History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

badly neglected, branch of science than in physics. As knowledge and

opinion have been found reducible to the associative play of ideas, and the

store of ideas, again, to original impressions and shown derivable from

these; so man's volition and action present themselves as results of the

mechanical working of the passions, which, in turn, point further back to

more primitive principles. The ultimate motives of all action are pleasure

and pain, to which we owe our ideas of good and evil.

The direct passions,

desire and aversion, joy and sorrow, hope and fear, are the immediate

effects of these original elements. From the direct arise in certain

circumstances the indirect passions, pride and humility, love and hatred

(together with respect and contempt); the first two, if the objects which

excite feeling are immediately connected with ourselves, the latter, when

pleasure and pain are aroused by the accomplishments or the defects of

others. While love and hate are always conjoined with a readiness

for action, with benevolence or anger, pride and humility are pure,

self-centered, inactive emotions.

[Footnote 1: Cf. G. von Gizycki, _Die Ethik David Humes_, 1878.]

All moral phenomena, will, moral judgment, conscience, virtue, are not

simple and original data, but of a composite or derivative nature. They are

without exception products of the regular interaction of the passions. With

such views there can be, of course, no question of a freedom of the will.

If anyone objects to determinism, that virtues and vices, if they are

involuntary and necessary, are not praise-or blame-worthy, he is to be

referred to the applause paid to beauty and talent, which are considered

meritorious, although they are not dependent upon our choice. The legal

attitude of theology and law first caused all desert to be based upon

freedom, whereas the ancient philosophers spoke unhesitatingly of

intellectual virtues.

Hume does not, like nearly all his predecessors and contemporaries, find

the determining grounds of volition in ideas, but in the feelings. After

curtailing the rights of the reason in the theoretical field in favor of

custom and instinct, he dispossesses her also in the sphere of practice.

Impassive reason, judging only of truth and falsehood, is an inactive

faculty, which of itself can never inspire us with inclination and desire

toward an object, can never itself become a motive. It is only capable

of influencing the will indirectly, through the aid of some affection.

Abstract relations of ideas, and facts as well, leave us entirely

indifferent so long as they fail to acquire an emotional value through

their relation to our state of mind. When we speak of a victory of reason

over passion it is nothing but a conquest of one passion by another, _i.

e_., of a violent passion by a calm one. That which is commonly called

reason here is nothing but one of those general and calm affections _(e.

g_., the love of life) which direct the will to a distant good, without

exciting any sensible emotion in the mind; by passion we commonly

understand the violent passions only, which engender a marked disturbance

in the soul and the production of which requires a certain propinquity of

the object. A man is said to be industrious "from reason," when a calm

desire for money makes him laborious. It is a mistake to consider all

violent passions powerful, and all calm ones weak. The prevalence of calm

affections constitutes the essence of strength of mind.

As reason is thus degraded from a governor of the will to a "slave of the

passions," so, further, judgment concerning right and wrong is taken away

from her. Moral distinctions are determined by our sense of the agreeable

and the disagreeable. We pass an immediate judgment of taste on the actions

of our fellow-men; the good pleases, evil displeases.

The sight of virtue

gives us satisfaction; that of vice repels us.

Accordingly an action or

trait of mind is virtuous when it calls forth in the observer an agreeable,

disinterested sentiment of approbation.

What, then, are the actions which receive such general approval, and how is

the praise to be explained which the spectator bestows on them? We approve

such traits of character as are immediately agreeable or useful, either to

the person himself or to others. This yields four classes of praiseworthy

qualities. The first class, those which are agreeable to the possessor

(quite apart from any utility to himself or to others), includes

cheerfulness, greatness of mind, courage, tranquillity, and benevolence;

the second, those immediately agreeable to others, modesty, good manners,

politeness, and wit; the third, those useful to ourselves, strength of

will, industry, frugality, strength of body, intelligence and other mental

gifts. The fourth class comprises the highest virtues, the qualities useful

to others, benevolence and justice. Pleasure and utility are in all cases

the criterion of merit. The monkish virtues of humility and mortification

of the flesh, which bring no pleasure or advantage either to their

possessor or to society, are considered meritorious by no one who

understands the subject.

If the moral value of actions is thus made to depend on their effects, we

cannot dispense with the assistance of reason in judging moral questions,

since it alone can inform us concerning these results of action. Reason,

however, is not sufficient to determine us to praise or blame. Nothing but

a sentiment can induce us to give the preference to beneficial and useful

tendencies over pernicious ones. This feeling is evidently no other than

satisfaction in the happiness of men and uneasiness in view of their

misery--in short, it is sympathy. By means of the imagination we enter into

the experiences of others and participate in their joy and sorrow. Whatever

depresses or rejoices them, whatever inspires them with pride, fills us

with similar emotions. From the habit of sympathetically passing moral

judgment on the actions of others, and of seeing our own judged by them,

is developed the further one of keeping a constant watch over ourselves and

of considering our dispositions and deeds from the standpoint of the good

of others. This custom is called conscience. Allied to this is the love of

reputation, which continually leads us to ask, How will our behavior appear

in the eyes of those with whom we associate?

Within the fourth and most important class, the social virtues, Hume

distinguishes between the natural virtues of humanity and benevolence and

the artificial virtues of justice and fidelity. The former proceed from our

inborn sympathy with the good of others, while the latter, on the other

hand, are not to be derived from a natural passion, an instinctive love of

humanity, but are the product of reflection and art, and take their origin

in a social convention.

In order that an action may gain the approval of the spectator two other

things are required besides its salutary effects: it must be a mark

of character, of a permanent disposition, and it must proceed from

disinterested motives. Hume is obliged by this latter position to show that

disinterested benevolence actually exists, that the unselfish affections

do not secretly spring from self-love. To cite only one of the thousand

examples of benevolence in which no discernible interest is concerned,

we desire happiness for our friends even when we have no expectation

of participating in it. The accounts of human selfishness are greatly

overdrawn, and those who deduce all actions from it make the mistake of

taking the inevitable consequences of virtue--the pleasure of self-approval

and of being esteemed by others--for the only motives to virtue. Because

virtue, in the outcome, produces inner satisfaction and is praised by

others, it does not follow that it is practiced merely for the sake of

these agreeable consequences. Self-love is a secondary impulse, whose

appearance at all presupposes primary impulses. Only after we have

experienced the pleasure which comes from the satisfaction of such an

original impulse (_e. g_., ambition), can this become the object of a

conscious reflective search after pleasure, or of egoism. Power brings no

enjoyment to the man by nature devoid of ambition, and he who is naturally

ambitious does not desire fame because it affords him pleasure, but

conversely, fame affords him pleasure because he desires it. The natural

propensity which terminates directly on the object, without knowledge or

foresight of the pleasurable results, comes first, and egoistic reflection

directed toward the hoped-for enjoyment can develop only after this has

been satisfied. The case is the same with benevolence as with the love

of fame. It is implanted in the constitution of our minds as an original

impulse immediately directed toward the happiness of other men. After

it has been exercised and its exercise rewarded by self-satisfaction,

admiration, thanks, and reciprocation, it is indeed possible for the

expectation of such agreeable consequences to lead us to the repetition of

beneficent acts. But the original motive is not an egoistic, regard for

useful consequences. If, from the force of the passion alone, vengeance

may be so eagerly pursued that every consideration of personal quiet and

security is silenced, it may also be conceded that humanity causes us

to forget our own interests. Nay, further, the social affections, as

Shaftesbury has proven, are the strongest of all, and the man will rarely

be found in whom the sum of the benevolent impulses will not outweigh that

of the selfish ones.

In the section on justice Hume attacks the contract theory. Law, property,

and the sacredness of contracts exist first in society, but not first in

the state. The obligation to observe contracts is, indeed, made stronger by

the civil law and civil authority, but not created by them. Law arises from

convention, _i. e_., not from a formal contract, but a tacit agreement, a

sense of common interest, and this agreement, in turn, proceeds from an

original propensity to enter into social relations. The unsocial and

lawless state of nature is a philosophical fiction which has never existed;

men have always been social. They have all at least been born into the

society of the family, and they know no-more terrible punishment than

isolation. States are not created, however, by a voluntary act, but have

their roots in history. The question at issue between Hobbes and Hume was

thus adjusted at a later period by Kant: the state, it is true, has not

historically arisen from a contract, yet it is allowable and useful to

consider it under the aspect of a contract as a regulative idea.

Only once since David Hume, in Herbert Spencer, has the English nation

produced a mind of like comprehensive power. Hume and Locke form the

culminating points of English thought. They are national types, in that

in them the two fundamental tendencies of English thinking, clearness of

understanding and practical sense, were manifested in equal force. In Locke

these worked together in harmonious co-operation. In Hume the friendly

alliance is broken, the common labor ceases; each of the two demands its

full rights; a painful breach opens up between science and life. Reason

leads inevitably to doubt, to insight into its own weakness, while life

demands conviction. The doubter cannot act, the agent cannot know. It is

true that a substitute is found for defective knowledge in belief based

upon instinct and custom; but this is a makeshift, not a solution of the

problem, an acknowledgment of the evil, not a cure for it. Further, Hume's

greatness does not consist in the fact that he preached modesty to the

contending parties, that he banished the doubting reason into the study

and restricted life to belief in probabilities, but in the mental strength

which enabled him to endure sharp contradictions, and, instead of an

overhasty and easy reconciliation, to suspend the one impulse until the

other had made its demands thoroughly, completely, and regardlessly heard.

Though he is distinguished from other skeptics by the fact that he not

only shows the fundamental conceptions of our knowledge of nature and the

principles of religion uncertain and erroneous, but finds _necessary_

errors in them and acutely uncovers their origin in the lawful workings

of our inner life, yet his historical influence essentially rests on his

skepticism. In his own country it roused in the

"Scottish School" the

reaction of common sense, while in Germany it helped to wake a kindred but

greater spirit from the bonds of his dogmatic slumbers, and to fortify him

for his critical achievements.

(c) %The Scottish School%.--Priestley's associational psychology,

Berkeley's idealism, and Hume's skepticism are legitimate deductions from

Locke's assumption that the immediate objects of thought are not things but

ideas, and that judgment or knowledge arises from the combination of ideas

originally separate. The absurdity of the consequences shows the falsity of

the premises. The true philosophy must not contradict common sense. It

is not correct to look upon the mind as a sheet of white paper on which

experience inscribes single characters, and then to make the understanding

combine these originally disconnected elements into judgments by means of

comparison, and the belief in the existence of the object come in as a

later result added to the ideas by reflection. It is rather true that the

elements discovered by the analysis of the cognitive processes are far from

being the originals from which these arise. It is not isolated ideas that

come first, but judgments, self-evident axioms of the understanding, which

form part of the mental constitution with which God has endowed us; and

sensation is accompanied by an immediate belief in the reality of the

object. Sensation guarantees the presence of an external thing possessing a

certain character, although it is not an image of this property, but merely

a sign for something in no wise resembling itself.

This is the standpoint of the founder[1] of the Scottish School, Thomas

Reid (1710-96, professor in Aberdeen and Glasgow; _An Inquiry into the

Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense_, 1764; _Essays on the

Intellectual Powers of Man_, 1785, _Essays on the Active Powers_, 1788,

together under the title, _Essays on the Powers of the Human Mind.

Collected Works_, 1804, and often since, especially the edition by

Hamilton, with valuable notes and dissertations, 7th ed., 2 vols., 1872).

We may recognize in it a revival of the common notions of Herbert, as well

as a transfer of the innate faculty of judgment inculcated by the ethical

and aesthetic writers from the practical to the theoretical field; the

"common sense" of Reid is an original sense for truth, as the "taste"

of Shaftesbury and Hutcheson was a natural sense for the good and the

beautiful. Like Jacobi at a later period, Reid points out that mediate,

reasoned knowledge presupposes a knowledge which is immediate, and all

inference and demonstration, fixed, undemonstrable, immediately certain

fundamental truths. The fundamental judgments or principles of common

sense, which are true for us, even if [possibly] not true in themselves,

are discoverable by observation (empirical rationalism).

In the enumeration

of them two dangers are to be avoided: we must neither raise contingent

principles to the position of axioms, nor, from an exaggerated endeavor

after unity, underestimate the number of these self-evident principles.

Reid himself is always more sparing with them than his disciples. He

distinguishes two classes: first principles of necessary truth, and first

principles of contingent truth or truth of fact. As first principles of

necessary truth he cites, besides the axioms of logic and mathematics,

grammatical, aesthetic, moral, and metaphysical principles (among the last

belong the principles: "That the qualities which we perceive by our senses

must have a subject, which we call body, and that the thoughts we are

conscious of must have a subject, which we call mind";

"that whatever

begins to exist, must have a cause which produced it").

He lays down twelve

principles as the basis of our knowledge of matters of fact, in which his

reference to the doubt of Berkeley and Hume is evident.

The most important

of these are: "The existence of everything of which I am conscious"; "that

the thoughts of which I am conscious, are the thoughts of a being which I

call myself, my mind, my person"; "our own personal identity and continued

existence, as far back as we remember anything distinctly"; "that those

things do really exist which we distinctly perceive by our senses, and are

what we perceive them to be"; "that we have some degree of power over our

actions, and the determinations of our will"; "that there is life and

intelligence in our fellow-men"; "that there is a certain regard due... to

human authority in matters of opinion"; "that, in the phenomena of

nature, what is to be, will probably be like what has been in similar

circumstances."

[Footnote 1: In the sense of "chief founder"; cf.

McCosh's _Scottish

Philosophy_, 1875, pp. 36, 68 _seq_., which is the standard authority on

the school as a whole.--TR.]

The widespread and lasting favor experienced by this theory, with its

invitation to forget all earnest work in the problems of philosophy

by taking refuge in common sense, shows that a general relaxation had

succeeded the energetic endeavors which Hume had demanded of himself and

of his readers. With this declaration of the infallibility of common

consciousness, the theory of knowledge, which had been so successfully

begun, was incontinently thrust aside, although, indeed, empirical

psychology gained by the industrious investigation of the inner life by

means of self-observation. James Beattie continued the attack on Hume

in his _Essay on the Nature and Immutability of Truth in Opposition to

Sophistry and Skepticism_, 1770, on the principle that wisdom must never

contradict nature, and that whatever our nature compels us to believe,

hence whatever all agree in, is true. In his briefer dissertations Beattie

discussed Memory and Imagination, Fable and Romance, the Effects of

Poetry and Music, Laughter, the Sublime, etc. While Beattie had given the

preference to psychological and aesthetic questions, James Oswald (1772)

appealed to common sense in matters of religion, describing it as an

instinctive faculty of judgment concerning truth and falsehood. The most

eminent among the followers of Reid was Dugald Stewart (professor in

Edinburgh; _Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind_, 1792-1827;

_Collected Works_, edited by Hamilton, 1854-58), who developed the

doctrines of the master and in some points modified them. Thomas

Brown (1778-1820), who is highly esteemed by Mill, Spencer, and Bain,

approximated the teachings of Reid and Stewart to those of Hume. The

philosophy of the Scottish School was long in favor both in England and in

France, where it was employed as a weapon against materialism.

By way of appendix we may mention the beginnings of a psychological

aesthetics in Henry Home (Lord Kames, 1696-1782), and Edmund Burke

(1728-97).[1] Home, in ethics a follower of Hutcheson, is fond of

supporting his aesthetic views by examples from Shakespeare. Beauty (chap.

iii.) appears to belong to the object itself, but in reality it is only an

effect, a "secondary quality," of the object; like color, it is nothing but

an idea in the mind, "for an object is said to be beautiful for no other

reason but that it appears so to the spectator." It arises from regularity,

proportion, order, simplicity--properties which belong to sublimity as well

(chap, iv.), but to which they are by no means so essential, since it is

satisfied with a less degree of them. While the beautiful excites emotions

of sweetness and gayety, the sublime rouses feelings which are agreeable,

it is true, but which are not sweet and gay, but strong and more serious.

Burke's explanation goes deeper. He derives the antithesis of the sublime

and the beautiful from the two fundamental impulses of human nature, the

instinct of self-preservation and the social impulse.

Whatever is contrary

to the former makes a strong and terrible impression on the soul; whatever

favors the latter makes a weak but agreeable one. The terrible delights us

(first depressing and then exalting us), when we merely contemplate it,

without being ourselves affected by the danger or the pain--this is the

sublime. On the other hand, that is beautiful which inspires us with

tenderness and affection without our desiring to possess it. Sublimity

implies a certain greatness, beauty, a certain smallness. Delight in both

is based on bodily phenomena. Terror moderated exercises a beneficent

influence on the nerves by stimulating them and giving them tension;

the gentle impression of beauty exerts a quieting effect upon them. The

disturbances caused by the former, and the recovery induced by the latter,

are both conducive to health, and hence, experienced as pleasures.

[Footnote 1: Home, _Elements of Criticism_, 1762. Burke, _A Philosophical

Inquiry info the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and the Beautiful_,

1756.]

CHAPTER VI.

THE FRENCH ILLUMINATION.

In the last decade of the seventeenth century France had yielded the

leadership in philosophy to England. Whereas Hobbes had in Paris imbibed

the spirit of the Galilean and Cartesian inquiry, while Bacon, Locke, and

even Hume had also visited France with advantage, now French thinkers take

the watchword from the English. Montesquieu and Voltaire, returning from

England in the same year (1729), acquaint their countrymen with the ideas

of Locke and his contemporaries. These are eagerly caught up; are, step

by step, and with the logical courage characteristic of the French mind,

developed to their extreme conclusions; and, at the same time, spread

abroad in this heightened form among the people beyond the circles of the

learned, nay, even beyond the educated classes. The English temperament is

favorable neither to this advance to extreme revolutionary inferences nor

to this propagandist tendency. Locke combines a rationalistic ethics with

his semi-sensational theory of knowledge; Newton is far from finding in his

mechanical physics a danger for religious beliefs; the deists treat the

additions of positive religion rather as superfluous ballast than as

hateful unreason; Bolingbroke wishes at least to conceal from the people

the illuminating principles which he offers to the higher classes. Such

halting where farther progress threatens to become dangerous to moral

interests does more honor to the moral, than to the logical, character of

the philosopher. But with the transfer of these ideas to France, the wall

of separation is broken down between the theory of knowledge and the theory

of ethics, between natural philosophy and the philosophy of religion;

sensationalism forces its way from the region of theory into the sphere

of practice, and the mechanical theory is transformed from a principal

of physical interpretation into a metaphysical view of the world of an

atheistical character. Naturalism is everywhere determined to have its

own: if knowledge comes from the senses, then morality must be rooted

in self-interest; wh