History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

[Footnote 2: In 1879 a summons was sent forth from Rome for the revival and

dissemination of the Thomistic system as the only true philosophy (cf. R.

Eucken, _Die Philosophic des Thomas von Aquino und die Kultur der

Neuzeit_, 1886). This movement is supported by the journals, _Jahrbuch für

Philosophie und spekulative Theologie_, edited by Professor E. Commer

of Münster, 1886 _seq_., and _Philosophisches Jahrbuch_, edited, at the

instance and with the support of the Görres Society, by Professor Const.

Gutberlet of Fulda, 1888 _seq_. While the text-books of Hagemann, Stoeckl,

Gutberlet, Pesch, Commer, C.M. Schneider, and others also follow Scholastic

lines, B. Bolzano (died 1848), M. Deutinger (died 1864) and his pupil

Neudecker, Oischinger, Michelis, and W. Rosenkrantz (1821-74; _Science of

Knowledge_, 1866-68), who was influenced by Schelling, have taken a freer

course.]

[Footnote 2: Trahndorff, gymnasial professor in Berlin (1782-1863),

_Aesthetics_, 1827 (cf. E. von Hartmann in the _Philosophische

Monatshefte_, vol. xxii. 1886, p. 59 _seq_., and J. von Billewicz, in the

same, vol. xxi. 1885, p. 561 _seq_.); J.F. Reiff in Tübingen: _System of

the Determinations of the Will_, 1842; K. Chr. Planck (died 1880): _The

Ages of the World_, 1850 _seq_.; _Testament of a German_, edited by Karl

Köstlin, 1881; F. Röse (1815-59), _On the Method of the Knowledge of

the Absolute_, 1841; _Psychology as Introduction to the Philosophy of

Individuality_, 1856. Emanuel Sharer follows Röse.

Friedrich Rohmer

(died 1856): _Science of God, Science of Man_, in _Friedrich Rohmer's

Wissenschaft und Leben_, edited by Bluntschli and Rud.

Seele, 6 vols.,

1871-92.]

Anton Günther (engaged in authorship from 1827; _Collected Writings_, 1881;

_Anti-Savarese_, edited with an appendix by P. Knoodt), who in 1857

was compelled to retract his views, invokes the spirit of Descartes in

opposition to the Hegelian pantheism. In agreement with Descartes,

Günther starts from self-consciousness (in the ego being and thought are

identical), and brings not only the Creator and the created world, but also

nature (to which the soul is to be regarded as belonging) and spirit into

a relation of exclusive opposition, yet holds that in man nature (body and

soul) and spirit are united, and that they interact without prejudice to

their qualitative difference. J.H. Pabst (died in 1838

in Vienna), Theodor

Weber of Breslau, Knoodt of Bonn (died 1889), V. Knauer of Vienna and

others are Güntherians.

Adolf Trendelenburg[1] of Berlin, the acute critic of Hegel and Herbart,

in his own thinking goes back to the philosophy of the past, especially to

that of Aristotle. Motion and purpose are for him fundamental facts, which

are common to both being and thinking, which mediate between the two, and

make the agreement of knowledge and reality possible.

The ethical is a

higher stage of the organic. Space, time, and the categories are forms of

thought as well as of being; the logical form must not be separated from

the content, nor the concept from intuition. We must not fail to mention

that Trendelenburg introduced a peculiar and fruitful method of treating

the history of philosophy, viz., the historical investigation of particular

concepts, in which Teichmüller of Dorpat (1832-88; _Studies in the History

of Concepts_, 1874; _New Studies in the History of Concepts_, 1876-79;

_The Immortality of the Soul_, 2d ed., 1879; _The Nature of Love_, 1880;

_Literary Quarrels in the Fourth Century before Christ_, 1881 and 1884),

and Eucken of Jena (cf. pp. 17 and 623) have followed his example. Kym in

Zurich (born 1822; _Metaphysical Investigations_, 1875; _The Problem of

Evil_, 1878) is a pupil of Trendelenburg.

[Footnote 1: Trendelenburg: _Logical Investigations_, 1840, 3d ed., 1870;

_Historical Contributions to Philosophy_, 3 vols., 1846, 1855, 1867;

_Natural Law on the Basis of Ethics_, 1860, 2d ed., 1868. On Trendelenburg

cf. Eucken in the _Philosophische Monatshefte_, 1884.]

Of more recent systematic attempts the following appear worthy of

mention: Von Kirchmann (1802-84; from 1868 editor of the _Philosophische

Bibliothek_), _The Philosophy of Knowledge_, 1865; _Aesthetics_, 1868; _On

the Principles of Realism_, 1875; _Catechism of Philosophy_ 2d ed., 1881;

E. Dühring (born 1833), _Natural Dialectic_, 1865; _The Value of Life_,

1865, 3d ed, 1881; _Critical History of the Principles of Mechanics_,

1873, 2d ed., 1877; _Course of Philosophy_, 1875 (cf. on Dühring, Helene

Druskowitz, 1889); J. Baumann of Göttingen (born 1837), _Philosophy as

Orientation concerning the World_, 1872; _Handbook of Ethics_, 1879;

_Elements of Philosophy_, 1891; L. Noiré, _The Monistic Idea_, 1875, and

many other works; Frohschammer of Munich (born 1821), _The Phantasy as

the Fundamental Principle of the World-process_, 1877; _On the Genesis

of Humanity, and its Spiritual Development in Religion, Morality and

Language_, 1883; _On the Organization and Culture of Human Society_, 1885.

In the first rank of the thinkers who have made their appearance since

Hegel and Herbart stand Fechner and Lotze, both masters in the use of exact

methods, yet at the same time with their whole souls devoted to the highest

questions, and superior to their contemporaries in breadth of view as in

the importance and range of their leading ideas--Fechner a dreamer and

sober investigator by turns, Lotze with gentle hand reconciling the

antitheses in life and science.

Gustav Theodor Fechner[1] (1801-87; professor at Leipsic) opposes the

abstract separation of God and the world, which has found a place in

natural inquiry and in theology alike, and brings the two into the same

relation of correspondence and reciprocal reference as the soul and the

body. The spirit gives cohesion to the manifold of material parts, and

needs them as a basis and material for its unifying activity. As our

ego connects the manifold of our activities and states in the unity of

consciousness, so the divine spirit is the supreme unity of consciousness

for all being and becoming. In the spirit of God everything is as in ours,

only expanded and enhanced. Our sensations and feelings, our thoughts and

resolutions are His also, only that He, whose body all nature is, and to

whom not only that which takes place in spirits is open, but also that

which goes on between them, perceives more, feels deeper, thinks higher,

and wills better things than we. According to the analogy of the human

organism, both the heavenly bodies and plants are to be conceived as beings

endowed with souls, although they lack nerves, a brain, and voluntary

motion. How could the earth bring forth living beings, if it were itself

dead? Shall not the flower itself rejoice in the color and fragrance which

it produces, and with which it refreshes us? Though its psychical life may

not exceed that of an infant, its sensations, at all events, since they do

not form the basis of a higher activity, are superior in force and richness

to those of the animal. Thus the human soul stands intermediate in the

scale of psychical life: beneath and about us are the souls of plants and

animals, above us the spirits of the earth and stars, which, sharing in and

encompassing the deeds and destinies of their inhabitants, are in

their turn embraced by the consciousness of the universal spirit. The

omnipresence of the divine spirit affords at the same time the means of

escaping from the desolate "night view" of modern science, which looks upon

the world outside the perceiving individual as dark and silent. No, light

and sound are not merely subjective phenomena within us, but extend around

us with objective reality--as sensations of the divine spirit, to which

everything that vibrates resounds and shines.

[Footnote 1: _Nanna, or on the Psychical Life of Plants_, 1848;

_Zend-Avesta, or on the Things of Heaven and the World Beyond_, 1851;

_Physical and Philosophical Atomism_, 1855; _The Three Motives and Grounds

of Belief_, 1863; _The Day View_, 1879; _Elements of Aesthetics_, 1876;

_Elements of Psycho-physics_, 1860; _In the Cause of Psycho-physics_, 1877;

_Review of the Chief Points in Psycho-physics_, 1882; _Book of the Life

after Death_, 1836, 3d ed., 1887; _On the Highest Good_, 1846; _Four

Paradoxes_, 1846; _On the Question of the. Soul_, 1861; _Minor Works by Dr.

Mises_ (Fechner's pseudonym), 1875. On Fechner cf. J. E.

Kuntze, Leipsic,

1892.]

The door of the world beyond also opens to the key of analogy. Similar

laws unite the here with the hereafter. As intuition prepares the way for

memory, and lives on in it, so the life of earth merges in the future life,

and continues active in it, elevated to a higher plane.

Fechner treats the

problem of evil in a way peculiar to himself. We must not consider the

fact of evil apart from the effort to remove it. It is the spur to all

activity--without evil, no labor and no progress.

Fechner's "psycho-physics," a science which was founded by him in

continuation of the investigations of Bernoulli, Euler, and especially

of E.H. Weber, wears an entirely different aspect from that of his

metaphysics (the "day view," moreover does not claim to be knowledge,

but belief--though a belief which is historically, practically, and

theoretically well-grounded). This aims to be an exact science of the

relations between body and mind, and to reach indirectly what Herbart

failed to reach by direct methods, that is, a measurement of psychical

magnitudes, using in this attempt the least observable differences in

sensations as the unit of measure. Weber's law of the dependence of the

intensity of the sensation on the strength of the stimulus--the increase

in the intensity of the sensation remains the same when the relative

increase of the stimulus (or the relation of the stimuli) remains

constant;[1] so that, _e.g._, in the case of light, an increase from a

stimulus of intensity 1 to one of intensity 100, gives just the same

increase in the intensity of the sensation as an increase from a stimulus

of intensity 2 (or 3) to a stimulus of 200 (or 300)--is much more generally

valid than its discoverer supposed; it holds good for all the senses. In

the case of the pressure sense of the skin, with an original weight of 15

grams (laid upon the hand when at rest and supported), in order to produce

a sensation perceptibly greater we must add not 1 gram, but 5, and with an

original weight of 30 grams, not 5, but 10. Equal additions to the weights

are not enough to produce a sensation of pressure whose intensity shall

render it capable of being distinguished with certainty, but the greater

the original weights the larger the increments must be; while the

intensities of the sensations form an arithmetical, those of the stimuli

form a geometrical, series; the change in sensation is proportional to the

relative change of the stimulus. Sensations of tone show the same

proportion (3:4) as those of pressure; the sensibility of the muscle sense

is finer (when weights are raised the proportion is 15:16), as also that

of vision (the relative brightness of two lights whose difference of

intensity is just perceptible is 100:101). In addition to the

investigations on the threshold of difference there are others on the

threshold of stimulation (the point at which a sensation becomes just

perceptible), on attention, on methods of measurement, on errors, etc.

Moreover, Fechner does not fail to connect his psycho-physics, the

presuppositions and results of which have recently been questioned in

several quarters,[2] with his metaphysical conclusions.

Both are pervaded

by the fundamental view that body and spirit belong together (consequently

that everything is endowed with a soul, and that nothing is without a

material basis), nay, that they are the same essence, only seen from

different sides. Body is the (manifold) phenomenon for others, while spirit

is the (unitary) self-phenomenon, in which, however, the inner aspect is

the truer one. That which appears to us as the external world of matter,

is nothing but a universal consciousness which overlaps and influences our

individual consciousness. This is Spinozism idealistically interpreted. In

aesthetics Fechner shows himself an extreme representative of the principle

of association.

[Footnote 1: Fechner teaches: The sensation increases and diminishes in

proportion to the logarithm of the stimulus and of the psycho-physical

nervous activity, the latter being directly proportional to the external

stimulus. Others, on the contrary, find a direct dependence between nervous

activity and sensation, and a logarithmic proportion between the external

stimulus and the nervous activity.]

[Footnote 2: So by Helmholtz; Hering _(Fechners psychophysisches Gesetz_,

1875); P. Langer _(Grundlagen der Psychophysik_, 1876); G.E. Müller in

Göttingen _(Zur Grundlegung der Psychophysik_, 1878); F.A. Müller _(Das

Axiom der Psychophysik_, 1882); A. Elsas _(Ueber die Psychophysik_, 1886);

O. Liebmann _(Aphorismen zur Psychologie, Zeitschrift für Philosophie_,

vol. ci.--Wundt has published a number of papers from his psycho-physical

laboratory in his _Philosophische Studien_, 1881 _seq_.

Cf. also Hugo

Münsterberg, _Neue Grundlegung der Psychophysik_ in _Heft_ iii. of his

_Beiträge zur experimentellen Psychologie_, 1889 _seq_).

[Further,

Delboeuf, in French, and a growing literature in English as A. Seth,

_Encyclopedia Britannica_, vol. xxiv. 469-471; Ladd, _Elements of

Physiological Psychology_, part ii. chap, v.; James, _Principles of

Psychology_, vol. i. p. 533 _seq_.; and numerous articles as Ward,

_Mind_, vol. i.; Jastrow, _American Journal of Psychology_, vols. i. and

iii.--TR.]]

The most important of the thinkers mentioned in the title of this section

is Rudolph Hermann Lotze (1817-81: born at Bautzen; a student of medicine,

and of philosophy under Weisse, in Leipsic; 1844-81

professor in Göttingen;

died in Berlin). Like Fechner, gifted rather with a talent for the fine and

the suggestive than for the large and the rigorous, with a greater reserve

than the former before the mystical and peculiar, as acute, cautious, and

thorough as he was full of taste and loftiness of spirit, Lotze has proved

that the classic philosophers did not die out with Hegel and Herbart. His

_Microcosmus_ (3 vols., 1856-64, 4th ed., 1884 _seq_; English translation

by Hamilton and Jones, 3d ed., 1888), which is more than an anthropology,

as it is modestly entitled, and _History of Aesthetics in Germany_, 1868,

which also gives more than the title betrays, enjoy a deserved popularity.

These works were preceded by the _Medical Psychology_, 1852, and a polemic

treatise against I.H. Fichte, 1857, as well as by a _Pathology_ and a

_Physiology_, and followed by the _System of Philosophy_, which remained

incomplete (part i. _Logic_, 1874, 2d ed., 1881, English translation

edited by Bosanquet, 2d ed., 1888; part ii.

_Metaphysics_, 1879, English

translation edited by Bosanquet, 2d ed., 1887). Lotze's _Minor Treatises_

have been published by Peipers in three volumes (1885-91); and Rehnisch has

edited eight sets of dictata from his lectures, 1871-84.[1] Since these

"Outlines," all of which we now have in new editions, make a convenient

introduction to the Lotzean system, and are, or should be, in the

possession of all, a brief survey may here suffice.

[Footnote 1: _Outlines of Psychology, Practical Philosophy, Philosophy of

Religion, Philosophy of Nature, Logic and the Encyclopedia of Philosophy,

Metaphysics, Aesthetics_, and the _History of Philosophy since Kant_, all

of which may be emphatically commended to students, especially the one

first mentioned, and, in spite of its subjective position, the last.

[English translations of these _Outlines_ except the fourth and the

last, by Ladd, 1884 _seq_.] On Lotze cf. the obituaries by J. Baumann

(_Philosophische Monatshefte_, vol. xvii.), H. Sommer (_Im Neuen Reich_),

A. Krohn (_Zeitschrift für Philosophie_, vol. lxxxi. pp.

56-93), R.

Falckenberg (Augsburg _Allgemeine Zeitung_, 1881, No.

233), and Rehnisch

(_National Zeitung_ and the _Revue Philosophique_, vol.

xii.). The last of

these was reprinted in the appendix to the _Grundzüge der Aesthetik_, 1884,

which contains, further, a chronological table of Lotze's works, essays,

and critiques, as well as of his lectures. Hugo Sommer has zealously

devoted himself to the popularization of the Lotzean system. Cf., further,

Fritz Koegel, _Lotzes Aesthetik_, Göttingen, 1886, and the article by

Koppelmann referred to above, p. 330.]

The subject of metaphysics is reality. Things which are, events which

happen, relations which exist, representative contents and truths which

are valid, are real. Events happening and relations existing presuppose

existing things as the subjects in and between which they happen and exist.

The being of things is neither their being perceived (for when we say that

a thing is we mean that it continues to be, even when we do not perceive

it), nor a pure, unrelated position, its position in general, but _to be is

to stand in relations_. Further, the _what_ or essence of the things which

enter into these relations cannot be conceived as passive quality, but

only abstractly, as a rule or a law which determines the connection and

succession of a series of qualities. The nature of water, for example, is

the unintuitable somewhat which contains the ground of the change of ice,

first into the liquid condition, and then into steam, when the temperature

increases, and conversely, of the possibility of changing steam back

into water and ice under opposite conditions. And when we speak of an

unchangeable identity of the thing with itself, as a result of which it

remains the same essence amid the change of its phenomena, we mean only the

consistency with which it keeps within the closed series of forms a1, a2,

a3, without ever going over into the series b1, b2. The relations, however,

in which things stand, cannot pass to and fro between things like threads

or little spirits, but are states in things themselves, and the change

of the former always implies a change in these inner states. To stand in

relations means to _exchange actions_. In order to experience such effects

from others and to exercise them upon others, things must neither be wholly

incomparable (as red, hard, sweet) and mutually indifferent, nor yet

absolutely independent; if the independence of individual beings were

complete the process of action would be entirely inconceivable. The

difficulty in the concept of causality--how does being _a_ come to produce

in itself a different state _a_ because another being _b_ enters into the

state [Greek: _b_]?--is removed only when we look on the things as

modes, states, parts of a single comprehensive being, of an infinite,

unconditioned substance, in so far as there is then only an action of

the absolute on itself. Nevertheless the assumption that, in virtue of

the unity and consistency of the absolute or of its impulse to

self-preservation, state [Greek: _b_] in being _b_

follows state

[Greek: _a_] in being _a_ as an accommodation or compensation follows a

disturbance, is not a full explanation of the process of action, does

not remove the difficulty as to how one state can give rise to another.

Metaphysics is, in general, unable to show how reality is made, but only to

remove certain contradictions which stand in the way of the conceivability

of these notions. The so far empty concept of an absolute looks to the

philosophy of religion for its content; the conception of the Godhead as

infinite personality (it is a person in a far higher sense than we) is

first produced when we add to the ontological postulate of a comprehensive

substance the ethical postulate of a supreme good or a universal

world-Idea.

By "thing" we understand the permanent unit-subject of changing states. But

the fact of consciousness furnishes the only guaranty that the different

states _a, [Greek: b], y_, are in reality states of one being, and not so

many different things alternating with one another. Only a conscious

being, which itself effects the distinction between itself and the states

occurring in it, and in memory and recollection feels and knows itself as

their identical subject, is actually a subject which has states. Hence,

if things are to be real, we must attribute to them a nature in essence

related to that of our soul. Reality is existence for self. All beings

are spiritual, and only spiritual beings possess true reality. Thus Lotze

combines the monadology of Leibnitz with the pantheism of Spinoza, just

as he understands how to reconcile the mechanical view of natural science

(which is valid also for the explanation of organic life) with the

teleology and the ethical idealism of Fichte. The sole mission of the

world of forms is to aid in the realization of the ideal purposes of the

absolute, of the world of values.

The ideality of space, which Kant had based on insufficient grounds, is

maintained by Lotze also, only that he makes things stand in "intellectual"

relations, which the knowing subject translates into spatial language. The

same character of subjectivity belongs not only to our sensations, but

also to our ideas concerning the connection of things.

Representations are

results, not copies, of the external stimuli; cognition comes under the

general concept of the interaction of real elements, and depends, like

every effect, as much upon the nature of the being that experiences the

effect as upon the nature of the one which exerts it, or rather, more upon

the former than upon the latter. If, nevertheless, it claims objective

reality, truth must not be interpreted as the correspondence of thought and

its object (the cognitive image can never be like the thing itself), nor

the mission of cognition, made to consist in copying a world already

finished and closed apart from the realm of spirits, to which mental

representation is added as something accessory. Light and sound are not

therefore illusions because they are not true copies of the waves of ether

and of air from which they spring, but they are the end which nature has

sought to attain through these motions, an end, however, which it cannot

attain alone, but only by acting upon spiritual subjects; the beauty and

splendor of colors and tones are that which of right ought to be in the

world; without the new world of representations awakened in spirits by the

action of external stimuli, the world would lack its essential culmination.

The purpose of things is to be known, experienced, and enjoyed by spirits.

The truth of cognition consists in the fact that it opens up the meaning

and destination of the world. That which ought to be is the ground of that

which is; that which is exists in order to the realization of values in

it; the good is the only real. It is true that we are not permitted to

penetrate farther than to the general conviction that the Idea of the good

is the ground and end of the world; the question, how the world has arisen

from this supreme Idea as from the absolute and why just this world with

its determinate forms and laws has arisen, is unanswerable. We understand

the meaning of the play, but we do not see the machinery by which it is

produced at work behind the stage. In ethics Lotze emphasizes with Fechner

the inseparability of the good and plea