A history of Jewish Medieval Philosophy by Isaac Husik - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

10. Being in a body means one of two things: being in it as an accident, or as constituting the essence of the body, like a

natural form. Both are corporeal powers.

11. Some things which are in a body are divided with the division of the body. They are then divided per accidens, like

colors and other powers extending throughout the body. Some of the things which constitute the body are not divisible at

all, like soul and intellect.

12. Every power which extends throughout a body is finite, because all body is finite.

13. None of the kinds of change mentioned in 4 is continuous except motion of translation; and of this only circular

motion.

14. Motion of translation is the first by nature of the motions. For genesis and decay presuppose qualitative change; and

qualitative change presupposes the approach of the agent causing the change to the thing undergoing the change. And

there is no growth or diminution without antecedent genesis and decay.

15. Time is an accident following motion and connected with it. The one cannot exist without the other. No motion except

in time, and time cannot be conceived except with motion. Whatever has no motion does not come under time.

16. Whatever is incorporeal cannot be subject to number, unless it is a corporeal power; in which case the individual

powers are numbered with their matters or bearers. Hence the separate forms or Intelligences, which are neither bodies

nor corporeal powers, cannot have the conception of number connected with them, except when they are related to one

another as cause and effect.

17. Everything that moves, necessarily has a mover, either outside, like the hand moving the stone, or inside like the

animal body, which consists of a mover, the soul, and a moved, the body proper. Every mobile of the last kind is called a

self-moving thing. This means that the motor element in the thing is part of the whole thing in motion.

18. If anything passes from potentiality to actuality, the agent that caused this must be outside the thing. For if it were

inside and there was no obstruction, the thing would never be potential, but always actual; and if there was an

obstruction, which was removed, the agency which removed the obstruction is the cause which caused the thing to pass

from potentiality to actuality.

19. Whatever has a cause for its existence is a "possible" existent in so far as itself is concerned. If the cause is there,

the thing exists; if not, it does not. Possible here means not necessary.

20. Whatever is a necessary existent in itself, has no cause for its existence.

21. Every composite has the cause of its existence in the composition. Hence it is not in itself a necessary existent; for its

existence is dependent upon the existence of its constituent parts and upon their composition.

22. All body is composed necessarily of two things, matter and form; and it necessarily has accidents, viz., quantity,

figure, situation.

23. Whatever is potential and has in it a possibility may at some time not exist as an actuality.

24. Whatever is potential is necessarily possessed of matter, for possibility is always in matter.

25. The principles of an individual compound substance are matter and form; and there must be an agent, i. e., a mover

which moves the object or the underlying matter until it prepares it to receive the form. This need not be the ultimate

mover, but a proximate one having a particular function. The idea of Aristotle is that matter cannot move itself. This is the

great principle which leads us to investigate into the existence of the first mover.

Of these twenty-five propositions, Maimonides continues, some are clear after a little reflection, some again require many

premises and proofs, but they are all proved in the Physics and Metaphysics of Aristotle and his commentators. My

purpose here is, as I said, not to reproduce the writings of the philosophers. I will simply mention those principles which

we must have for our purpose. I must add, however, one more proposition, which Aristotle thinks is true and more

deserving of belief than anything else. We will grant him this by way of hypothesis until we explain what we intend to

prove. The proposition is:

26. Time and motion are eternal and actual. Hence there must be a body moving eternally and existing actually. This is

the matter constituting the substance of the heavenly bodies. Hence the heavens are not subject to genesis and decay,

for their motion is eternal. This presupposes the possibility of accidental infinity (cf. above, p. 251). Aristotle regards this

as true, though it does not seem to me that he claims he has proved it. His followers and commentators maintain that it is

a necessary proposition and demonstrated. The Mutakallimun, on the other hand, think it is impossible that there should

be an infinite number of states in succession (cf. ibid.). It seems to me it is neither necessary nor impossible, but

possible. This is, however, not the place to discuss it.[273]

Now follows the classical proof of the existence of God from motion. It is in essence the same as that given by Ibn Daud,

but much more elaborate. We shall try to simplify it as much as possible. The numbers in parentheses in the sequel refer

to the preliminary propositions above given.

We start with something that is known, namely, the motion we see in the sublunar world, the motion which is involved in

all the processes of genesis and decay and change generally. This motion must have a mover (25). This mover must

have another mover to move it, and this would lead us to infinity, which is impossible (3). We find, however, that all

motion here below ends with the motion of the heaven. Let us take an example. The wind is blowing through an opening

in the wall. I take a stone and stop up the hole. Here the stone is moved by the hand, the hand by the tendons, the

tendons by the nerves, the nerves by the veins, the veins by the natural heat, the natural heat by the animal soul, the

animal soul by a purpose, namely, to stop the hole from which the wind comes, the purpose by the wind, the wind by the

motion of the heavenly sphere. But this is not the end. The sphere must also have a mover (17). This mover is either

outside the sphere it moves or within it. If it is something outside, it is either again a body like the sphere, or an

incorporeal thing, a "Separate Intelligence." If the mover of the sphere is something within the sphere, two alternatives

are again possible. The internal moving power of the sphere may be a corporeal force extended throughout the body of

the sphere and divisible with it like heat, or an indivisible power like soul or intellect (10, 11). We thus have four

possibilities in all. The mover of the heavenly sphere may be (a) a body external to the sphere; (b) a separate incorporeal

substance; (c) an internal corporeal power divisible with the division of the sphere; (d) an internal indivisible power. Of

these four, (a) is impossible. For if the mover of the sphere is another body, it is likewise in motion (9) and must have

another to move it, which, if a body, must have another, and so on ad infinitum, which is impossible (2). The third

hypothesis, (c), is likewise impossible. For as the sphere is a body it is finite (1), and its power is also finite (12), since it

is divisible with the body of the sphere (11). Hence it cannot move infinitely (26). Nor can we adopt the last alternative,

(d). For a soul residing within the sphere could not alone be the cause of continuous motion. For a soul that moves its

body is itself in motion per accidens (6); and whatever moves per accidens must necessarily sometime stop (8), and with

it the thing set in motion by it will stop also. There is thus only one alternative left, (b), viz., that the cause of the motion of

the sphere is a "separate" (i. e., incorporeal) power, which is itself not subject to motion either per se or per accidens;

hence it is indivisible and unchangeable (7, 5). This is God. He cannot be two or more, for "separate" essences which

are not body are not subject to number unless one is cause and the other effect (16). It follows, too, that he is not subject

to time, for there is no time without motion (15).

We have thus proved with one stroke God's existence as well as his unity and incorporeality. But, it will be observed, if

not for the twenty-sixth proposition concerning the eternity of motion, which implies an infinite power, we should not have

been forced to the alternative (b), and could have adopted (c) as well as (d). That is, we might have concluded that God

is the soul of the heavenly sphere resident within it, or even that he is a corporeal force pervading the extension of the

sphere as heat pervades an ordinary body. But we must admit that in this way we prove only the existence of a God who

is the cause of the heavenly motions, and through these of the processes of genesis and decay, hence of all the life of

our sublunar world. This is not the God of Jewish tradition, who creates out of nothing, who is the cause of the being of

the universe as well as of its life processes. Maimonides was aware of this defect in the Aristotelian view, and he later

repudiates the Stagirite's theory of eternal motion on philosophical as well as religious grounds. Before, however, we

speak of Maimonides's attitude in this matter, we must for completeness' sake briefly mention three other proofs for the

existence of God as given by Maimonides. They are not strictly Aristotelian, though they are based upon Peripatetic

principles cited above and due to the Arabian commentators of Aristotle.

The second proof is as follows. If we find a thing composed of two elements, and one of these elements is also found

separately, it follows that the other element is found separately also. Now we frequently find the two elements of causing

motion and being moved combined in the same object. And we also find things which are moved only, but do not cause

motion, as for example matter, or the stone in the last proof. It stands to reason therefore that there is something that

causes motion without being itself subject to motion. Not being subject to motion, it is indivisible, incorporeal and not

subject to time, as above.

The third proof is based upon the idea of necessary existence. There is no doubt that there are existing things, for

example the things we perceive with our senses. Now either all things are incapable of decay, or all are subject to

genesis and decay, or some are and some are not. The first is evidently untrue for we see things coming into, and

passing out, of being. The second hypothesis is likewise untrue. For if all things are subject to genesis and decay, there

is a possibility that at some time all things might cease to be and nothing should exist at all. But as the coming and going

of individuals in the various species in the world has been going on from eternity, the possibility just spoken of must have

been realized—a possibility that is never realized is not a possibility—and nothing existed at all at that moment. But in

that case how could they ever have come into being, since there was nothing to bring them into being? And yet they do

exist, as ourselves for example and everything else. There is only one alternative left, therefore, and that is that beside

the great majority of things subject to genesis and decay, there is a being not subject to change, a necessary existent,

and ultimately one that exists by virtue of its own necessity (19).

Whatever is necessary per se can have no cause for its existence (20) and can have no multiplicity in itself (21); hence it

is neither a body nor a corporeal power (12).

We can also prove easily that there cannot be two necessary existents per se. For in that case the element of necessary

existence would be something added to the essence of each, and neither would then be necessary per se, but per that

element of necessary existence which is common to both.

The last argument against dualism may also be formulated as follows. If there are two Gods, they must have something

in common—that in virtue of which they are Gods—and something in which they differ, which makes them two and not

one. If each of them has in addition to divinity a differential element, they are both composite, and neither is the first

cause or the necessary existent (19). If one of them only has this differentia, then this one is composite and is not the first

cause.

The fourth proof is very much like the first, but is based upon the ideas of potentiality and actuality instead of motion. But

when we consider that Aristotle defines motion in terms of potentiality and actuality, the fourth proof is identical with the

first. It reads in Maimonides as follows: We see constantly things existing potentially and coming into actuality. Every

such thing must have an agent outside (18). It is clear, too, that this agent was first an agent potentially and then became

one actually. This potentiality was due either to an obstacle in the agent himself or to the absence of a certain relation

between the agent and its effect. In order that the potential agent may become an actual agent, there is need of another

agent to remove the obstacle or to bring about the needed relation between the agent and the thing to be acted upon.

This agent requires another agent, and so it goes ad infinitum. As this is impossible, we must stop somewhere with an

agent that is always actual and in one condition. This agent cannot be material, but must be a "separate" (24). But the

separate in which there is no kind of potentiality and which exists per se, is God. As we have already proved him

incorporeal, he is one (16).[274]

We must now analyze the expressions incorporeal and one, and see what in strictness they imply, and how our logical

deductions agree with Scripture. Many persons, misled by the metaphorical expressions in the Bible, think of God as

having a body with organs and senses on the analogy of ours. Others are not so crude as to think of God in

anthropomorphic terms, nor are they polytheists, and yet for the same reason, namely, misunderstanding of Scriptural

expressions, ascribe a plurality of essential attributes to God. We must therefore insist on the absolute incorporeality of

God and explain the purpose of Scripture in expressing itself in anthropomorphic terms, and on the other hand

emphasize the absolute unity of God against the believers in essential attributes.

Belief in God as body or as liable to suffer affection is worse than idolatry. For the idolater does not deny the existence of

God; he merely makes the mistake of supposing that the image of his own construction resembles a being which

mediates between him and God. And yet because this leads to erroneous belief on the part of the people, who are

inclined to worship the image itself instead of God (for the people cannot discriminate between the outward act and its

idea), the Bible punishes idolatry with death, and calls the idolater a man who angers God. How much more serious is

the error of him who thinks God is body! He entertains an error regarding the nature of God directly, and surely causes

the anger of God to burn. Habit and custom and the evidence of the literal understanding of the Biblical text are no more

an excuse for this erroneous belief than they are for idolatry; for the idolater, too, has been brought up in his wrong ideas

and is confirmed in them by some false notions. If a man is not himself able to reason out the truth, there is no excuse for

his refusing to listen to one who has reasoned it out. A person is not an unbeliever for not being able to prove the

incorporeality of God. He is an unbeliever if he thinks God is corporeal.[275]

The expressions in the Bible which have led many to err so grievously in their conceptions of God are due to a desire on

the part of their authors to show all people, the masses including women and children, that God exists and is possessed

of all perfection, that he is existent, living, wise, powerful, and active. Hence it was necessary to speak of him as body,

for this is the only thing that suggests real existence to the masses. It was necessary to endow him with motion, as this

alone denotes life; to ascribe to him seeing, hearing, and so on, in order to indicate that he understands; to represent him

as speaking, in order to show that he communicates with prophets, because to the minds of common people this is the

only way in which ideas are communicated from one person to another. As we are active by our sense of touch, God,

too, is described as doing. He is given a soul, to denote that he is alive. Then as all these activities are among us done

by means of organs, these also are ascribed to God, as feet, hands, ear, eye, nose, mouth, tongue, voice, fingers, palm,

arm. In other words, to show that God has all perfections, certain senses are ascribed to him; and to indicate these

senses the respective organs are related to them, organs of motion to denote life, of sensation to denote understanding,

of touch to denote activity, of speech to denote revelation. As a matter of fact, however, since all these organs and

perceptions and powers in man and animals are due to imperfection and are for the purpose of satisfying various wants

for the preservation of the individual or the species, and God has no wants of any kind, he has no such powers or

organs.[276]

Having disposed of crude anthropomorphism we must now take up the problem of attributes, which endangers the unity.

It is a self-evident truth that an attribute is something different from the essence of a thing. It is an accident added to the

essence. Otherwise it is the thing over again, or it is the definition of the thing and the explanation of the name, and

signifies that the thing is composed of these elements. If we say God has many attributes, it will follow that there are

many eternals. The only belief in true unity is to think that God is one simple substance without composition or multiplicity

of elements, but one in all respects and aspects. Some go so far as to say that the divine attributes are neither God's

essence nor anything outside of his essence. This is absurd. It is saying words which have nothing corresponding to

them in fact. A thing is either the same as another, or it is not the same. There is no other alternative. The imagination is

responsible for this error. Because bodies as we know them always have attributes, they thought that God, too, is made

up of many essential elements or attributes.

Attributes may be of five kinds:

1. The attributes of a thing may be its definition, which denotes its essence as determined by its causes. This everyone

will admit cannot be in God, for God has no cause, hence cannot be defined.

2. An attribute may consist of a part of a definition, as when we say, "man is rational," where the attribute rational is part

of the definition of man, "rational animal" being the whole definition. This can apply to God no more than the first; for if

there is a part in God's essence, he is composite.

3. An attribute may be an expression which characterizes not the essence of the thing but its quality. Quality is one of the

nine categories of accident, and God has no accidents.

4. An attribute may indicate relation, such as father, master, son, slave. At first sight it might seem as if this kind of

attribute may be applicable to God; but after reflection we find that it is not. There can be no relation of time between

God and anything else; because time is the measure of motion, and motion is an accident of body. God is not corporeal.

In the same way it is clear that there cannot be a relation of place between God and other things. But neither can there

be any other kind of relation between God and his creation. For God is a necessary existent, while everything else is a

possible existent. A relation exists only between things of the same proximate species, as between white and black. If the

things have only a common genus, and still more so if they belong to two different genera, there is no relation between

them. If there were a relation between God and other things, he would have the accident of relation, though relation is

the least serious of attributes, since it does not necessitate a multiplicity of eternals, nor change in God's essence owing

to change in the related things.

5. An attribute may characterize a thing by reference to its effects or works, not in the sense that the thing or author of

the effect has acquired a character by reason of the product, like carpenter, painter, blacksmith, but merely in the sense

that he is the one who made a particular thing. An attribute of this kind is far removed from the essence of the thing so

characterized by it; and hence we may apply it to God, provided we remember that the varied effects need not be

produced by different elements in the agent, but are all done by the one essence.

Those who believe in attributes divide them into two classes, and number the following four as essential attributes, not

derived from God's effects like "creator," which denotes God's relation to his work, since God did not create himself. The

four essential attributes about which all agree are, living, powerful, wise, possessed of will. Now if by wise is meant

God's knowledge of himself, there might be some reason for calling it an essential attribute; though in that case it implies

"living," and there is no need of two. But they refer the attribute wise to God's knowledge of the world, and then there is

no reason for calling it an essential attribute any more than the word "creator," for example. In the same way "powerful"

and "having will" cannot refer to himself, but to his actions. We therefore hold that just as we do not say that there is

something additional in his essence by which he created the heavens, something else with which he created the

elements, and a third with which he created the Intelligences, so we do not say that he has one attribute with which he

exercises power, another with which he wills, a third with which he knows, and so on, but his essence is simple and

one.[277]

Four things must be removed from God: (1) corporeality, (2) affection, (3) potentiality, (4) resemblance to his creatures.

The first we have already proved. The second implies change, and the author of the change cannot be the same as he

who suffers the change and feels the affection. If then God were subject to affection, there would be another who would

cause the change in him. So all want must be removed from him; for he who is in want of something is potential, and in

order to pass into actuality requires an agent having that quality in actu. The fourth is also evident; for resemblance

involves relation. As there is no relation between God and ourselves, there is no resemblance. Resemblance can exist

only between things of the same species. All the expressions including "existent" are applied to God and to ourselves in a

homonymous sense (cf. above, p. 240). The use is not even analogical; for in analogy there must be some resemblance

between the things having the same name, but not so here. Existence in things which are determined by causes (and

this includes all that is not God), is not identical with the essence of those things. The essence is that which is expressed

in the definition, whereas the existence or non-existence of the thing so defined is not part of the definition. It is an

accident added to the essence. In God the case is different. His existence has no cause, since he is a necessary

existent; hence his existence is identical with his essence. So we say God exists, but not with existence, as we do.

Similarly he is living, but not with life; knowing, but not with knowledge; powerful, but not with power; wise, but not with

wisdom. Unity and plurality are also accidents of things which are one or many as the case may be. They are accidents

of the category of quantity. God, who is a necessary existent and simple cannot be one any more than many. He is one,

but not with unity. Language is inadequate to express our ideas of God. Wishing to say he is not many, we have to say

he is one; though one as well as many pertains to the accidents of quantity. To correct the inexactness of the expression,

we add, "but not with unity." So we say "eternal" to indicate that he is not "new," though in reality eternal is an accident of

time, which in turn is an accident of motion, the latter being dependent upon body. In reality neither "eternal" nor "new" is

applicable to God. When we say one, we mean merely that there is none other like him; and when Scripture speaks of

him as the first and the last, the meaning is that he does not change.

The only true attributes of God are the negative ones. Negative attributes, too, by excluding the part of the field in which

the thing to be designated is not contained, bring us nearer to the thing itself; though unlike positive attributes they do

not designate any part of the thing itself. God cannot have positive attributes because he has no essence different from

his existence for the attributes to designate, and surely no accidents. Negative attributes are of value in leading us to a

knowledge of God, because in negation no plurality is involved. So when we have proved that there is a being beside

these sensible and intelligible things, and we say he is existent, we mean that his non-existence is unthinkable. In the

same way living means not dead; incorporeal is negative; eternal signifies not caused; powerful means not weak; wise—

not ignorant; willing denotes that creation proceeds from him not by natural necessity like heat from fire or light from the

sun, but with purpose and design and method. All attributes therefore are either derived from God's effects or, if they

have reference to himself, are meant to exclude their opposites, i. e., are really negatives. This does not mean, however,

that God is devoid of a quality which he might have, but in the sense in which we say a ston