History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

main question of the _Critique of Pure Reason_: How are synthetic judgments

_a priori_ possible?

The philosophy of experience had overestimated sense and underestimated the

understanding, when it found the source of all knowledge in the faculty of

perception and degraded the faculty of thought to an almost wholly inactive

recipient of messages coming to it from without. From the standpoint of

empiricism concepts (Ideas) deserve confidence only in so far as they can

legitimate themselves by their origin in sensations (impressions). It

overlooks the _active_ character of all knowing. Among the rationalists,

on the other hand, we find an underestimation of the senses and an

overestimation of the understanding. They believe that sense reveals

only the deceptive exterior of things, while reason gives their true

non-sensuous essence. That which the mind perceives of things is deceptive,

but that which it thinks concerning them is true. The former power is the

faculty of confused, the latter the faculty of distinct knowledge. Sense is

the enemy rather than the servant of true knowledge, which consists in the

development and explication of pregnant innate conceptions and principles.

These philosophers forget that we can never reach reality by conceptual

analysis; and that the senses have a far greater importance for knowledge

than merely to give it an impulse; that it is they which supply the

understanding with real objects, and so with the content of knowledge.

Beside the (formal) activity (of the understanding), cognition implies a

passive factor, a reception of impressions. Neither sense alone nor the

understanding alone produces knowledge, but both cognitive powers are

necessary, the active and the passive, the conceptual and the intuitive.

Here the question arises, How do concept and intuition, sensuous and

rational knowledge, differ, and what is the basis of their congruence?

Notwithstanding their different points of departure and their variant

results, the two main tendencies of modern philosophy agree in certain

points. If the conflict between the two schools and their one-sidedness

suggested the idea of supplementing the conclusions of the one by those of

the other, the recognition of the incorrectness of their common

convictions furnished the occasion to go beyond them and to establish a

new, a higher point of view above them both, as also above the eclecticism

which sought to unite the opposing principles. The errors common to both

concern, in the first place, the nature of judgment and the difference

between sensibility and understanding. Neither side had recognized that

the peculiar character of judgment consists in _active connection_. The

rationalists made judgment an active function, it is true, but a mere

activity of conscious development, of elucidation and analytical inference,

which does not advance knowledge a single step. The empiricists described

it as a process of comparison and discrimination, as the mere perception

and recognition of the relations and connections already existing between

ideas; while in reality judgment does not discover the relations and

connections of representations, but itself establishes them. In the former

case the synthetic moment is ignored, in the latter the active moment. The

imperfect view of judgment was one of the reasons for the appearance of

extreme theories concerning the origin of ideas in reason or in perception.

Rationalism regards even those concepts which have a content as innate,

whereas it is only formal concepts which are so.

Empiricism regards all,

even the highest formal concepts (the categories), as abstracted from

experience, whereas experience furnishes only the content of knowledge,

and not the synthesis which is necessary to it. On the one hand too much,

and on the other too little, is regarded as the original possession of the

understanding. The question "What concepts are innate?"

can be decided only

by answering the further question, What are the concepts through which the

faculty of judgment connects the representations obtained from experience?

These connective concepts, these formal instruments of synthesis are

_a priori_. The agreement of the two schools is still greater in regard to

the relation of sense and understanding, notwithstanding the apparently

sharp contrast between them. The empiricist considers thought transformed,

sublimated perception, while the rationalist sees in perception only

confused and less distinct thought. For the former concepts are faded

images of sensations, for the latter sensations are concepts which have not

yet become clear; the difference is scarcely greater than if the one should

call ice frozen water, and the other should prefer to call water melted

ice. Both arrange intuition and thought in a single series, and derive the

one from the other by enhancement or attenuation. Both make the mistake of

recognizing only a difference in degree where a difference in kind exists.

In such a case only an energetic dualism can afford help. Sense and

understanding are not one and the same cognitive power at different stages,

but two heterogeneous faculties. Sensation and thought are not different in

degree, but in kind. As Descartes began with the metaphysical dualism of

extension and thought, so Kant begins with the noëtical dualism of

intuition and thought.

Much more serious, however, than any of the mistakes yet mentioned was

a sin of omission of which the two schools were alike guilty, and the

recognition and avoidance of which constituted in Kant's own eyes the

distinctive character of his philosophy and its principiant-advance beyond

preceding systems. The pre-Kantian thinker had proceeded to the discussion

of knowledge without raising _the question of the possibility of

knowledge_. He had approached things in the full confidence that the human

mind was capable of cognizing them, and with a naïve trust in the power of

reason to possess itself of the truth. His trust was naïve and ingenuous,

because the idea that it could deceive him had never entered his mind. Now

no matter whether this belief in man's capacity for knowledge and in the

possibility of knowing things is justifiable or not, and no matter how

far it may be justifiable, it was in any case untested; so that when the

skeptic approached with his objections the dogmatist was defenseless.

All previous philosophy, so far as it had not been skeptical, had been,

according to Kant's expression, dogmatic; that is, it had held as an

article of faith, and without precedent inquiry, that we possess the power

of cognizing objects. It had not asked _how_ this is possible; it had not

even asked what knowledge is, what may and must be demanded of it, and by

what means our reason is in a position to satisfy such demands. It had left

human intelligence and its extent uninvestigated. The skeptic, on the other

hand, had been no more thorough. He had doubted and denied man's capacity

for knowledge just as uncritically as the dogmatist had believed and

presupposed it. He had directed his ingenuity against the theories of

dogmatic philosophy, instead of toward the fundamental question of the

possibility of knowledge. Human intelligence, which the dogmatist had

approached with unreasoned trust and the skeptic with just as unreasoned

distrust, is subjected, according to the plan of the critical philosopher,

to a searching examination. For this reason Kant termed his standpoint

"criticism," and his undertaking a "Critique of Reason."

Instead of

asserting and denying, he investigates how knowledge arises, of what

factors it is composed, and how far it extends. He inquires into the origin

and extent of knowledge, into its sources and its limits, into the grounds

of its existence and of its legitimacy. The Critique of Reason finds itself

confronted by two problems, the second of which cannot be solved until

after the solution of the first. The investigation of the sources of

knowledge must precede the inquiry into the extent of knowledge. Only after

the conditions of knowledge have been established can it be ascertained

what objects are attainable by it. Its sphere cannot be determined except

from its origin.

Whether the critical philosopher stands nearer to the skeptic or to the

dogmatist is rather an idle question. He is specifically distinct from

both, in that he summons and guides the reason to self-contemplation, to

a methodical examination of its capacity for knowledge.

Where the one had

blindly trusted and the other suspected and denied, he investigates; they

overlook, he raises the question of the possibility of knowledge. The

critical problem does not mean, Does a faculty of knowledge exist? but, Of

what powers is it composed? are all objects knowable which have been so

regarded? Kant does not ask whether, but how and by what means, knowledge

is possible. Everyone who gives himself to scientific reflection must

postulate that knowledge is possible, and the demand of the noëtical

theorists of the day for a philosophy absolutely without assumptions is

quite incapable of fulfillment. Nay, in order to be able to begin his

inquiry at all, it was necessary for Kant to assume still more special

postulates; for that a cognition of cognition is possible, that there is a

critical, self-investigating reason could, at first, be only a matter of

belief. This would not have excluded a supplementary detailed statement

concerning the _how_ of this self-knowledge, concerning the organ of the

critical philosophy. But Kant never gave one, and the omission subsequently

led to a sharp debate concerning the character and method of the Critique

of Reason. On this point, if we may so express it, Kant remained a

dogmatist.

Kant felt himself to be the finisher of skepticism; but this was chiefly

because he had received the strongest impulse to the development of his

critique of knowledge from Hume's inquiries concerning causation. Brought

up in the dogmatic rationalism of the Wolffian school, to which he

remained true for a considerable period as a teacher and writer (till about

1760), although at the same time he was inquiring with an independent

spirit, Kant was gradually won over through the influence of the English

philosophy to the side of empirical skepticism. Then--as the result, no

doubt, of reading the _Nouveaux Essais_ of Leibnitz, published in

1765--he returned to rationalistic principles, until finally, after a

renewal of empirical influences,[1] he took the position crystallized in

the _Critique of Pure Reason_, 1781, which, however, experienced still

other, though less considerable, changes in the sequel, just as in itself

it shows the traces of previous transformations.

[Footnote 1: Cf. H. Vaihinger's _Kommentar zu Kants Kritik der reinen

Vernunft_, vol. i., 1881, pp. 48-49. This is a work marked by acuteness,

great industry, and an objective point of view which merits respect. The

second volume, which treats of the Transcendental Aesthetic, appeared in

1892.]

It would be a most interesting task to trace in the writings which belong

to Kant's pre-critical period the growth and development of the fundamental

critical positions. Here, however, we can only mention in passing the

subjects of his reflection and some of the most striking anticipations and

beginnings of his epoch-making position. Even his maiden work, _Thoughts on

the True Estimation of Vis Viva_, 1747, betokens the mediating nature of

its author. In this it is argued that when men of profound and penetrating

minds maintain exactly opposite opinions, attention must be chiefly

directed to some intermediate principle to a certain degree compatible with

the correctness of both parties. The question under discussion was whether

the measure of _vis viva_ is equal, as the Cartesians thought, to the

product of the mass into the velocity, or, according to the Leibnitzians,

to the product of the mass into the square of the velocity. Kant's

unsatisfactory solution of the problem--the law of Descartes holds for

dead, and that of Leibnitz for living forces--drew upon him the derision

of Lessing, who said that he had endeavored to estimate living forces

without having tested his own. A similar tendency toward compromise--this

time it is a synthesis of Leibnitz and Newton--is seen in his

_Habilitationsschrift, Principiorum Primorum Cognitionis Metaphysicae Nova

Dilucidatio_, 1755, and in the dissertation _Monadologia Physica_, 1756.

The former distinguishes between _ratio essendi_ and _ratio cognoscendi_,

rejects the ontological argument, and defends determinism against Crusius

on Leibnitzian grounds. In the _Physical Monadology_

Kant gives his

adherence to dynamism (matter the product of attraction and repulsion), and

makes the monads or elements of body fill space without prejudice to

their simplicity. A series of treatises is devoted to subjects in natural

science: The Effect of the Tides in retarding the Earth's Rotation; The

Obsolescence of the Earth; Fire (Inaugural Dissertation), Earthquakes, and

the Theory of the Winds. The most important of these, the _General Natural

History and Theory of the Heavens_, 1755, which for a long time remained

unnoticed, and which was dedicated to Frederick II., developed the

hypothesis (carried out forty years later by Laplace in ignorance of Kant's

work) of the mechanical origin of the universe and of the motion of the

planets. It presupposes merely the two forces of matter, attraction and

repulsion, and its primitive chaotic condition, a world-mist with elements

of different density. It is noticeable that Kant acknowledges the failure

of the mechanical theory at two points: it is brought to a halt at the

origin of the organic world and at the origin of matter.

The mechanical

cosmogony is far from denying creation; on the contrary, the proof that

this well-ordered and purposive world necessarily arose from the regular

action of material forces under law and without divine intervention, can

only serve to support our assumption of a Supreme Intelligence as the

author of matter and its laws; the belief is necessary, just because

nature, even in its chaotic condition, can act only in an orderly and

regular way.

The empirical phase of Kant's development is represented by the writings

of the 60's. _The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures_, 1762,

asserts that the first figure is the only natural one, and that the others

are superfluous and need reduction to the first. In the _Only Possible

Foundation for a Demonstration of the Existence of God_, 1763, which, in

the seventh Reflection of the Second Division, recapitulates the cosmogony

advanced in the _Natural History of the Heavens_, the discussions

concerning being ("existence" is absolute position, not a predicate which

increases the sum of the qualities but is posited in a merely relative

way), and the conclusion, prophetical of his later point of view, "It is

altogether necessary that we should be _convinced_ of the existence of God,

but not so necessary that his existence should be _demonstrated_" are more

noteworthy than the argument itself. This runs: All possibility presupposes

something actual wherein and whereby all that is conceivable is given as

a determination or a consequence. That actuality the destruction of which

would destroy all possibility is absolutely necessary.

Therefore there

exists an absolutely necessary Being as the ultimate real ground of all

possibility; this Being is one, simple, unchangeable, eternal, the _ens

realissimum_ and a spirit. The _Attempt to introduce the Notion of

Negative Quantities into Philosophy_, 1763, distinguishes--contrary to

Crusius--between logical opposition, contradiction or mere negation (_a_

and _not-a_, pleasure and the absence of pleasure, power and lack of

power), and real opposition, which cannot be explained by logic (+_a_ and

-_a_, pleasure and pain, capital and debts, attraction and repulsion;

in real opposition both determinations are positive, but in opposite

directions). Parallel with this it distinguishes, also, between logical

ground and real ground. The prize essay, _Inquiry concerning the Clearness_

(Evidence) _of the Principles of Natural Theology and Ethics_, 1764, draws

a sharp distinction between mathematical and metaphysical knowledge, and

warns philosophy against the hurtful imitation of the geometrical method,

in place of which it should rather take as an example the method which

Newton introduced into natural science. Quantity constitutes the object of

mathematics, qualities, the object of philosophy; the former is easy and

simple, the latter difficult and complicated--how much more comprehensible

the conception of a trillion is than the philosophical idea of freedom,

which the philosophers thus far have been unable to make intelligible.

In mathematics the general is considered under symbols _in concrete_, in

philosophy, by means of symbols _in abstracto_; the former constructs its

object in sensuous intuition, while the object of the latter is given

to it, and that as a confused concept to be decomposed.

Mathematics,

therefore, may well begin with definitions, since the conception which is

to be explained is first brought into being through the definition, while

philosophy must begin by seeking her conceptions. In the former the

definition is first in order, and in the latter almost always last; in the

one case the method is synthetic, in the other it is analytic. It is the

function of mathematics to connect and compare clear and certain concepts

of quantity in order to draw conclusions from them; the function of

philosophy is to analyze concepts given in a confused state, and to make

them detailed and definite. Philosophy has also this disadvantage, that

it possesses very many undecomposable concepts and undemonstrable

propositions, while mathematics has only a few such.

"Philosophical truths

are like meteors, whose brightness gives no assurance of their permanence.

They vanish, but mathematics remains. Metaphysics is without doubt the most

difficult of all human sciences _(Einsichten)_, but a metaphysic has

never yet been written"; for one cannot be so kind as to

"apply the term

philosophy to all that is contained in the books which bear this title." In

the closing paragraphs, on the ultimate bases of ethics, the stern features

of the categorical imperative are already seen, veiled by the English

theory of moral sense, while the attractive _Observations on the Feeling

of the Beautiful and the Sublime_, which appeared in the same year, still

naïvely follow the empirical road.

The empirical phase reaches its skeptical termination in the satire _Dreams

of a Ghost-seer explained by the Dreams of Metaphysics_, 1766, which pours

out its ingenious sarcasm impartially on spiritualism and on the assumed

knowledge of the suprasensible. Here Kant is already clearly conscious of

his new problem, a theory of the limits of human reason, conscious also

that the attack on this problem is to be begun by a discussion of the

question of space. This second question had been for many years a frequent

subject of his reflections;[1] and it was this part of the general critical

problem that first received definitive solution. In the Latin dissertation

_On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and Intelligible World_, 1770,

which concludes the pre-critical period, and which was written on the

occasion of his assumption of his chair as ordinary professor, the

critique of sensibility, the new theory of space and time, is set forth in

approximately the same form as in the _Critique of Pure Reason_, while the

critique of the understanding and of reason, the theory of the categories

and the Ideas and of the sphere of their validity, required for its

completion the intellectual labor of several more years.

For this essay,

_De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Principiis_, leaves

unchallenged the possibility of a knowledge of things in themselves and of

God, thus showing that its author has abandoned the skepticism maintained

in the _Dreams of a Ghost-seer_, and has turned anew to dogmatic

rationalism, whose final overthrow required another swing in the direction

of skeptical empiricism. In regard to the progress of this latter phase

of opinion, the letters to M. Herz are almost the only, though not very

valuable, source of information.

[Footnote 1: _New Theory of Motion and Rest_, 1758; _On the First Ground of

the Distinction of Positions in Space_, 1768; besides several of the works

mentioned above.]

The _Critique of Pure Reason_ appeared in 1781, much later than Kant had

hoped when he began a work on "The Limits of Sensibility and Reason," and a

second, altered edition in 1787.[1] After the _Prolegomena to every Future

Metaphysic which may present itself as Science_, 1783, had given a popular

form to the critical doctrine of knowledge, it was followed by the critical

philosophy of ethics in the _Foundation of the Metaphysics of Ethics_,

1785, and the _Critique of Practical Reason_, 1788; by the critical

aesthetics and teleology in the _Critique of Judgment_, 1790; and by the

critical philosophy of religion in _Religion within the Limits of Reason

Only_, 1793[2] (consisting of four essays, of which the first, "Of Radical

Evil," had already appeared in the _Berliner Monatsschrift_ in 1792). The

_Metaphysical Elements of Natural Science_, 1786, and the _Metaphysics

of Ethics_, 1797 (in two parts, "Metaphysical Elements of the Theory of

Right," and "Metaphysical Elements of the Theory of Virtue "), are devoted

to the development of the system. The year 1798 brought two more larger

works, the _Conflict of the Faculties_ and the _Anthropology_. Of the

reviews, that on Herder's _Ideen_ maybe mentioned, and among the minor

essays, the following: _Idea for a Universal History in a Cosmopolitan

Sense, Answer to the Question: What is Illumination f_

both in 1784;

_What does it mean to Orient oneself in Thought_? 1786; _On the Use of

Teleological Principles in Philosophy_, 1788; _On a Discovery according to

which all Recent Criticism of Pure Reason is to be superseded by a Previous

One_, 1790; _On the Progress of Metaphysics since the Time of Wolff; On

Philosophy in General, The End of all Things_, 1794; _On Everlasting

Peace_, 1795. Kant's _Logic_ was published by Jäsche in 1800; his _Physical

Geography_ and his _Observations on Pedagogics_ by F.T.

Rink in 1803; his

lectures on the _Philosophical Theory of Religion_

(1817; 2d. ed., 1830)

and on _Metaphysics_ (1821; cf. Benno Erdmann in the _Philosophische

Monatshefte_, vol. xix. 1883, p. 129 _seq_., and vol.

xx. 1884, p. 65

_seq_.) by Pölitz. If we may judge by the specimens given by Reicke in the

_Altpreussische Monatsschrift_, 1882-84, and by Krause himself,[3]

the promised publication of a manuscript of Kant's last years, now in

possession of the Hamburg pastor, Albrecht Krause, and which discusses the

transition from the metaphysical elements of natural science to physics,

will hardly meet the expectations which some have cherished concerning it.

Benno Erdmann has issued _Nachträge zu Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft aus

Kants Nachlass_, 1881, and _Reflexionen Kants zur kritischen Philosophie

aus handschriftlichen Aufzeichnungen_--the first volume first _Heft

(Reflexionen zur Anthropologie_) appearing in 1882, the second volume

_(Reflexionen zur Kritik der reinen Vernunft, aus Kants Handexemplar

von Baumgartens Metaphysica)_ in 1884. Max Müller has made an English

translation of the _Critique of Pure Reason_, 2 vols., 1881.[4]