what has been said concerning

accession, we shall easily account for this phaenomenon.

When there is no form of government established by long possession,

the present possession is sufficient to supply its place, and may

be regarded as the second source of all public authority. Right

to authority is nothing but the constant possession of authority,

maintained by the laws of society and the interests of mankind; and

nothing can be more natural than to join this constant possession to the

present one, according to the principles abovementioned. If the same

principles did not take place with regard to the property of private

persons, it was because these principles were counter-ballanced by

very strong considerations of interest; when we observed, that all

restitution would by that means be prevented, and every violence be

authorized and protected. And though the same motives may seem to

have force, with regard to public authority, yet they are opposed by a

contrary interest; which consists in the preservation of peace, and the

avoiding of all changes, which, however they may be easily produced in

private affairs, are unavoidably attended with bloodshed and confusion,

where the public is interested.

Any one, who finding the impossibility of accounting for the right of

the present possessor, by any received system of ethics, should resolve

to deny absolutely that right, and assert, that it is not authorized

by morality, would be justly thought to maintain a very extravagant

paradox, and to shock the common sense and judgment of mankind. No maxim

is more conformable, both to prudence and morals, than to submit quietly

to the government, which we find established in the country where we

happen to live, without enquiring too curiously into its origin and

first establishment. Few governments will bear being examined so

rigorously. How many kingdoms are there at present in the world, and

how many more do we find in history, whose governors have no better

foundation for their authority than that of present possession? To

confine ourselves to the Roman and Grecian empire; is it not evident,

that the long succession of emperors, from the dissolution of the Roman

liberty, to the final extinction of that empire by the Turks, coued not

so much as pretend to any other title to the empire? The election of the

senate was a mere form, which always followed the choice of the legions;

and these were almost always divided in the different provinces, and

nothing but the sword was able to terminate the difference. It was by

the sword, therefore, that every emperor acquired, as well as defended

his right; and we must either say, that all the known world, for so

many ages, had no government, and owed no allegiance to any one, or

must allow, that the right of the stronger, in public affairs, is to be

received as legitimate, and authorized by morality, when not opposed by

any other title.

The right of conquest may be considered as a third source of the

title of sovereigns. This right resembles very much that of present

possession; but has rather a superior force, being seconded by the

notions of glory and honour, which we ascribe to conquerors, instead

of the sentiments of hatred and detestation, which attend usurpers. Men

naturally favour those they love; and therefore are more apt to ascribe

a right to successful violence, betwixt one sovereign and another, than

to the successful rebellion of a subject against his sovereign.

[Footnote 23 It is not here asserted, that present possession or conquest are sufficient to give a title

against long possession and positive laws but only that they

have some force, and will be able to call the ballance where

the titles are otherwise equal, and will even be sufficient

sometimes to sanctify the weaker title. What degree of force

they have is difficult to determine. I believe all moderate

men will allow, that they have great force in all disputes

concerning the rights of princes.]

When neither long possession, nor present possession, nor conquest take

place, as when the first sovereign, who founded any monarchy, dies; in

that case, the right of succession naturally prevails in their stead,

and men are commonly induced to place the son of their late monarch

on the throne, and suppose him to inherit his father's authority. The

presumed consent of the father, the imitation of the succession to

private families, the interest, which the state has in chusing the

person, who is most powerful, and has the most numerous followers; all

these reasons lead men to prefer the son of their late monarch to any

other person.

[Footnote 24 To prevent mistakes I must observe, that this

case of succession is not the same with that of hereditary

monarchies, where custom has fix'd the right of succession.

These depend upon the principle of long possession above

explain'd.]

These reasons have some weight; but I am persuaded, that to one, who

considers impartially of the matter, it will appear, that there concur

some principles of the imagination, along with those views of interest.

The royal authority seems to be connected with the young prince even in

his father's life-time, by the natural transition of the thought; and

still more after his death: So that nothing is more natural than to

compleat this union by a new relation, and by putting him actually in

possession of what seems so naturally to belong to him.

To confirm this we may weigh the following phaenomena, which are pretty

curious in their kind. In elective monarchies the right of succession

has no place by the laws and settled custom; and yet its influence is

so natural, that it is impossible entirely to exclude it from the

imagination, and render the subjects indifferent to the son of their

deceased monarch. Hence in some governments of this kind, the choice

commonly falls on one or other of the royal family; and in some

governments they are all excluded. Those contrary phaenomena proceed

from the same principle. Where the royal family is excluded, it is

from a refinement in politics, which makes people sensible of their

propensity to chuse a sovereign in that family, and gives them a

jealousy of their liberty, lest their new monarch, aided by this

propensity, should establish his family, and destroy the freedom of

elections for the future.

The history of Artaxerxes, and the younger Cyrus, may furnish us with

some reflections to the same purpose. Cyrus pretended a right to the

throne above his elder brother, because he was born after his father's

accession. I do not pretend, that this reason was valid.

I would only

infer from it, that he would never have made use of such a pretext, were

it not for the qualities of the imagination abovementioned, by which

we are naturally inclined to unite by a new relation whatever objects we

find already united. Artaxerxes had an advantage above his brother, as

being the eldest son, and the first in succession: But Cyrus was more

closely related to the royal authority, as being begot after his father

was invested with it.

Should it here be pretended, that the view of convenience may be

the source of all the right of succession, and that men gladly take

advantage of any rule, by which they can fix the successor of their late

so