History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

the subsumption of the latter under the former.

[Footnote 1: This determination is important for psychology. Since

the inner sense shows nothing constant, but everything in a continual

flux,--for the permanent subject of our thoughts is an identical activity

of the understanding, not an intuitable object,--the concept of substance

is not applicable to psychical phenomena.

Representations of a permanent

(material substances) exist, indeed, but not permanent representations. The

abiding self (ego, soul) which we posit back of internal phenomena is, as

the Dialectic will show, a mere Idea, which, or, rather, the object of

which, maybe "thought" as substance, it is true, but cannot be "given" in

intuition, hence cannot be "known."]

As a result of the fact that the schematism permits a presentation of the

categories in time intuition antecedent to all experience, the possibility

is given of synthetic judgments _a priori_ concerning objects of possible

experience. Such judgments, in so far as they are not based on higher

and more general cognitions, are termed "principles,"

and the system of

them--to be given, with the table of the categories as a guide, in

the _Analytic of Principles_ or the Doctrine of the Faculty of

Judgment--furnishes the outlines of "pure natural science." When thus

the rules of the subsumption to be effected have been found in the pure

concepts, and the conditions and criteria of the subsumption in the

schemata, it remains to indicate the principles which the understanding,

through the aid of the schemata, actually produces _a priori_ from its

concepts.

The principle of quantity is the _Axiom of Intuition_, the principle of

quality the _Anticipation of Perception_; the principles of relation

are termed _Analogies of Experience_, those of modality _Postulates

of Empirical Thought in General_. The first runs, "All intuitions are

extensive quantities"; the second, "In all phenomena sensation, and the

real which corresponds to it in the object, has an intensive quantity,

i.e., a degree." The principle of the "Analogies" is,

"All phenomena, as

far as their existence is concerned, are subject _a priori_ to rules,

determining their mutual relation in time" (in the second edition this is

stated as follows: "Experience is possible only through the representation

of a necessary connection of perceptions"). As there are three modes of

time, there result three "Analogies," the principles of permanence, of

succession (production), and of coexistence. These are: (1) "In all changes

of phenomena the substance is permanent, and its quantum is neither

increased nor diminished in nature." (2) "All changes take place according

to the law of connection between cause and effect"; or,

"Everything that

happens (begins to be) presupposes something on which it follows according

to a rule." (3) "All substances, in so far as they are coexistent, stand in

complete community, that is, reciprocity, one to another." And, finally,

the three "Postulates": "That which agrees with the formal conditions of

experience (in intuition and in concepts) is possible,"

"That which is

connected with the material conditions of experience (sensation) is actual"

(perception is the only criterion of actuality). "That which, in its

connection with the actual, is determined by universal conditions of

experience, is (exists as) necessary."

As the categories of substance and causality are specially preferred to the

others by Kant and the Kantians, and are even proclaimed by some as the

only fundamental concepts, so also the principles of relation have an

established reputation for special importance. The leading ideas in the

proofs of the "Analogies of Experience"--for in spite of their underivative

character the principles require, and are capable of, proof--may next be

noted.

The time determinations of phenomena, the knowledge of their duration,

their succession, and their coexistence, form an indispensable part of our

experience, not only of scientific experience, but of everyday experience

as well. How is the objective time-determination of things and events

possible? If the matter in hand is the determination of the particulars of

a fight with a bloody ending, the witnesses are questioned and testify:

We heard and saw how A began the quarrel by insulting B, and the latter

answered the insult with a blow, whereupon A drew his knife and wounded his

opponent. Here the succession of perceptions on the part of the persons

present is accepted as a true reproduction of the succession of the actual

events. But the succession of perceptions is not always the sure indication

of an actual succession: the trees along an avenue are perceived one after

the other, while they are in reality coexistent. We might now propose the

following statement: The representation of the manifold of phenomena is

always successive, I apprehend one part after another. I can decide whether

these parts succeed one another in the object also, or whether they

are coexistent, by the fact that, in the second case, the series of

my perceptions is reversible, while in the first it is not. I can, if I

choose, direct my glance along the avenue in such a way that I shall begin

the second time with the tree at which I left off the first time; if I wish

to assure myself that the parts of a house are coexistent, I cause my eye

to wander from the upper to the lower portions, from the right side to the

left, and then to perform the same motions in the opposite direction. On

the other hand, it is not left to my choice to hear the thunder either

before or after I see the lightning, or to see a passing wagon now here,

now there, but in these cases I am bound in the succession of my sensuous

representations. The possibility of interchange in the series of

perceptions proves an objective coexistence, the impossibility of this,

an objective succession. But this criterion is limited to the immediate

present, and fails us when a time relation between unobserved phenomena is

to be established. If I go at evening into the dining room and see a vessel

of bubbling water, which is to be used in making tea, over a burning spirit

lamp, whence do I derive the knowledge that the water began, and could

begin, to boil only after the alcohol had been lighted, and not before?

Because I have often seen the flame precede the boiling of the water, and

in this the irreversibility of the two perceptions has guaranteed to me the

succession of the events perceived? Then I may only assume that it is very

probable, not that it is certain, that in this case also the order of the

two events has been the same as I have observed several times before. As a

matter of fact, however, we all assert that the water could not have come

into a boiling condition unless the generation of heat had preceded; that

in every case the fire must be there before the boiling of the water can

commence. Whence do we derive this _must_? Simply and alone from the

thought of a causal connection between the two events.

Every phenomenon

_must_ follow in time that phenomenon of which it is the effect, and must

precede that of which it is the cause. It is through the relation of

causality, and through this alone, that the objective time relation of

phenomena is determined. If nothing preceded an event on which it must

follow according to a rule,[1] then all succession in perception would be

subjective merely, and nothing whatever would be objectively determined by

it as to what was the antecedent and what the consequent in the phenomenon

itself. We should then have a mere play of representations without

significance for the real succession of events. Only the thought of a rule,

according to which the antecedent state contains the necessary condition of

the consequent state, justifies us in transferring the time order of our

representations to phenomena.[2] Nay, even the distinction between

the phenomenon itself, as the object of our representations, and our

representations of it, is effected only by subjecting the phenomenon to

this rule, which assigns to it its definite position in time after another

phenomenon by which it is caused, and thus forbids the inversion of the

perceptions. We can derive the rule of the understanding which produces the

objective time order of the manifold from experience, only because we have

put it into experience, and have first brought experience into being by

means of the rule. We recapitulate in Kant's own words: The objective

(time) relation of phenomena remains undetermined by mere perception (the

mere succession in my apprehension, if it is not determined by means of a

rule in relation to an antecedent, does not guarantee any succession in

the object). In order that this may be known as determined, the relation

between the two states must be so conceived (through the understanding's

concept of causality) that it is thereby determined with necessity which of

them must be taken as coming first, and which second, and not conversely.

Thus it is only by subjecting the succession of phenomena to the law of

causality that empirical knowledge of them is possible.

Without the concept

of cause no objective time determination, and hence, without it, no

experience.

[Footnote 1: "A reality following on an empty time, that is, a beginning of

existence preceded by no state of things, can as little be apprehended as

empty time itself."]

[Footnote 2: "If phenomena were things in themselves no one would be able,

from the succession of the representations of their manifold, to tell how

this is connected in the object."]

That which the relation of cause and effect does for the succession[1] of

phenomena, the relation of reciprocity does for their coexistence, and that

of substance and accident for their duration. Since absolute time is not an

object of perception, the position of phenomena in time cannot be directly

determined, but only through a concept of the understanding. When I

conclude that two objects (the earth and the moon) must be coexistent,

because perceptions of them can follow upon one another in both ways, I

do this on the presupposition that the objects themselves reciprocally

determine their position in time, hence are not isolated, but stand in

causal community or a relation of reciprocal influence.

It is only on the

condition of reciprocity between phenomena, through which they form a

whole, that I can represent them as coexistent.

[Footnote 1: Against the objection that cause and effect are frequently,

indeed in most cases, simultaneous (_e.g._ the heated stove and the warmth

of the room), Kant remarks that the question concerns the order of time

merely, and not the lapse of time. The ball lying on a soft cushion is

simultaneous, it is true, with its effect, the depression in the cushion.

"But I, nevertheless, distinguish the two by the time relation of dynamical

connection. For if I place the ball on the cushion, its previously smooth

surface is followed by a depression, but if there is a depression in the

cushion (I know not whence) a leaden ball does not follow from it."]

Coexistence and succession can be represented only in a permanent

substratum; they are merely the modes in which the permanent exists. Since

time (in which all change takes place, but which itself abides and does not

change) in itself cannot be perceived, the substratum of simultaneity and

succession must exist in phenomena themselves: the permanent in relation

to which alone all the time relations of phenomena can be determined, is

substance; that which alters is its determinations, accidents, or special

modes of existing. Alteration, _i.e._, origin and extinction, is true of

states only, which can begin and cease to be, and not of substances, which

change (_sich verändern_), i.e., pass from one mode of existence into

another, but do not alter (_wechseln_), i.e., pass from non-existence into

existence, or the reverse. It is the permanent alone that changes, and

its states alone that begin and cease to be. The origin and extinction of

substances, or the increase and diminution of their quantum, would remove

the sole condition of the empirical unity of time; for the time relations

of the coexistent and the successive can be perceived only in an identical

substratum, in a permanent, which exists always. The law

"From nothing

nothing comes, and nothing can return to nothing," is everywhere assumed

and has been frequently advanced, but never yet proved, for, indeed, it is

impossible to prove it dogmatically. Here the only possible proof for it,

the critical proof, is given: the principle of permanence is a necessary

condition of experience. The same argument establishes the principle of

sufficient reason, and the principle of the community of substances,

together with the unity of the world to be inferred from this. The three

Analogies together assert: "All phenomena exist in one nature and must so

exist, because without such a unity _a priori_ no unity of experience,

and therefore no determination of objects in experience, would be

possible."--In connection with the Postulates the same transcendental proof

is given for a series of other laws of nature _a priori_, viz., that in the

course of the changes in the world--for the causal principle holds only for

effects in nature, not for the existence of things as substances--there

can be neither blind chance nor a blind necessity (but only a conditional,

hence an intelligible, necessity); and, further, that in the series of

phenomena, there can be neither leap, nor gap, nor break, and hence no

void--_in mundo non datur casus, non datur fatum, non datur saltus, non

datur hiatus_.

While the dynamical principles have to do with the relation of phenomena,

whether it be to one another (Analogies), or to our faculty of cognition

(Postulates), the mathematical relate to the quantity of intuitions and

sensations, and furnish the basis for the application of mathematics

to natural science.[1] An extensive quantity is one in which the

representation of the parts makes the representation of the whole possible,

and so precedes it. I cannot represent a line without drawing it in

thought, i.e., without producing all parts of it one after the other,

starting from a point. All phenomena are intuited as aggregates or as

collections of previously given parts. That which geometry asserts of

pure intuition (i.e., the infinite divisibility of lines) holds also of

empirical intuition. An intensive quantity is one which is apprehended only

as unity, and in which plurality can be represented only by approximation

to negation = 0. Every sensation, consequently every reality in phenomena,

has a degree, which, however small it may be, is never the smallest, but

can always be still more diminished; and between reality and negation there

exists a continuous connection of possible smaller intermediate sensations,

or an infinite series of ever decreasing degrees. The property of

quantities, according to which no part in them is the smallest possible

part, and no part is simple, is termed their continuity.

All phenomena

are continuous quantities, i.e., all their parts are in turn (further

divisible) quantities. Hence it follows, first, that a proof for an empty

space or empty time can never be drawn from experience, and secondly, that

all change is also continuous. "It is remarkable," so Kant ends his proof

of the Anticipation, "that of quantities in general we can know one

_quality_ only _a priori_, namely, their continuity, while with regard to

quality (the real of phenomena) nothing is known to us _a priori_ but their

intensive _quantity_, that is, that they must have a degree. Everything

else is left to experience."

[Footnote 1: In each particular science of nature, science proper (i.e.,

apodictically certain science) is found only to the extent in which

mathematics can be applied therein. For this reason chemistry can never

be anything more than a systematic art or experimental doctrine; and

psychology not even this, but only a natural history of the inner sense or

natural description of the soul. That which Kant's _Metaphysical Elements

of Natural Science_, 1786--in four chapters, Phoronomy, Dynamics,

Mechanics, and Phenomenology--advances as pure physics or the metaphysics

of corporeal nature, is a doctrine of motion. The fundamental determination

of matter (of a somewhat which is to be the object of the external senses)

is motion, for it is only through motion that these senses can be affected,

and the understanding itself reduces all other predicates of matter to

this. The second and most valuable part of the work defines matter as the

movable, that which fills space by its moving force, and recognizes two

original forces, repulsive, expansive superficial force or force of

contact, by which a body resists the entrance of other bodies into its own

space, and attractive, penetrative force or the force which works at a

distance, in virtue of which all particles of matter attract one another.

In order to a determinate filling of space the co-operation of both

fundamental forces is required. In opposition to the mechanical theory of

the atomists, which explains forces from matter and makes them inhere in

it, Kant holds fast to the dynamical view which he had early adopted (cf.

p. 324), according to which forces are the primary factor and matter is

constituted by them.]

The outcome of the Analytic of Principles sounds bold enough. _The

understanding is the lawgiver of nature_: "It does not draw its laws _a

priori_ from nature, but prescribes them to it"; the principles of the pure

understanding are the most universal laws of nature, the empirical laws of

nature only particular determinations of these. All order and regularity

take their origin in the spirit, and are put into objects by this.

Universal and necessary knowledge remained inexplicable so long as it was

assumed that the understanding must conform itself to objects; it is at

once explained if, conversely, we make objects conform themselves to the

understanding. This is a reversal of philosophical opinion which may justly

be compared to the Copernican revolution in astronomy; it is just as

paradoxical as the latter, but just as incontestably true, and just as rich

in results. The sequel will show that this strangely sounding principle,

that things conform themselves to our representations and the laws of

nature are dependent on the understanding, is calculated to make us humble

rather than proud. Our understanding is lawgiver within the limits of its

knowledge, no doubt, but it knows only within the limits of its legislative

authority; nature, to which it dictates laws, is nothing but a totality of

phenomena; beyond the limits of the phenomenal, where its commands become

of no effect, its wishes also find no hearing.

In the second edition the Analytic of Principles contains as a supplement a

"Refutation of Idealism," which, in opposition to Descartes's position that

the only immediate experience is inner experience, from which we reach

outer experience by inference alone, argues that, conversely, it is only

through outer experience, which is immediate experience proper, that inner

experience--as the consciousness of my own existence in time--is possible.

For all time determination presupposes something permanent in perception,

and this permanent something cannot be in me (the mere representation of an

external thing), but only actually existing things which I perceive without

me. There is, further, a chapter on the "Ground of the Distinction of all

Objects in general into Phenomena and Noumena," with an appendix on the

Amphiboly (ambiguity) of the Concepts of Reflection. The latter shows

that the concepts of comparison: identity and difference, agreement and

opposition, the internal and the external, matter and form, acquire

entirely different meanings when they relate to phenomena and to things in

themselves (in other words, to things in their relation to the sensibility,

and in relation to the understanding merely); and further, in a criticism

of the philosophy of Leibnitz, reproaches him with having intellectualized

phenomena, while Locke is said to have sensationalized the concepts of the

understanding.

The chapter on the distinction between phenomena and noumena very much

lessens the hopes, aroused, perchance, by the establishment of the

non-empirical origin of the categories, for an application of these not

confined to any experience. Although the categories, that is, are in their

origin entirely independent of all experience (so much so that they first

make experience possible), they are yet confined in their application

within the bounds of possible experience. They "serve only to spell

phenomena, that we may be able to read them as experience," and when

applied to things in themselves lose all significance.[1] Similarly the

principles which spring from them are "nothing more than principles of

possible experience," and can be referred to phenomena alone, beyond which

they are arbitrary combinations without objective reality. Things in

themselves may be thought, but they can never be known; for knowledge,

besides the empty thought of an object, implies intuitions which must be

subsumed under it or by which the object must be determined. In themselves

the pure concepts relate to all that is thinkable, not merely to that which

can be experienced, but the schemata, which assures their applicability in

the field of experience, at the same time limit them to this sphere. The

schematism makes the immanent use of the categories, and thus a metaphysics

of phenomena, possible, but the transcendent use of them, and consequently

the metaphysics of the suprasensible, impossible. The case would be

different if our intuition were intellectual instead of sensuous, or,

which is the same thing, if our understanding were intuitive instead of

discursive; then the objects which we think would not need to be given us

from another source (through sensuous intuition), but would be themselves

produced in the act by which we thought them. The divine spirit may be such

an archetypal, creative understanding (_intellectus archetypus_), which

generates objects by its thought; the human spirit is not such, and

therefore is confined, with its knowledge, within the circle of possible

perception.--The conception of "intellectual intuition"

leads to a

distinction in regard to things in themselves: in its negative meaning

noumenon denotes a thing in so far as it is _not_ the object of our

_sensuous_ intuition, in its positive meaning a thing which is the

object of a _non-sensuous_ intuition. The positive thing in itself is a

problematical concept; its possibility depends on the existence of an

intuitive understanding, something about which we are ignorant. The

negative thing in itself cannot be known, indeed, but it can be thought;

and the representation of it is a possible concept, one which is not

self-contradictory[2] (a principle which is of great importance for

practical philosophy). Still further, it is an indispensable concept, which

shows that the boundary where our intuition ends is not the boundary of

the thinkable as well; and even if it affords no positive extension of

knowledge[3] it is, nevertheless, very useful, since it sets bounds to the

use of the understanding, and thus, as it were, negatively extends our

knowledge. That which lies beyond the boundary, the "how are they possible"

_(Wiemöglichkeit)_ of things in themselves is shrouded in darkness, but the

boundary itself, _i.e._, the