History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

modern period, wears the badge of physics. The world is conceived from the

standpoint of nature, psychical phenomena are in part neglected, in part

see their inconvenient claims reduced to a minimum, while it is but rarely

that we find an appreciation of their independence and co-ordinate value,

not to speak of their superior position. The power which natural science

has gained over philosophy dates essentially from a series of famous

discoveries and theories, by which science has opened up entirely new and

wide outlooks, and whose title to be considered in the formation of a

general view of reality is incontestable. To mention only the most

prominent, the following have all posited important and far-reaching

problems for philosophy as well as for science: Johannes Müller's (Müller

died 1858) theory of the specific energies of the senses, which Helmholtz

made use of as an empirical confirmation of the Kantian apriorism; the law

of the conservation of energy discovered by Robert Mayer (1842, 1850;

Helmholtz, 1847, 1862), and, in particular, the law of the transformation

of heat into motion, which invited an examination of all the forces active

in the world to test their mutual convertibility; the extension of

mechanism to the vital processes, favored even by Lotze; the renewed

conflict between atomism and dynamism; further, the Darwinian theory[1]

(1859), which makes organic species develop from one another by natural

selection in the struggle for existence (through inheritance and

adaptation); finally, the meta-geometrical speculations[2] of Gauss (1828),

Riemann (_On the Hypotheses which lie at the Basis of Geometry_, 1854,

published in 1867), Helmholtz (1868), B. Erdmann (_The Axioms of Geometry_,

1877). G. Cantor, and others, which look on our Euclidean space of three

dimensions as a special case of the unintuitable yet thinkable analytic

concept of a space of _n_ dimensions. The circumstance that these theories

are still largely hypothetical in their own field appears to have stirred

up rather than moderated the zeal for carrying them over into other

departments and for applying them to the world as a whole. Thus,

especially, the Darwinians[3] have undauntedly attempted to utilize the

biological hypothesis of the master as a philosophical principle of the

world, and to bring the mental sciences under the point of view of the

mechanical theory of development, though thus far with more daring and

noise than success. The finely conceived ethics of Höffding (p. 585) is an

exception to the rule which is the object of this remark.

[Footnote 1: A critical exposition of the modern doctrine of development

and of the causes used to explain it is given by Otto Hamann,

_Entwickelungslehre und Darwinismus_, Jena, 1892. Cf.

also, O. Liebmann,

_Analysis der Wirklichkeit_; and Ed. von Hartmann (above, p. 610). [Among

the numerous works in English the reader may be referred to the article

"Evolution," by Huxley and Sully, _Encyclopedia Britannica_, 9th ed., vol.

viii.; Wallace's _Darwinism_, 1889; Romanes, _Darwin and after Darwin_,

i. _The Darwinian Theory_, 1892; and Conn's _Evolution of To-day_,

1886.--TR.]]

[Footnote 2: Cf. Liebmann, _Analysis der Wirklichkeit_, 2d ed., pp. 53-59.

G. Frege (_Begriffsschrift_, 1879; _The Foundations of Arithmetic_, 1884;

_Function and Concept_, 1891; "On Sense and Meaning" in the _Zeitschrift

für Philosophie,_ vol. c. 1892) has also chosen the region intermediate

between mathematics and philosophy for his field of work. We note, further,

E.G. Husserl, _Philosophy of Arithmetic_, vol. i., 1891.]

[Footnote 3: Ernst Haeckel of Jena (born 1834; _General Morphology_, 1866;

_Natural History of Creation_, 1868 [English, 1875] I _Anthropogeny_, 1874;

_Aims and Methods of the Development History of To-day_, 1875; _Popular

Lectures_, 1878 _seq_.--English, 1883), G. Jäger, A.

Schleicher _(The

Darwinian Theory and the Science of Language_, 1865), Ernst Krause

(Carus Sterne, the editor of _Kosmos_) O. Caspari, Carneri (_Morals and

Darwinism_, 1871), O. Schmidt, Du Prel, Paul Rée (_The Origin of the Moral

Feelings_, 1877; _The Genesis of Conscience_, 1885; _The Illusion of Free

Will_, 1885); G.H. Schneider (_The Animal Will_, 1880; _The Human Will_,

1882; _The Good and III of the Human Race_, 1883).]

Besides the theory of knowledge, in the elaboration of which the most

eminent naturalists[1] participate with acuteness and success, psychology

and the practical disciplines also betray the influence of the scientific

spirit. While sociology and ethics, following the English model, seek an

empirical basis and begin to make philosophical use of statistical results

(E.F. Schäffle, _Frame and Life of the Social Body_, new ed., 1885; A. von

Oettingen, _Moral Statistic in its Significance for a Social Ethics_, 3d

ed., 1882), psychology endeavors to attain exact results in regard to

psychical life and its relation to its physical basis--

besides Fechner and

the Herbartians, W. Wundt and A. Horwicz should be mentioned here. Wundt

and, of late, Haeckel go back to the Spinozistic parallelism of material

and psychical existence, only that the latter emphasizes merely the

inseparability _(Nichtohneeinander)_ of the two sides (the cell-body and

the cell-soul) with a real difference between them and a metaphysical

preponderance of the material side, while the former emphasizes the

essential unity of body and soul, and the higher reality of the spiritual

side.

[Footnote 1: Helmholtz, Virchow (born 1821), Zöllner (1834-82; _On the

Nature of Comets_, 1872), and Du Bois-Reymond (born 1818), who, in his

lectures _On the Limits of the Knowledge of Nature_, 1872, and _The Seven

World-riddles_, 1880 (both together in 1882, and reprinted in the first

series of his _Addresses_, 1886), looks on the origin of life, the

purposive order of nature, and thought as problems soluble in the future,

but declares, on the other hand, that the nature of matter (atoms)

and force _(actio in distant)_, the origin of motion, the genesis of

consciousness (of sensation, together with pleasure and pain) from the

knowable conditions of psychical life, and the freedom of the will, are

absolute limits to our knowledge of nature.]

%(b) Idealistic Reaction against the Scientific Spirit.%--In opposition to

the preponderance of natural science and the empirico-skeptical tendency of

the philosophy of the day conditioned by it, an idealistic counter-movement

is making itself increasingly felt as the years go on.

Wilhelm Dilthey[1]

abandons metaphysics as a basis, it is true, but (with the assent of

Gierke, _Preussische Jahrbücher_, vol. liii. 1884) declares against the

transfer of the method of natural science to the mental sciences, which

require a special foundation. In spite of his critical rejection of

metaphysics, Wilhelm Windelband in Strasburg (born 1848; _Preludes_, 1884)

is, like Dilthey, to be counted among the idealists. In opposition to the

individualism of the positivists, the folk-psychologists--at their head

Steinthal and Lazarus (p. 536); Gustav Glogau[2] in Kiel (born 1844) is

an adherent of the same movement--defend the power of the universal over

individual spirits. The spirit of the people is not a phrase, an empty

name, but a real force, not the sum of the individuals belonging to the

people, but an encompassing and controlling power, which brings forth

in the whole body processes (_e.g._, language) which could not occur in

individuals as such. It is only as a member of society that anyone becomes

truly man; the community is the subject of the higher life of spirit.

[Footnote 1: Dilthey: _Introduction to the Mental Sciences_, part i.,

1883; _Poetic Creation_ in the Zeller _Aufsätze_, 1887;

"Contributions to

the Solution of the Question of the Origin of our Belief in the Reality of

the External World, and its Validity,"

_Sitzungsberichte_ of the Berlin

Academy of Sciences, 1890; "Conception and Analysis of Man in the

Fifteenth and Sixteenth Centuries" in the _Archiv für Geschichte der

Philosophie_, vols. iv., v., 1891-92.]

[Footnote 2: Glogau: _Sketch of the Fundamental Philosophical Sciences_

(part i., _The Form and the Laws of Motion of the Spirit_, 1880; part

ii., _The Nature and the Fundamental Forms of Conscious Spirit_, 1888);

_Outlines of Psychology_; 1884.]

If folk-psychology, whose title but imperfectly expresses the comprehensive

endeavor to construct a psychology of society or of the universal spirit,

is, as it were, an empirical confirmation of Hegel's theory of Objective

Spirit, Rudolf Eucken[1] (born 1846), pressing on in the Fichtean manner

from the secondary facts of consciousness to an original real-life,

endeavors to solve the question of a universal becoming, of an

all-pervasive force, of a supporting unity ("totality") in the life of

spirit (neither in a purely noëtical nor a purely metaphysical, but) in a

noölogical way, and demands that the fundamental science or doctrine of

principles direct its attention not to cognition by itself, but to the

activity of psychical life as a whole.

[Footnote 1: Eucken: _The Unity of Spiritual Life in the Consciousness and

Deeds of Humanity_, 1888; _Prolegomena_ to this, 1885. A detailed analysis

of the latter by Falckenberg is given in the _Zeitschrift für Philosophie_,

vol. xc, 1887; cf. above, pp. 17 and 610.]

We have elsewhere discussed the more recent attempts to establish a

metaphysic which shall be empirically well grounded and shall cautiously

rise from facts.[1] In regard to the possibility of metaphysics three

parties are to be distinguished: On the left, the positivists, the

neo-Kantians, and the monists of consciousness, who deny it out of hand. On

the right, a series of philosophers--e.g., adherents of Hegel, Herbart, and

Schopenhauer--who, without making any concessions to the modern theory of

knowledge, hold fast to the possibility of a speculative metaphysics of the

old type. In the center, a group of thinkers who are willing to renounce

neither a solid noëtical foundation nor the attainment of metaphysical

conclusions--so Eduard von Hartmann, Wundt,[2] Eucken, Volkelt (pp. 590,

617). Otto Liebmann (born 1840; _On the Analysis of Reality_, 1876, 2d

ed., 1880; _Thoughts and Facts_, Heft i. 1882) demands a sharp separation

between the certain and the uncertain and an exact estimation of the degree

of probability which theories possess; puts the principles of metaphysics

under the rubric of logical hypothesis; and, in his _Climax of the

Theories_, 1884, calls attention to the fact that experiential science, in

addition to axioms necessarily or apodictically certain and empeiremes

possessing actual or assertory certainty, needs, further, a number of

"interpolation maxims," which form an attribute of our type of intellectual

organization _(i.e._, principles, according to the standard of which we

supplement the fragmentary and discrete series of single perceptions and

isolated observations by the interpolation of the needed intermediate

links, so that they form a connected experience). The most important of

these maxims are the principles of real identity, of the continuity of

existence, of causality, and of the continuity of becoming. Experience is

a gift of the understanding; the premises, as a rule, latent in ordinary

consciousness, on whose anticipatory application our experience is based

throughout, assert something absolutely incapable of being experienced.

If, in order to the production of a "pure experience,"

we eliminate all

subjective additions of the understanding contained in experiential thought

(all that cannot be present at the moment or locally at hand, in short, all

that cannot be the direct object and content of actual observation),

this breaks up into an unordered, unconnected aggregate of discontinuous

perceptual fragments; in order that a complete and articulated condition

of experience may result, these fragments (the purely factual content of

observation, the incoherent matter of perception) must be supplemented and

connected by very much that is not observed.

[Footnote 1: R. Falckenberg, _Ueber die gegenwärtige Lage der deutschen

Philosophie_, inaugural address at Erlangen, Leipsic, 1890.]

[Footnote 2: Wundt: _Essays_, 1885, including

"Philosophy and Science";

_System of Philosophy_, 1889. On the latter cf.

Volkelt's paper in the

_Philosophische Monatshefte_, vol. xxvii. 1891; and on the _Essays_ a

notice by the same author in the same review, vol.

xxiii. 1887.]

Further, a reaction against crude naturalism is observable in the practical

field, though political economists (Roscher) and jurists take a more active

part in it than the philosophers. Personally R. von Jhering (1818-92;

_Purpose in Law_, 2 vols., 1877-83, 2d ed., 1884-86) stands on idealistic

ground, although, rejecting the nativistic and formalistic theory, he is in

principle an adherent of "realism," of the principle of interest and social

utility (the moral is that Which is permanently useful to society).

Finally, similar motives underlie the growing interest in the history

of philosophy. The idealistic impulse seeks the nourishment which the

un-metaphysical present denies to it from the great works of the past, and

hopes, by keeping alive the classical achievements of previous times, to

enhance the consciousness of the urgency and irrepressibleness of the

highest questions, and to awaken courage for renewed attempts at their

solution. Thus the study of history enters the service of systematic

philosophy.

%(c) The Special Philosophical Sciences.%--The more the courage to attack

the central problems of philosophy has been paralyzed by the neo-Kantian

theory of knowledge and the coming-in of the positivistic spirit, the more

lively has been the work of the last decades in the special departments:

the transfer of the center of gravity from metaphysics to the particular

sciences is the most prominent characteristic of the philosophy of the

time. Logic sees century-old convictions shattered and new foundations

arising. Psychology has entered into competition with physiology in regard

to the discovery of the laws of the psychical functions which depend

on bodily processes, while metaphysical questions are forced into the

background and there is a growing distrust of the reliability of inner

observation. The philosophy of religion is favored with undiminished

interest and aesthetics, after long neglect, with a renewal of attention;

the philosophy of history is about to reconquer its former rights.

There is, moreover, an especially lively interest in ethics; and the

investigation of the history of philosophy is more widely extended than

ever before. We will close our sketch with a short survey of the particular

disciplines.

In the department of _logic_ the following should be mentioned as classical

achievements: the works of Christoph Sigwart of Tübingen (vol. i. 1873,

2d ed., 1889; vol. ii. 1878), of Lotze (p. 605), and of Wundt (vol. i.

_Erkenntnisslehre_, 1880; vol. ii. _Methodenlehre_, 1883). Besides these,

Bergmann (p. 620), Schuppe (p. 619), and Benno Erdmann (_Logik_, vol. i.

1892) deserve notice.

In _psychology_ the following writers have made themselves prominent:

Wilhelm Wundt at Leipsic (born 1832), _Grundzüge der physiologischen

Psychologie_, 1874, 3d ed., 1887; A. Horwicz, _Psychologische Analysen auf

physiologischer Grundlage_, 1872 _seq_.; Franz Brentano in Vienna (born

1838), _Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkte_, vol.

i. 1874; Carl

Stumpf of Munich (born 1848), _Ueber den psychologischen Ursprung der

Raumvorstellung_, 1873, _Tonpsychologie_, vol. i. 1883, vol. ii. 1890;

Theodor Lipps of Breslau (born 1851), _Grundthatsachen des Seelenlebens_,

1883. The following may be mentioned in the same connection: J.H. Witte,

_Das Wesen der Seele_, 1888; H. Münsterberg, _Die Willenshandlung_, 1888,

_Beiträge zur experimentellen Psychologie_, 1889 _seq_,; Goswin K. Uphues

at Halle, _Wahrnehmung und Empfindung_, 1888, _Ueber die Erinnerung_, 1889;

H. Schmidkunz, _Psychologie der Suggestion_, 1892; H.

Ebbinghaus, the

co-editor of the _Zeitschrift für Psychologie una Physiologie der

Sinnesorgane_, 1890 _seq_.; H. Spitta; Max Dessoir, _Der Hautsinn_, in

the _Archiv für Anatomie una Physiologie_, 1892. The following works are

psychological contributions to the theory of knowledge: E.L. Fischer,

_Theorie der Gesichtswahrnehmung_, 1891; Hermann Schwarz, _Das

Wahrnehmungsproblem_, 1892. Finally we may add A. Dorner in Königsberg,

_Das menschliche Erkennen_, 1887; and E.L. Fischer, _Die Grundfragen der

Erkenntnisstheorie_, 1887.

The literature of _moral philosophy_ has been substantially enriched by

Wundt, _Ethik_, 1886, 2d ed., 1892; and Friedrich Paulsen, _System der

Ethik_, 1889, 2d ed., 1891. We may mention, further, Baumann (p. 601);

Schuppe, _Grundzüge der Ethik und Rechtsphilosophie_, 1882; Witte,

_Freiheit des Willens_, 1882; G. Class in Erlangen, _Ideale und Güter_,

1886; Richard Wallaschek, _Ideen zur praktischen Philosophic_, 1886;

F. Tönnies in Kiel, _Gemeinschaft und Gesellschaft_, 1887; A. Döring,

_Philosophische Güterlehre_, 1888; Th. Ziegler, _Sittliches Sein und

Werden_, 2d ed., 1890; G. Simmel, _Einleitung in die Moralwissenschaft_,

vol. i. 1892.

Of the newer works in the field of _aesthetics_, in addition to A.

Zeising's _Aesthetische Forschungen_, 1855, C. Hermann's _Aesthetik_,

1875, and Hartmann's _Philosophie des Schönen_, 1887, we may mention the

_Einleitung in die Aesthetik_ of Karl Groos, 1892, and the following by

Lipps: _Der Streit über die Tragödie_, 1890; _Aesthetische Faktoren der

Raumanschauung_, 1891; the essay _Psychologie der Komik (Philosophische

Monatshefte_, vols. xxiv.-xxv. 1888-89), and _Aesthetische

Litteraturberichte_, (in the same review, vol. xxvi.

1890 _seq_.).

Among the writers and works on the _philosophy of history_ we may note

Conrad Hermann in Leipsic (born 1819), _Philosophie der Geschichte_, 1870;

Bernheim, _Geschichtsforschung und

Geschichtsphilosophie_, 1880; Karl

Fischer, _Ist eine Philosophie der Geschichte wissenschaftlich erforderlich

bezw. möglich?_ Dillenburg Programme, 1889; Hinneberg, _Die philosophischen

Grundlagen der Geschichtswissenschaft_ in Sybel's _Historische

Zeitschrift_, vol. lxiii. 1889; A. Dippe, _Das Geschichtsstudium mit

seinen Zielen und Fragen_, 1891; Georg Simmel, _Die Probleme der

Geschichtsphilosophie_, 1892.

In the _philosophy of religion_, which is discussed especially by the

theologians, a neo-Kantian and a neo-Hegelian tendency confront each other.

The former, dividing in its turn, is represented, on the one hand, by

the Ritschlian school--W. Herrmann in Marburg (_Die Metaphysik in der

Theologie_, 1876, _Die Religion im Verhältniss zum Welterkennen und zur

Sittlichkeit_, 1889), J. Kaftan in Berlin (_Das Wesen der christlichen

Religion_, 1881)--and, on the other, by R.A. Lipsius in Jena (born 1830;

_Dogmatik_, 1876, 2d ed., 1879; _Philosophie und Religion_, 1885). The

latter is represented by A.E. Biedermann of Zurich (1819-85; _Christliche

Dogmatik_, 1868; 2d ed., 1884-85), a pupil of W. Vatke, and by Otto

Pfleiderer of Berlin (born 1839; _Religionsphilosophie_, 1879; 2d ed.,

1883-4). The neo-Kantians base religion exclusively on the practical side

of human nature, especially on the moral law, derive it from the contrast

between external dependence on nature and the inner freedom or supernatural

destination of the spirit, and wish it preserved from all intermixture

with metaphysics. According to the neo-Hegelians, on the contrary, the

theoretical element in religion is no less essential; and is capable of

being purified, of being elevated from the form of representation, which is

full of contradictions, into the adequate form of pure thought, capable,

therefore, of reconciliation with philosophy. Hugo Delff (_Ueber den Weg

zum Wissen und zur Gewissheit zu gelangen_, 1882; _Die Hauptprobleme der

Philosophie und Religion_, 1886) follows Jacobi's course.

Among the numerous works on the _history of philosophy_, besides the

masterpieces of Zeller, J.E. Erdmann, and Kuno Fischer, the following are

especially worthy of attention:

Cl. Bäumker in Breslau, _Das Problem der Materie in der griechischen

Philosophie_, 1890; H. Bonitz, _Platonische Studien_, 3d ed., 1886,

_Aristotelische Studien_, 1862 _seq., Index Aristotelicus_, 1870, _Kleine

Schriften_; P. Deussen (born 1845), _Das System der Vedanta_, 1883, H.

Diels in Berlin, _Doxographi Graeci_, 1879; Eucken in Jena (p. 17), _Die

Methode der aristotelischen Forschung_, 1872, Address _Ueber den Werth der

Geschichte der Philosophie_, 1874; J. Freudenthal in Breslau (born 1839,

pp. 63, 118), _Hellenistische Studien, 3 Hefte_, 1879, _Ueber die Theologie

des Xenophanes_, 1886; M. Heinze in Leipsic, _Die Lehre vom Logos in der

griechischen Philosophie_, 1872; G. Freiherr von Hertling in Munich (born

1843), _Materie und Form und die Definition der Seele bei Aristoteles_,

1871, _Albertus Magnus_, 1880; H. Heussler in Basle (p.

65 note),

_Der Rationalismus des XVII. Jahrhunderts in seinen Beziehungen zur

Eniwickelungslehre_, 1885; Fr. Jodl in Prague (born 1849; pp. 16, 221

note); A. Krohn (1840-89), _Sokrates und Xenophon_, 1874, _Der platonische

Staat_, 1876, _Die platonische Frage_, 1878--on Krohn, an obituary by

Falckenberg in the _Biographisches Jahrbuch für Alterthumskunde, Jahrg_.

12, 1889; P. Natorp (pp. 88 note, 598), _Forschungen zur Geschichte des

Erkenntnissproblems im Alterthum_, 1884; Edmund Pfleiderer in Tübingen

(born 1842; p. 113 note[1]), _Empirismus und Skepsis im D. Humes

Philosophie_, 1874, _Die Philosophie des Heraklit im Lichte der

Mysterienidee_, 1886; K. von Prantl (1820-88), _Geschichte der Logik im

Abendlande_, 4 vols., 1855-70; Carl Schaarschmidt (pp.

88 note, 117-118);

_Johannes Sarisberiensis_, 1862, _Die Sammlung der platonischen Schriften_,

1866; L. Schmidt in Marburg (born 1824), _Die Ethik der alten Griechen_,

1881; Gustav Schneider, _Die platonische Metaphysik_, 1884; H. Siebeck in

Giessen, _Untersuchungen zur Philosophie der Griechen_, 1873, 2d ed., 1888,

_Geschichte der Psychologie_, part i. 1880-84; Chr. von Sigwart (born 1830;

pp. 17, 118); Heinrich von Stein in Rostock (born 1833), _Sieben Bücher zur

Geschichte des Platonismus_, 1862-75; Ludwig Stein in Berne, editor of the

_Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie_, founded in 1877, _Die Psychologie

der Stoa_, I. _Metaphysisch-Anthropologischer Theil_, 1886, II.

_Erkenntnisstheorie_, 1888, _Leibniz und Spinoza_, 1890; L. Strümpell,

_Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie_, 1854, 1861; Susemihl in

Greifswald, _Die Politik des Aristoteles_, Greek and German with notes,

1879, further, a series of essays on Plato and Aristotle; Teichmüller (p.

601); Trendelenburg (pp. 600-601), _Aristotelis de Anima_, 2d ed., by

Belger. 1887; Th. Waitz, _Aristotelis Organon_, 1844-46; J. Walter in

Königsberg, _Die Lehre von der praktischen Vernunft in der griechischen

Philosophie_, 1874, _Geschichte der Aesthetik im Alterthum_, 1892; Tob.

Wildauer in Innsbruck, _Die Psychologie des Willens bei Sokrates, Platon,

und Aristoteles_, 1877, 1879; W. Windelbund in Strasburg (pp. 15-16),

_Geschichte der alten Philosophie_, 1888; Theob. Ziegler in Strasburg,