An Essay Concerning Human Understanding by John Locke - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

Chapter III

Of General Terms

1. The greatest part of words are general terms. All things that exist being particulars, it may

perhaps be thought reasonable that words, which ought to be conformed to things, should be so

too,--I mean in their signification: but yet we find quite the contrary. The far greatest part of words

that make all languages are general terms: which has not been the effect of neglect or chance, but

of reason and necessity.

2. That every particular thing should have a name for itself is impossible. First, It is impossible that

every particular thing should have a distinct peculiar name. For, the signification and use of words

depending on that connexion which the mind makes between its ideas and the sounds it uses as

signs of them, it is necessary, in the application of names to things, that the mind should have

distinct ideas of the things, and retain also the particular name that belongs to every one, with its

peculiar appropriation to that idea. But it is beyond the power of human capacity to frame and retain

distinct ideas of all the particular things we meet with: every bird and beast men saw; every tree and

plant that affected the senses, could not find a place in the most capacious understanding. If it be

looked on as an instance of a prodigious memory, that some generals have been able to call every

soldier in their army by his proper name, we may easily find a reason why men have never

attempted to give names to each sheep in their flock, or crow that flies over their heads; much less

to call every leaf of plants, or grain of sand that came in their way, by a peculiar name.

3. And would be useless, if it were possible. Secondly, If it were possible, it would yet be useless;

because it would not serve to the chief end of language. Men would in vain heap up names of

particular things, that would not serve them to communicate their thoughts. Men learn names, and

use them in talk with others, only that they may be understood: which is then only done when, by

use or consent, the sound I make by the organs of speech, excites in another man's mind who

hears it, the idea I apply it to in mine, when I speak it. This cannot be done by names applied to

particular things; whereof I alone having the ideas in my mind, the names of them could not be

significant or intelligible to another, who was not acquainted with all those very particular things

which had fallen under my notice.

4. A distinct name for every particular thing, not fitted for enlargement of knowledge. Thirdly, But yet,

granting this also feasible, (which I think is not), yet a distinct name for every particular thing would

not be of any great use for the improvement of knowledge: which, though founded in particular

things, enlarges itself by general views; to which things reduced into sorts, under general names,

are properly subservient. These, with the names belonging to them, come within some compass,

and do not multiply every moment, beyond what either the mind can contain, or use requires. And

therefore, in these, men have for the most part stopped: but yet not so as to hinder themselves from

distinguishing particular things by appropriated names, where convenience demands it. And

therefore in their own species, which they have most to do with, and wherein they have often

occasion to mention particular persons, they make use of proper names; and there distinct

individuals have distinct denominations.

5. What things have proper names, and why. Besides persons, countries also, cities, rivers,

mountains, and other the like distinctions of place have usually found peculiar names, and that for

the same reason; they being such as men have often an occasion to mark particularly, and, as it

were, set before others in their discourses with them. And I doubt not but, if we had reason to

mention particular horses as often as we have to mention particular men, we should have proper

names for the one, as familiar as for the other, and Bucephalus would be a word as much in use as

Alexander. And therefore we see that, amongst jockeys, horses have their proper names to be

known and distinguished by, as commonly as their servants: because, amongst them, there is often

occasion to mention this or that particular horse when he is out of sight.

6. How general words are made. The next thing to be considered is,--How general words come to

be made. For, since all things that exist are only particulars, how come we by general terms; or

where find we those general natures they are supposed to stand for? Words become general by

being made the signs of general ideas: and ideas become general, by separating from them the

circumstances of time and place, and any other ideas that may determine them to this or that

particular existence. By this way of abstraction they are made capable of representing more

individuals than one; each of which having in it a conformity to that abstract idea, is (as we call it) of

that sort.

7. Shown by the way we enlarge our complex ideas from infancy. But, to deduce this a little more

distinctly, it will not perhaps be amiss to trace our notions and names from their beginning, and

observe by what degrees we proceed, and by what steps we enlarge our ideas from our first infancy.

There is nothing more evident, than that the ideas of the persons children converse with (to instance

in them alone) are, like the persons themselves, only particular. The ideas of the nurse and the

mother are well framed in their minds; and, like pictures of them there, represent only those

individuals. The names they first gave to them are confined to these individuals; and the names of

nurse and mamma, the child uses, determine themselves to those persons. Afterwards, when time

and a larger acquaintance have made them observe that there are a great many other things in the

world, that in some common agreements of shape, and several other qualities, resemble their father

and mother, and those persons they have been used to, they frame an idea, which they find those

many particulars do partake in; and to that they give, with others, the name man, for example. And

thus they come to have a general name, and a general idea. Wherein they make nothing new; but

only leave out of the complex idea they had of Peter and James, Mary and Jane, that which is

peculiar to each, and retain only what is common to them all.

8. And further enlarge our complex ideas, by still leaving out properties contained in them. By the

same way that they come by the general name and idea of man, they easily advance to more

general names and notions. For, observing that several things that differ from their idea of man, and

cannot therefore be comprehended under that name, have yet certain qualities wherein they agree

with man, by retaining only those qualities, and uniting them into one idea, they have again another

and more general idea; to which having given a name they make a term of a more comprehensive

extension: which new idea is made, not by any new addition, but only as before, by leaving out the

shape, and some other properties signified by the name man, and retaining only a body, with life,

sense, and spontaneous motion, comprehended under the name animal.

9. General natures are nothing but abstract and partial ideas of more complex ones. That this is the

way whereby men first formed general ideas, and general names to them, I think is so evident, that

there needs no other proof of it but the considering of a man's self, or others, and the ordinary

proceedings of their minds in knowledge. And he that thinks general natures or notions are anything

else but such abstract and partial ideas of more complex ones, taken at first from particular

existences, will, I fear, be at a loss where to find them. For let any one effect, and then tell me,

wherein does his idea of man differ from that of Peter and Paul, or his idea of horse from that of

Bucephalus, but in the leaving out something that is peculiar to each individual, and retaining so

much of those particular complex ideas of several particular existences as they are found to agree

in? Of the complex ideas signified by the names man and horse, leaving out but those particulars

wherein they differ, and retaining only those wherein they agree, and of those making a new distinct

complex idea, and giving the name animal to it, one has a more general term, that comprehends

with man several other creatures. Leave out of the idea of animal, sense and spontaneous motion,

and the remaining complex idea, made up of the remaining simple ones of body, life, and

nourishment, becomes a more general one, under the more comprehensive term, vivens. And, not

to dwell longer upon this particular, so evident in itself; by the same way the mind proceeds to body,

substance, and at last to being, thing, and such universal terms, which stand for any of our ideas

whatsoever. To conclude: this whole mystery of genera and species, which make such a noise in

the schools, and are with justice so little regarded out of them, is nothing else but abstract ideas,

more or less comprehensive, with names annexed to them. In all which this is constant and

unvariable, That every more general term stands for such an idea, and is but a part of any of those

contained under it.

10. Why the genus is ordinarily made use of in definitions. This may show us the reason why, in the

defining of words, which is nothing but declaring their signification, we make use of the genus, or

next general word that comprehends it. Which is not out of necessity, but only to save the labour of

enumerating the several simple ideas which the next general word or genus stands for; or, perhaps,

sometimes the shame of not being able to do it. But though defining by genus and differentia (I

crave leave to use these terms of art, though originally Latin, since they most properly suit those

notions they are applied to), I say, though defining by the genus be the shortest way, yet I think it

may be doubted whether it be the best. This I am sure, it is not the only, and so not absolutely

necessary. For, definition being nothing but making another understand by words what idea the term

defined stands for, a definition is best made by enumerating those simple ideas that are combined

in the signification of the term defined: and if, instead of such an enumeration, men have

accustomed themselves to use the next general term, it has not been out of necessity, or for greater

clearness, but for quickness and dispatch sake. For I think that, to one who desired to know what

idea the word man stood for; if it should be said, that man was a solid extended substance, having

life, sense, spontaneous motion, and the faculty of reasoning, I doubt not but the meaning of the

term man would be as wel understood, and the idea it stands for be at least as clearly made known,

as when it is defined to be a rational animal: which, by the several definitions of animal, vivens, and

corpus, resolves itself into those enumerated ideas. I have, in explaining the term man, followed

here the ordinary definition of the schools; which, though perhaps not the most exact, yet serves

well enough to my present purpose. And one may, in this instance, see what gave occasion to the

rule, that a definition must consist of genus and differentia; and it suffices to show us the little

necessity there is of such a rule, or advantage in the strict observing of it. For, definitions, as has

been said, being only the explaining of one word by several others, so that the meaning or idea it

stands for may be certainly known; languages are not always so made according to the rules of

logic, that every term can have its signification exactly and clearly expressed by two others.

Experience sufficiently satisfies us to the contrary; or else those who have made this rule have done

ill, that they have given us so few definitions conformable to it. But of definitions more in the next

chapter.

11. General and universal are creatures of the understanding, and belong not to the real existence

of things. To return to general words: it is plain, by what has been said, that general and universal

belong not to the real existence of things; but are the inventions and creatures of the understanding,

made by it for its own use, and concern only signs, whether words or ideas. Words are general, as

has been said, when used for signs of general ideas, and so are applicable indifferently to many

particular things; and ideas are general when they are set up as the representatives of many

particular things: but universality belongs not to things themselves, which are all of them particular in

their existence, even those words and ideas which in their signification are general. When therefore

we quit particulars, the generals that rest are only creatures of our own making; their general nature

being nothing but the capacity they are put into, by the understanding, of signifying or representing

many particulars. For the signification they have is nothing but a relation that, by the mind of man, is

added to them.

12. Abstract ideas are the essences of genera and species. The next thing therefore to be

considered is, What kind of signification it is that general words have. For, as it is evident that they

do not signify barely one particular thing; for then they would not be general terms, but proper

names, so, on the other side, it is as evident they do not signify a plurality; for man and men would

then signify the same; and the distinction of numbers (as the grammarians call them) would be

superfluous and useless. That then which general words signify is a sort of things; and each of them

does that, by being a sign of an abstract idea in the mind; to which idea, as things existing are found

to agree, so they come to be ranked under that name, or, which is all one, be of that sort. Whereby it

is evident that the essences of the sorts, or, if the Latin word pleases better, species of things, are

nothing else but these abstract ideas. For the having the essence of any species, being that which

makes anything to be of that species; and the conformity to the idea to which the name is annexed

being that which gives a right to that name; the having the essence, and the having that conformity,

must needs be the same thing: since to be of any species, and to have a right to the name of that

species, is all one. As, for example, to be a man, or of the species man, and to have right to the

name man, is the same thing. Again, to be a man, or of the species man, and have the essence of a

man, is the same thing. Now, since nothing can be a man, or have a right to the name man, but

what has a conformity to the abstract idea the name man stands for, nor anything be a man, or have

a right to the species man, but what has the essence of that species; it follows, that the abstract idea

for which the name stands, and the essence of the species, is one and the same. From whence it is

easy to observe, that the essences of the sorts of things, and, consequently, the sorting of things, is

the workmanship of the understanding that abstracts and makes those general ideas.

13. They are the workmanship of the understanding, but have their foundation in the similitude of

things. I would not here be thought to forget, much less to deny, that Nature, in the production of

things, makes several of them alike: there is nothing more obvious, especially in the race of animals,

and all things propagated by seed. But yet I think we may say, the sorting of them under names is

the workmanship of the understanding, taking occasion, from the similitude it observes amongst

them, to make abstract general ideas, and set them up in the mind, with names annexed to them, as

patterns or forms, (for, in that sense, the word form has a very proper signification,) to which as

particular things existing are found to agree, so they come to be of that species, have that

denomination, or are put into that classis. For when we say this is a man, that a horse; this justice,

that cruelty; this a watch, that a jack; what do we else but rank things under different specific names,

as agreeing to those abstract ideas, of which we have made those names the signs? And what are

the essences of those species set out and marked by names, but those abstract ideas in the mind;

which are, as it were, the bonds between particular things that exist, and the names they are to be

ranked under? And when general names have any connexion with particular beings, these abstract

ideas are the medium that unites them: so that the essences of species, as distinguished and

denominated by us, neither are nor can be anything but those precise abstract ideas we have in our

minds. And therefore the supposed real essences of substances, if different from our abstract ideas,

cannot be the essences of the species we rank things into. For two species may be one, as

rationally as two different essences be the essence of one species: and I demand what are the

alterations [which] may, or may not be made in a horse or lead, without making either of them to be

of another species? In determining the species of things by our abstract ideas, this is easy to

resolve: but if any one will regulate himself herein by supposed real essences, he will, I suppose, be

at a loss: and he will never be able to know when anything precisely ceases to be of the species of a

horse or lead.

14. Each distinct abstract idea is a distinct essence. Nor will any one wonder that I say these

essences, or abstract ideas (which are the measures of name, and the boundaries of species) are

the workmanship of the understanding, who considers that at least the complex ones are often, in

several men, different collections of simple ideas; and therefore that is covetousness to one man,

which is not so to another. Nay, even in substances, where their abstract ideas seem to be taken

from the things themselves, they are not constantly the same; no, not in that species which is most

familiar to us, and with which we have the most intimate acquaintance: it having been more than

once doubted, whether the foetus born of a woman were a man, even so far as that it hath been

debated, whether it were or were not to be nourished and baptized: which could not be, if the

abstract idea or essence to which the name man belonged were of nature's making; and were not

the uncertain and various collection of simple ideas, which the understanding put together, and

then, abstracting it, affixed a name to it. So that, in truth, every distinct abstract idea is a distinct

essence; and the names that stand for such distinct ideas are the names of things essentially

different. Thus a circle is as essentially different from an oval as a sheep from a goat; and rain is as

essentially different from snow as water from earth: that abstract idea which is the essence of one

being impossible to be communicated to the other. And thus any two abstract ideas, that in any part

vary one from another, with two distinct names annexed to them, constitute two distinct sorts, or, if

you please, species, as essentially different as any two of the most remote or opposite in the world.

15. Several significations of the word "essence." But since the essences of things are thought by

some (and not without reason) to be wholly unknown, it may not be amiss to consider the several

significations of the word essence.

Real essences. First, Essence may be taken for the very being of anything, whereby it is what it is.

And thus the real internal, but generally (in substances) unknown constitution of things, whereon

their discoverable qualities depend, may be called their essence. This is the proper original

signification of the word, as is evident from the formation of it; essentia, in its primary notation,

signifying properly, being. And in this sense it is still used, when we speak of the essence of

particular things, without giving them any name.

Nominal essences. Secondly, The learning and disputes of the schools having been much busied

about genus and species, the word essence has almost lost its primary signification: and, instead of

the real constitution of things, has been almost wholly applied to the artificial constitution of genus

and species. It is true, there is ordinarily supposed a real constitution of the sorts of things; and it is

past doubt there must be some real constitution, on which any collection of simple ideas co-existing

must depend. But, it being evident that things are ranked under names into sorts or species, only as

they agree to certain abstract ideas, to which we have annexed those names, the essence of each

genus, or sort, comes to be nothing but that abstract idea which the general, or sortal (if I may have

leave so to call it from sort, as I do general from genus), name stands for. And this we shall find to

be that which the word essence imports in its most familiar use.

These two sorts of essences, I suppose, may not unfitly be termed, the one the real, the other

nominal essence.

16. Constant connexion between the name and nominal essence. Between the nominal essence

and the name there is so near a connexion, that the name of any sort of things cannot be attributed

to any particular being but what has this essence, whereby it answers that abstract idea whereof

that name is the sign.

17. Supposition, that species are distinguished by their real essences, useless. Concerning the real

essences of corporeal substances (to mention these only) there are, if I mistake not, two opinions.

The one is of those who, using the word essence for they know not what, suppose a certain number

of those essences, according to which all natural things are made, and wherein they do exactly

every one of them partake, and so become of this or that species. The other and more rational

opinion is of those who look on all natural things to have a real, but unknown, constitution of their

insensible parts; from which flow those sensible qualities which serve us to distinguish them one

from another, according as we have occasion to rank them into sorts, under common

denominations. The former of these opinions, which supposes these essences as a certain number

of forms or moulds, wherein all natural things that exist are cast, and do equally partake, has, I

imagine, very much perplexed the knowledge of natural things. The frequent productions of

monsters, in all the species of animals, and of changelings, and other strange issues of human birth,

carry with them difficulties, not possible to consist with this hypothesis; since it is as impossible that

two things partaking exactly of the same real essence should have different properties, as that two

figures partaking of the same real essence of a circle should have different properties. But were

there no other reason against it, yet the supposition of essences that cannot be known; and the

making of them, nevertheless, to be that which distinguishes the species of things, is so wholly

useless and unserviceable to any part of our knowledge, that that alone were sufficient to make us

lay it by, and content ourselves with such essences of the sorts or species of things as come within

the reach of our knowledge: which, when seriously considered, will be found, as I have said, to be

nothing else but, those abstract complex ideas to which we have annexed distinct general names.

18. Real and nominal essence the same in simple ideas and modes, different in substances.

Essences being thus distinguished into nominal and real, we may further observe, that, in the

species of simple ideas and modes, they are always the same; but in substances always quite

different. Thus, a figure including a space between three lines, is the real as well as nominal

essence of a triangle; it being not only the abstract idea to which the general name is annexed, but

the very essentia or being of the thing itself; that foundation from which all its properties flow, and to

which they are all inseparably annexed. But it is far otherwise concerning that parcel of matter which

makes the ring on my finger; wherein these two essences are apparently different. For, it is the real

constitution of its insensible parts, on which depend all those properties of colour, weight, fusibility,

fixedness, etc., which are to be found in it; which constitution we know not, and so, having no

particular idea of, having no name that is the sign of it. But yet it is its colour, weight, fusibility,

fixedness, etc., which makes it to be gold, or gives it a right to that name, which is therefore its

nominal essence. Since nothing can be called gold but what has a conformity of qualities to that

abstract complex idea to which that name is annexed. But this distinction of essences, belonging

particularly to substances, we shall, when we come to consider their names, have an occasion to

treat of more fully.

19. Essences ingenerable and incorruptible. That such abstract ideas, with names to them, as we

have been speaking of are essences, may further appear by what we are told concerning essences,

viz., that they are all ingenerable and incorruptible. Which cannot be true of the real constitutions of

things, which begin and perish with them. All things that exist, besides their Author, are all liable to

change; especially those things we are acquain