History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

changes under his hands into another, that of proving the existence of

external phenomena. "That external objects are real as representations"

Berkeley had never disputed.]

On the basis of the inseparability of sensibility and understanding the

ideal of knowledge--an extension of knowledge to be attained by _a priori_

means (p. 333)--experiences a remarkable addition in the position that the

rational synthesis thus obtained must be a knowledge of reality, must be

applied to matter given in intuition. To the question,

"How are synthetic

judgments _a priori possible_?" is joined a second equally legitimate

inquiry, "How do they become _objectively valid_, or applicable to objects

of experience?" The principle from which their validity is proved--they are

applicable to objects of experience because _without them experience would

not be possible_, because they are _conditions of experience_--like the

criterion of apriority (strict universality and necessity), is one of the

noëtic assumptions of the critical theory.[1]

[Footnote 1: Cf. Vaihinger, _Kommentar_, i. pp. 425-430.]

Inasmuch as its investigation relates to the conditions of experience the

Kantian criticism follows a method which it itself terms _transcendental_.

Heretofore, when the metaphysical method had been adopted, the object had

been the suprasensible; and when knowledge had been made the object of

investigation, the method followed had been empirical, psychological. Kant

had the right to consider himself the creator of noëtics, for he showed it

the transcendental point of view. Knowledge is an object of experience, but

its conditions are not. The object is to explain knowledge, not merely to

describe it psychologically,--to establish a new science of knowledge from

principles, from pure reason. That which lies beyond experience is

sealed from our thought; that which lies on this side of it is still

uninvestigated, though capable and worthy of investigation, and in

extreme need thereof. Criticism forbids the _transcendent_ use of reason

(transcending experience); it permits, demands, and itself exercises the

_transcendental_[1] use of it, which explains an experiential object,

knowledge, from its conditions, which are not empirically given.

[Footnote A: Kant applies the term _transcendental_ to the knowledge (the

discovery, the proof) of the _a priori_ factor and its relation to objects

of experience. Unfortunately he often uses the same word not only to

designate the _a priori_ element itself, but also as a synonym for

transcendent. In all three cases its opposite is _empirical_, namely,

empirico-psychological investigation by observation in distinction from

noëtical investigation from principles; empirical origin in distinction

from an origin in pure reason, and empirical use in distinction from

application beyond the limits of experience.]

There is, apparently, a contradiction between the empiristic result of the

Critique of Reason (the limitation of knowledge to objects of experience)

and its rationalistic proofs (which proceed metaphysically, not

empirically), and, in fact, a considerable degree of opposition really

exists. Kant argues in a metaphysical way that there can be no metaphysics.

This contradiction is solved by the distinction which has been mentioned

between that which is beyond, and that which lies within, the boundary of

experience. That metaphysic is forbidden which on the objective side soars

beyond experience, but that pure rational knowledge is permissible and

necessary which develops from principles the grounds of experiential

knowledge existing in the subject. In the Kantian school, however, these

complementary elements,--empirical result, transcendental or metaphysical,

properly speaking, pro-physical method,--were divorced, and the one

emphasized, favored, and further developed at the expense of the other.

The empiricists hold to the result, while they either weaken or completely

misunderstand the rationalism of the method: the _a priori_ factor, says

Fries, was not reached by _a priori_, but by _a posteriori_, means, and

there is no other way by which it could have been reached. The constructive

thinkers, Fichte and his successors, adopt and continue the metaphysical

method, but reject the empirical result. Fichte's aim is directed to

a system of necessary, unconscious processes of reason, among which,

rejecting the thing in itself, he includes sensation.

According to

Schelling nature itself is _a priori_, a condition of consciousness. This

discrepancy between foundation and result continues in an altered form even

among contemporary thinkers--as a discussion whether the

"main purpose"

of Criticism is to be found in the limitation of knowledge to possible

experience, or the establishment of _a priori_ elements-

-though many, in

adherence to Kant's own view, maintain that the metaphysics of knowledge

and of phenomena (immanent rationalism) is the only legitimate metaphysics.

%1. Theory of Knowledge.

(a) The Pure Intuitions (Transcendental Aesthetic).%--

The first part of the

Critique of Reason, the Transcendental Aesthetic, lays down the position

that _space and time_ are not independent existences, not real beings, and

not properties or relations which would belong to things in themselves

though they were not intuited, but _forms of our intuition_, which have

their basis in the subjective constitution of our, the human, mind. If we

separate from sensuous intuition all that the understanding thinks in it

through its concepts, and all that belongs to sensation, these two forms of

intuition remain, which may be termed pure intuitions, since they can be

considered apart from all sensation. As subjective _conditions_ (lying in

the nature of the subject) through which alone a thing can become an object

of intuition for us, they precede all empirical intuitions or are

_a priori_.

Space and time are neither substantial receptacles which contain all

that is real nor orders inhering in things in themselves, but forms of

intuition. Now all our representations are either pure or empirical in

their origin, and either intuitive or conceptual in character. Kant

advances four proofs for the position that space and time are not empirical

and not concepts, but pure intuitions: (1) Time is not an empirical

concept which has been abstracted from experience. For the coexistence or

succession of phenomena, _i.e._, their existence at the same time or at

different times (from which, as many believe, the representation of time

is abstracted), itself presupposes time--a coexistence or succession is

possible only in time. It is no less false that space is abstracted from

the empirical space relations of external phenomena, their existence

outside and beside one another, or in different places, for it is

impossible to represent relative situation except in space. Therefore

experience does not make space and time possible; but space and time first

of all make experience possible, the one outer, the other inner experience.

They are postulates of perception, not abstractions from it. (2) Time is a

necessary representation _a priori_. We can easily think all phenomena away

from it, but we cannot remove time itself in view of phenomena in general;

we can think time without phenomena, but not phenomena without time. The

same is true of space in reference to external objects.

Both are conditions

of the possibility of phenomena. (3) Time is not a discursive or general

concept. For there is but one time. And different times do not precede the

one time as the constituent parts of which it is made up, but are mere

limitations of it; the part is possible only through the whole. In the same

way the various spaces are only parts of one and the same space, and can

be thought in it alone. But a representation which can be given only by

a single object is a particular representation or an intuition. Because,

therefore, of the oneness of space and time, the representation of each

is an intuition. The _a priori_, immediate intuition of the one space is

entirely different from the empirical, general conception of space, which

is abstracted from the various spaces. (4) Determinate periods of time

arise by limitation of the one, fundamental time.

Consequently this

original time must be unlimited or infinite, and the representation of it

must be an intuition, not a concept. Time contains in itself an endless

number of representations (its parts, times), but this is never the

case with a generic concept, which, indeed, is contained as a partial

representation in an endless number of representations (those of the

individuals having the same name), and, consequently, comprehends them all

under itself, but which never contains them in itself.

The general concept

horse is contained in each particular representation of a horse as a

general characteristic, and that of justice in each representation of a

definite just act; time, however, is not contained in the different times,

but they are contained in it. Similarly the relation of infinite space to

the finite spaces is not the logical relation of a concept to examples of

it, but the intuitive relation of an unlimited whole to its limited parts.

The _Prolegomena_ employs as a fifth proof for the intuitive character of

space, an argument which had already appeared in the essay _On the Ultimate

Ground of the Distinction of Positions in Space_. There are certain spatial

distinctions which can be grasped by intuition alone, and which are

absolutely incapable of comprehension through the understanding--for

example, those of right and left, above and below, before and behind. No

logical marks can be given for the distinction between the object and its

image in the mirror, or between the right ear and the left. The complete

description of a right hand must, in all respects (quality, proportionate

position of parts, size of the whole), hold for the left as well;

but, despite the complete similarity, the one hand cannot be exactly

super-imposed on the other; the glove of the one cannot be worn on the

other. This difference in direction, which has significance only when

viewed from a definite point, and the impossibility mentioned of a

congruence between an object (right hand) and its reflected image (left

hand) can be understood only by intuition; they must be seen and felt, and

cannot be made clear through concepts, and, consequently, can never be

explained to a being which lacks the intuition of space.

In the "transcendental" exposition of space and time Kant follows this

"metaphysical" exposition, which had to prove their non-empirical, and

non-discursive, hence their _a priori_ and intuitive, character, with

the proof that only such an explanation of space and time could make it

conceivable how synthetic cognitions _a priori_ can arise from them. The

principles of mathematics are of this kind. The synthetic character of

geometrical truths is explained by the intuitive nature of space, their

apodictic character by its apriority, and their objective reality or

applicability to empirical objects by the fact that space is the condition

of (external) perception. The like is true of arithmetic and time.

If space were a mere concept, no proposition could be derived from it which

should go beyond the concept and extend our knowledge of its properties.

The possibility of such extension or synthesis in mathematics depends on

the fact that spatial concepts can always be presented or "constructed" in

intuition. The geometrical axiom that in the triangle the sum of two sides

is greater than the third is derived from intuition, by describing the

triangle in imagination or, actually, on the board. Here the object is

given through the cognition and not before it.--If space and time were

empirical representations the knowledge obtained from them would lack

necessity, which, as a matter of fact, it possesses in a marked degree.

While experience teaches us only that something is thus or so, and not that

it could not be otherwise, the axioms, (space has only three dimensions,

time only one; only one straight line is possible between two points),

nay, all the propositions of mathematics are strictly universal and

apodictically certain: we are entirely relieved from the necessity of

measuring all triangles in the world in order to find out whether the sum

of their angles is equal to two right angles, and we do not need, as in the

case of judgments of experience, to add the limitation, so far as it is yet

known there are no exceptions to this rule. The apriority is the _ratio

essendi_ of the strict necessity involved in the "it must be so" _(des

Soseinmüssens_), while the latter is the _ratio cognoscendi_ of the former.

Now since the necessity of mathematical judgments can only be explained

through the ideality of space, this doctrine is perfectly certain, not

merely a probable hypothesis.--The validity of mathematical principles for

all objects of perception, finally, is based on the fact that they are

rules under which alone experience is possible for us.

It should be

mentioned, further, that the conceptions of change and motion (change of

place) are possible only through and in the representation of time. No

concept could make intelligible the possibility of change, that is, of the

connection of contradictory predicates in one and the same thing, but the

intuition of succession easily succeeds in accomplishing it.

The argument is followed by conclusions and explanations based upon it;

(1) Space is the form of the outer, time of the inner, sense. Through the

outer sense external objects are given to us, and through the inner sense

our own inner states. But since all representations, whether they have

external things for their objects or not, belong in themselves, as mental

determinations, to our inner state, time is the formal condition of all

phenomena in general, directly of internal (psychical) phenomena, and,

thereby, indirectly of external phenomena also. (2) The validity of the

relations of space and time cognizable _a priori_ is established for all

objects of possible experience, but is limited to these.

They are valid

for _all phenomena_ (for all things which at any time may be given to our

senses), but only for these, not for things as they are _in themselves_.

They have "empirical reality, but, at the same time, transcendental

ideality." As external phenomena all things are beside one another in

space, and all phenomena whatever are in time and of necessity under

temporal relations; in regard to all things which can occur in our

experience, and in so far as they can occur, space and time are

objectively, therefore empirically, real. But they do not possess absolute

reality (neither subsistent reality nor the reality of inherence); for if

we abstract from our sensuous intuition both vanish, and, apart from the

subject (_N.B._, the transcendental subject, concerning which more below),

they are naught. It is only from man's point of view that we can speak

of space, and of extended, moveable, changeable things; for we can know

nothing concerning the intuitions of other thinking beings, we have no

means of discovering whether they are bound by the same conditions which

limit our intuitions, and which for us are universally valid. (3) Nothing

which is intuited in space is a thing in itself. What we call external

objects are nothing but mere representations of our sensibility, whose

true correlative, the _thing in itself_, cannot be known by ever so deep

penetration into the phenomenon; such properties as belong to things in

themselves can never be given to us through the senses.

Similarly nothing

that is intuited in time is a thing in itself, so that we intuit ourselves

only as we appear to ourselves, and not as we are.

The merely empirical reality of space and time, the limitation of their

validity to phenomena, leaves the certainty of knowledge within the limits

of experience intact; for we are equally certain of it, whether these forms

necessarily belong to things in themselves, or only to our intuitions

of things. The assertion of their absolute reality, on the other hand,

involves us in sheer absurdities (that is, it necessitates the assumption

of two infinite nonentities which exist, but without being anything real,

merely in order to comprehend all reality, and on one of which even our own

existence would be dependent), in view of which the origin of so peculiar

a theory as the idealism of Berkeley appears intelligible. The critical

theory of space and time is so far from being identical with, or akin to,

the theory of Berkeley, that it furnishes the best and only defense against

the latter. If anyone assumes the absolute or transcendental reality of

these forms, it is impossible for him to prevent everything, including even

our own existence, from being changed thereby into mere illusion. But

the critical philosopher is far from degrading bodies to mere illusion;

external phenomena are just as real for him as internal phenomena, though

only as phenomena, it is true, as (possible) representations.

Phenomenon and illusion are not the same. The transcendental distinction

between phenomena and things in themselves must not be confused with the

distinction common to ordinary life and to physics, in accordance with

which we call the rainbow a mere appearance (better, illusion), but the

combination of sun and rain which gives rise to this illusion the thing

in itself, as that which in universal experience and in all different

positions with respect to the senses, is thus and not otherwise determined

in intuition, or that which essentially belongs to the intuition of the

object, and is valid for every human sensibility (in antithesis to that

which only contingently belongs to it, and is valid only for a special

position or organization of this or that sense).

Similarly an object always

appears to grow smaller as its distance increases, while in itself it is

and remains of some fixed size. And this use of words is perfectly

correct, in the _physical or empirical_ sense of "in itself"; but in the

_transcendental_ sense the raindrops, also, together with their form and

size, are themselves mere phenomena, the "in itself" of which remains

entirely unknown to us. Kant, moreover, does not wish to see the

subjectivity of the forms of intuition placed on a level with the

subjectivity of sensations or explained by this, though he accepts it as

a fact long established. The sensations of color, of tone, of temperature

are, no doubt, like the representation of space in that they belong only to

the subjective constitution of the sensibility, and can be attributed to

objects only in relation to our senses. But the great difference between

the two is that these sense qualities may be different in different persons

(the color of the rose may seem different to each eye), or may fail to

harmonize with any human sense; that they are not _a priori_ in the same

strict sense as space and time, and consequently afford no knowledge of the

objects of possible experience independently of perception; and that they

are connected with the phenomenon only as the contingently added effects of

a particular organization, while space, as the condition of external

objects, necessarily belongs to the phenomenon or intuition of them. _It is

through space alone that it is possible for things to be external objects

for us_. The subjectivity of sensation is individual, while that of space

and time is general or universal to mankind; the former is empirical,

individually different, and contingent, the latter _a priori_ and

necessary. Space alone, not sensation, is a _conditio sine qua non_ of

external perception. Space and time are the sole _a priori_ elements of

the sensibility; all other sensuous concepts, even motion and change,

presuppose perception; the movable in space and the succession of

properties in an existing thing are empirical data.

In confirmation of the theory that all objects of the senses are mere

phenomena, the fact is adduced that (with the exception of the will and the

feelings, which are not cognitions) nothing is given us through the senses

but representations of relations, while a thing in itself cannot be known

by mere relations. The phenomenon is a sum total of mere relations. In

regard to matter we know only extension, motion, and the laws of this

motion or forces (attraction, repulsion, impenetrability), but all these

are merely relations of the thing to something, else, that is, external

relations. Where is the inner side which underlies this exterior, and

which belongs to the object in itself? This is never to be found in the

phenomenon, and no matter how far the observation and analysis of nature

may advance (a work with unlimited horizons!) they reach nothing but

portions of space occupied by matter and effects which matter exercises,

that is, nothing beyond that which is comparatively internal, and which,

in its turn, consists of external relations. The absolutely inner side

of matter is a mere fancy; and if the complaint that the

"inner side" of

things is concealed from us is to mean that we do not comprehend what

the things which appear to us may be in themselves, it is unjust and

irrational, for it demands that we should be able to intuit without

senses, in other words, that we should be other than men. The transcendent

questions concerning the noumenon of things are unanswerable; we know

ourselves, even, only as phenomena! A phenomenon consists in nothing but

the relation of something in general to the senses.

It is indubitable _that_ something corresponds to phenomena, which,

by affecting our sensibility, occasions sensations in us, and thereby

phenomena. The very word, the very concept,

"phenomenon", indicates a

relation to something which is not phenomenon, to an object not dependent

on the sensibility. _What_ this may be continues hidden from us, for

knowledge is impossible without intuition. Things in themselves are

unknowable. Nevertheless the idea (it must be confessed, the entirely empty

idea) of this "transcendental object", as an indeterminate somewhat = _x_

which underlies phenomena, is not only allowable, but, as a limiting

concept, unavoidable in order to confine the pretensions of sense to the

only field which is accessible to it, that is, to the field of phenomena.

The inference "space and time are nothing but representations and

representations are in us, therefore space and time as well as all

phenomena in them, bodies with their forces and motions, are in us," does

not accurately express Kant's position, for he might justly reply that,

according to him, bodies as phenomena are in different parts in space from

that which we assign to ourselves, and thus without us; that space is the

form of external intuition, and through it external objects arise for us

from sensations; but that, in regard to the things in themselves which

affect us, we are entirely ignorant whether they are within or without us.

It can easily be shown by literal quotations that there were distinct

tendencies in Kant, especially in the first edition of his principal

work, toward a radical idealism which doubts or denies not merely the

cognizability, but also the existence of objects external to the subject

and its representations, and which degrades the thing in itself to a mere

thought in us, or completely does away with it (_e.g._,

"The representation