History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

Among the editors of the _Encyclopedia_, the mathematician D'Alembert

_(Elements of Philosophy_, 1758) remained loyal to skeptical views. Neither

matter nor spirit is in its essence knowable; the world is probably quite

different from our sensuous conception of it. As Diderot (1713-84), and

the _Encyclopedia_ with him, advanced from skepticism to materialism,

D'Alembert retired from the editorial board (1757), after Rousseau, also,

had separated himself from the Encyclopedists.

Diderot[1] was the leading

spirit in the second half of the eighteenth century, as Voltaire in the

first half. His lively and many-sided receptivity, active industry, clever

and combative eloquence, and enthusiastic disposition qualified him for

this rôle beyond all his contemporaries, who testify that they owe even

more to his stimulating conversation than to his writings. He commenced by

bringing Shaftesbury's _Inquiry into Virtue and Merit_

to the notice of

his countrymen; and then turned his sword, on the one hand, against the

atheists, to refute whom, he thought, a single glance into the microscope

was sufficient, and, on the other, against the traditional belief in a

God of anger and revenge, who takes pleasure in bathing in the tears of

mankind. Then followed a period of skepticism, which is well illustrated by

the prayer in the _Thoughts on the Interpretation of Nature_, 1754: O God!

I do not know whether thou art, but I will guide my thoughts and actions

as though thou didst see me think and act, etc. Under the influence

of Holbach's circle he finally reached (in the _Conversation between

D'Alembert and Diderot_, and _D'Alembert's Dream_, written in 1769, but not

published until 1830, in vol. iv. of the _Mémoires, Correspondance, et

Ouvrages Inédits de Diderot_) the position of naturalistic monism--there

exists but one great individual, the All. Though he had formerly

distinguished thinking substance from material substance, and had based the

immortality of the soul on the unity of sensation and the unity of the ego,

he now makes sensation a universal and essential property of matter

(_la pierre sent_), declares the talk about the simplicity of the

soul metaphysico-theological nonsense, calls the brain a self-playing

instrument, ridicules self-esteem, shame, and repentance as the absurd

folly of a being that imputes to itself merit or demerit for necessary

actions, and recognizes no other immortality than that of posthumous fame.

But even amid these extreme conclusions, his enthusiasm for virtue remains

too intense to allow him to assent to the audacious theories of La Mettrie

and Helvetius.

[Footnote 1: _Works_ in twenty-two vols., Paris, Brière, 1821; latest

edition, 1875 _seq_. Cf. on Diderot the fine work by Karl Rosenkranz,

_Diderots Leben und Werke_, 1866.]

French natural science also tended toward materialism.

Buffon _(Natural

History_, 1749 _seq_) endeavors to facilitate the mechanical explanation

of the phenomena of life by the assumption of living molecules, from

which visible organisms are built up. Robinet (_On Nature_, 1761 _seq_.),

availing himself of Spinozistic and Leibnitzian conceptions, goes still

further, in that he endows every particle of matter with sensation, looks

on the whole world as a succession of living beings with increasing

mentality, and subjects the interaction of the material and psychical sides

of the individual, as well as the relation of pleasure and pain in the

universe, to a law of harmonious compensation.

The _System of Nature_, 1770, which bore on its title page the name of

Mirabaud, who had died 1760, proceeded from the company of freethinkers

accustomed to meet in the hospitable house of Baron von Holbach (died

1789), a native of the Palatinate. Its real author was Holbach himself,

although his friends Diderot, Naigeon, Lagrange, the mathematician, and the

clever Grimm (died 1807) seem to have co-operated in the preparation

of certain sections. The cumbrous seriousness and the dry tone of this

systematic combination of the radical ideas which the century had produced,

were no doubt the chief causes of its unsympathetic reception by the

public. Similarly unsuccessful was the popular account of materialism with

which Holbach followed it, in 1772, and Helvetius's excerpts from the

_System of Nature_, 1774.

Holbach applies himself to the despiritualization of nature and the

destruction of religious prejudices with sincere faith in the sacred

mission of unbelief--the happiness of humanity depends on atheism. "O

Nature, sovereign of all beings, and ye her daughters, Virtue, Reason, and

Truth, be forever our only divinities." What has made virtue so difficult

and so rare? Religion, which divides men instead of uniting them. What has

so long delayed the illumination of the reason, and the discovery of truth?

Religion with its mischievous errors, God, spirit, freedom, immortality.

Immortality exists only in the memory of later generations; man is the

creature of a day; nothing is permanent but the great whole of nature and

the eternal law of universal change. Can a clock broken into a thousand

pieces continue to mark the hours? The senseless doctrine of freedom was

invented only to solve the senseless problem of the justification of God in

view of the existence of evil. Man is at every moment of his life a passive

instrument in the hands of necessity; the universe is an immeasurable

and uninterrupted chain of actions and reactions, an eternal round of

interchanging motions, ruled by laws, a change in which would at once alter

the nature of all things. The most fatal error is the idea of human and

divine spirits, which has been advanced by philosophers and adopted with

applause by fools. The opinion that man is divided into two substances is

based on the fact that, of the changes in our body, we directly perceive

only the external molar movements, while, on the other hand, the inner

motions of the invisible molecules are known only by their effects. These

latter have been ascribed to the mind, which, moreover, we have adorned

with properties whose emptiness is manifested by the fact that they are all

mere negations of that which we know. Experience reveals to us only the

extended, the corporeal, the divisible--but the mind is to be the opposite

of all three, yet at the same time to possess the power (how, no man can

tell) of acting on that which is material and of being acted upon by it.

In thus dividing himself into body and soul, man has in reality only

distinguished between his brain and himself. Man is a purely physical

being. All so-called spiritual phenomena are functions of the brain,

special cases of the operation of the universal forces of nature. Thought

and volition are sensation, sensation is motion. The moving forces in the

moral world are the same as those in the physical world; in the latter they

are called attraction and repulsion, in the former, love and hate;

that which the moralist terms self-love is the same instinct of

self-preservation which is familiar in physics as the force of inertia.

As man has doubled himself, so also he has doubled nature. Evil gave the

first impulse to the formation of the idea of God, pain and ignorance have

been the parents of superstition; our sufferings were ascribed to unknown

powers, of which we were in fear, but which, at the same time, we hoped to

propitiate by prayer and sacrifice. The wise turned with their worship and

reverence toward a more worthy object, to the great All; and, in fact, if

we seek to give the word God a tenable meaning, it signifies active nature.

The error lay in the dualistic view, in the distinction between nature and

itself, _i.e._ its activity, and in the belief that the explanation of

motion required a separate immaterial Mover. This assumption is, in the

first place, false, for since the All is the complex of all that exists

there can be nothing outside it; motion follows from the existence of the

universe as necessarily as its other properties; the world does not receive

it from without, but imparts it to itself by its own power. In the second

place the assumption is useless; it explains nothing, but confuses the

problems of natural science to the point of insolubility. In the third

place it is self-contradictory, for after theology has removed the Deity

as far away from man as possible, by means of the negative metaphysical

predicates, it finds itself necessitated to bring the two together again

through the moral attributes--which are neither compatible with one another

nor with the meta-physical--and crowns the absurdity by the assurance that

we can please God by believing that which is incomprehensible. Finally, the

assumption is dangerous; it draws men away from the present, disturbs their

peace and enjoyment, stirs up hatred, and thus makes happiness and morality

impossible. If, then, utility is the criterion of truth, theism--even in

the mild form of deism--is proven erroneous by its disastrous consequences.

All error is bane.

Matter and motion are alike eternal. Nature is an active, self-moving,

living whole, an endless chain of causes and effects.

All is in unceasing

motion, all is cause (nothing is dead, nothing rests), all is effect (there

is no spontaneous motion, none directed to an end).

Order and disorder are

not in nature, but only in our understanding; they are abstract ideas to

denote that which is conformable to our nature and that which is contrary

to it. The end of the All is itself alone, is life, activity; the universal

goal of particular beings, like that of the universe, is the conservation

of being.

Anthropology is for Holbach essentially reduced to two problems, the

deduction of thought from motion, and of morality from the physical

tendency to self-preservation. The forces of the soul are no other than

those of the body. All mental faculties develop from sensation; sensations

are motions in the brain which reveal to us motions without the brain. All

the passions may be reduced to love and hate, desire and aversion, and

depend upon temperament, on the individual mixture of the fluid parts.

Virtue is the equilibrium of the fluids. All human actions proceed from

interest. Good and bad men are distinguished only by their organizations,

and by the ideas they form concerning happiness. With the same necessity

as that of the act itself, follow the love or contempt of fellow-men,

the pleasure of self-esteem and the pain of repentance (regret for evil

consequences, hence no evidence of freedom). Neither responsibility nor

punishment is done away with by this necessity--have we not the right to

protect ourselves against the stream which damages our fields, by building

dikes and altering its course? The end of endeavor is permanent happiness,

and this can be attained through virtue alone. The passions which are

useful to society compel the affection and approval of our fellows. In

order to interest others in our welfare we must interest ourselves in

theirs--nothing is more indispensable to man than man.

The clever man acts

morally, interest binds us to the good; love for others means love for the

means to our own happiness. Virtue is the art of making ourselves happy

through the happiness of others. Nature itself chastises immorality, since

she makes the intemperate unhappy. Religion has hindered the recognition of

these rules, has misunderstood the diseases of the soul, and applied false

and ineffective remedies; the renunciation which she requires is opposed to

human nature. The true moralist recognizes in medicine the key to the human

heart; he will cure the mind through the body, control the passions and

hold them in check by other passions instead of by sermons, and will teach

men that the surest road to personal ends is to labor for the public good.

Illumination is the way to virtue and to happiness.

Volney (Chasseboeuf, died 1820; _Catechism of the French Citizen_, 1793,

later under the title _Natural Law or Physical Principles of Morals deduced

front the Organization of Man and of the Universe_; further, _The Ruins;

Complete Works_, 1821) belongs among the moralists of self-love, although,

besides the egoistic interests, he takes account of the natural sympathetic

impulses also. This is still more the case with Condorcet (_Sketch of

an Historical View of the Progress of the Human Mind_, 1794), who was

influenced alike by Condillac and by Turgot, and who defends a tendency

toward universal perfection both in the individual and in the race. Besides

the selfish affections, which are directed as much to the injury as to the

support of others, there lies in the organization of man a force which

steadily tends toward the good, in the form of underived feelings of

sympathy and benevolence, from which moral self-judgment is developed by

the aid of reflection. The aim of true ethics and social art is not to make

the "great" virtues universal, but to make them needless; the nearer the

nations approximate to mental and moral perfection, the less they stand in

need of these--happy the people in which good deeds are so customary that

scarcely an opportunity is left for heroism. The chief instrument for the

moral cultivation of the people is the development of the reason, the

conscience, and the benevolent affections. Habituation to deeds of kindness

is a source of pure and inexhaustible happiness.

Sympathy with the good of

others must be so cultivated that the sacrifice of personal enjoyment will

be a sweeter joy than the pleasure itself. Let the child early learn to

enjoy the delight of loving and of being loved. We must, finally, strive

toward the gradual diminution of the inequalities of capacity, of property,

and between ruler and ruled, for to abolish them is impossible.

Of the remaining philosophers of the revolutionary period mention may be

made of the physician Cabanis _(Relations of the Physical and the Moral in

Man, 1799)_, and Destutt de Tracy _(Elements of Ideology, 1801 seq.)_. The

former is a materialist in psychology (the nerves are the man, ideas are

secretions of the brain), considers consciousness a property of organic

matter (the soul is not a being, but a faculty), and makes moral sympathy

develop out of the animal instincts of preservation and nourishment.

De Tracy, also, derives all psychical activity from organization and

sensation. His doctrine of the will, though but briefly sketched, is

interesting. The desires have a passive and an active side (corresponding

to the twofold action of the nerves, on themselves and on the muscles); on

the one hand, they are feelings of pleasure or pain, and on the other, they

lead us to action--will is need, and, at the same time, the source of

the means for satisfying this need. Both these feelings and the external

movements are probably based upon unconscious organic motions. The will is

rightly identified with the personality, it is the ego itself, the totality

of the physico-psychical life of man attaining to self-consciousness. The

inner or organic life consists in the self-preserving functions of the

individual, the outer or animal life, in the functions of relation (of

sense, of motion, of speech, of reproduction); individual interests are

rooted in the former, sympathy in the latter. The primal good is freedom,

or the power to do what we will; the highest thing in life is love. In

order to be happy we must avoid punishment, blame, and pangs of conscience.

%4. Rousseau's Conflict with the Illumination.%

The Genevese, Jean Jacques Rousseau[1] (1712-78), stands in a similar

relation of opposition to the French Illumination as the Scottish School to

the English, and Herder and Jacobi to the German. He points us away from

the cold sophistical inferences of the understanding to the immediate

conviction of feeling; from the imaginations of science to the unerring

voice of the heart and the conscience; from the artificial conditions of

culture to healthy nature. The vaunted Illumination is not the lever of

progress, but the source of all degeneration; morality does not rest on the

shrewd calculation of self-interest, but on original social and sympathetic

instincts (love for the good is just as natural to the human heart as

self-love; enthusiasm for virtue has nothing to do with our interest; what

would it mean to give up one's life for the sake of advantage?); the truths

of religion are not objects of thought, but of pious feeling.

[Footnote 1: Cf. Brockerhoff, Leipsic, 1863-74; L.

Moreau, Paris, 1870.]

Rousseau commenced his career as an author with the _Discourse on the

Sciences and the Arts_, 1750 (the discussion of a prize question, crowned

by the Academy of Dijon), which he describes as entirely pernicious, and

the _Discourse on the Origin and the Bases of the Inequality among Men_,

1753. By nature man is innocent and good, becoming evil only in society.

Reflection, civilization, and egoism are unnatural. In the happy state of

nature pity and innocent self-love (_amour de soi_) ruled, and the

latter was first corrupted by the reason into the artificial feeling of

selfishness (_amour propre_) in the course of social development--thinking

man is a degenerate animal. Property has divided men into rich and poor;

the magistracy, into strong and weak; arbitrary power, into masters and

slaves. Wealth generated luxury with its artificial delights of science and

the theater, which make us more unhappy and evil than we otherwise are;

science, the child of vice, becomes in turn the mother of new vices. All

nature, all that is characteristic, all that is good, has disappeared with

advancing culture; the only relief from the universal degeneracy is to be

hoped for from a return to nature on the part of the individual and society

alike--from education and a state conformed to nature.

The novel _Emile_ is

devoted to the pedagogical, and the _Social Contract, or the Principles of

Political Law_, to the political problem. Both appeared in 1762, followed

two years later by the _Letters from the Mountain_, a defense against the

attacks of the clergy. In these later writings Rousseau's naturalistic

hatred of reason appears essentially softened.

Social order is a sacred right, which forms the basis of all others. It

does not proceed, however, from nature--no man has natural power over his

fellows, and might confers no right--consequently it rests on a contract.

Not, however, on a contract between ruler and people.

The act by which the

people chooses a king is preceded by the act in virtue of which it is a

people. In the social contract each devotes himself with his powers and his

goods to the community, in order to gain the protection of the latter.

With this act the spiritual body politic comes into being, and attains its

unity, its ego, its will. The sum of the members is called the people; each

member, as a participant in the sovereignty, citizen, and, as bound to

obedience to the law, subject. The individual loses his natural freedom,

receiving in exchange the liberty of a citizen, which is limited by the

general will, and, in addition, property rights in all that he possesses,

equality before the law, and moral freedom, which first really makes him

master of himself. The impulse of mere desire is slavery, obedience to

self-imposed law, freedom. The sovereign is the people, law the general

popular will directed to the common good, the supreme goods, "freedom and

equality," the chief objects of legislation. The lawgiving power is the

moral will of the body politic, the government (magistracy, prince) its

executive physical power; the former is its heart, the latter its brain.

Rousseau calls the government the middle term between the head of the state

and the individual, or between the citizen as lawgiver and as subject--the

sovereign (the people) commands, the government executes, the subject

obeys. The act by which the people submits itself to its head is not a

contract, but merely a mandate; whenever it chooses it can limit, alter, or

entirely recall the delegated power. In order to security against illegal

encroachments on the part of the government, Rousseau recommends regular

assemblies of the people, in which, under suspension of governmental

authority, the confirmation, abrogation, or alteration of the constitution

shall be determined upon. Even the establishment of the articles of social

belief falls to the sovereign people. The essential difference between

Rousseau's theory of the state and that of Locke and Montesquieu consists

in his rejection of the division of powers and of representation by

delegates, hence in its unlimited democratic character.

A generation after

it was given to the world, the French Revolution made the attempt to

translate it into practice. "The masses carried out what Rousseau himself

had thought, it is true, but never willed" (Windelband).

Rousseau's theory of education is closely allied to Locke's (cf. above),

whose leading idea--the development of individuality--

was entirely in

harmony with the subjectivism of the philosopher of feeling. Posterity has

not found it a difficult task to free the sound kernel therein from the

husks of exaggeration and idiosyncrasy which surrounded it. Among the

latter belong the preference of bodily over intellectual development, and

the unlimited faith in the goodness of human nature.

Exercise the body, the

organs, the senses of the pupil, and keep his soul unemployed as long as

possible; for the first, take care only that his mind be kept free from

error and his heart from vice. In order to secure complete freedom from

disturbance in this development, it is advisable to isolate the child from

society, nay, even from the family, and to bring him up in retirement under

the guidance of a private tutor.

As the Swiss republican spoke in Rousseau's politics, so his religious

theories[1] betray the Genevan Calvinist. "The Savoyard Vicar's Profession

of Faith" (in _Emile_) proclaims deism as a religion of feeling. The

rational proofs brought forward for the existence of God--from the motion

of matter in itself at rest, and from the finality of the world--are only

designed, as he declares by letter, to confute the materialists, and derive

their impregnability entirely from the inner evidence of feeling, which

amid the vacillation of the reason _pro_ and _con_ gives the final

decision.

[Footnote 1: Cf. Ch. Borgeaud, _Rousseaus Religionsphilosophie_, Geneva and

Leipsic, 1883.]

If we limit our inquiry to that which is alone of importance for us, and

rely on the evidence of feeling, it cannot be doubted that I myself exist

and feel; that there exists an external world which affects me; that

thought, comparison or judgment concerning relations is different from

sensation or the perception of objects--for the latter is a passive,

but the former an active process; that I myself produce the activity of

attention or consideration; that, consequently, I am not merely a sensitive

or passive, but also an active or intelligent being. The freedom of my

thought and action guarantees to me the immateriality of my soul, and is

that which distinguishes me from the brute. The life of the soul after

the decay of the body is assured to me by the fact that in this world the

wicked triumphs, while the good are oppressed. The favored position which

man occupies in the scale of beings--he is able to look over the universe

and to reverence its author, to recognize order and beauty, to love the

good and to do it; and shall he, then, compare himself to the brute?--fills

<