Reading for Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction to Philosophical Thinking by Lee Archie and John G. Archie - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

drank what he earned, he lived like a brute, and finished by killing and rob-

bing an old man. He was caught, tried, and condemned to death. They are

not sentimentalists there. And in prison he was immediately surrounded

by pastors, members of Christian brotherhoods, philanthropic ladies, and

the like. They taught him to read and write in prison, and expounded the

Gospel to him. They exhorted him, worked upon him, drummed at him

incessantly, till at last he solemnly confessed his crime. He was converted.

He wrote to the court himself that he was a monster, but that in the end God

had vouchsafed him light and shown grace. All Geneva was in excitement

about him—all philanthropic and religious Geneva. All the aristocratic and

well-bred society of the town rushed to the prison, kissed Richard and em-

braced him; ‘You are our brother, you have found grace.’ And Richard

does nothing but weep with emotion, ‘Yes, I’ve found grace! All my youth

and childhood I was glad of pigs’ food, but now even I have found grace. I

am dying in the Lord.’ ‘Yes, Richard, die in the Lord; you have shed blood

and must die. Though it’s not your fault that you knew not the Lord, when

you coveted the pigs’ food and were beaten for stealing it (which was very

wrong of you, for stealing is forbidden); but you’ve shed blood and you

must die.’ And on the last day, Richard, perfectly limp, did nothing but

cry and repeat every minute: ‘This is my happiest day. I am going to the

Lord.’ ‘Yes,’ cry the pastors and the judges and philanthropic ladies. ‘This

is the happiest day of your life, for you are going to the Lord!’ They all

walk or drive to the scaffold in procession behind the prison van. At the

scaffold they call to Richard: ‘Die, brother, die in the Lord, for even thou

hast found grace!’ And so, covered with his brothers’ kisses, Richard is

dragged on to the scaffold, and led to the guillotine. And they chopped

off his head in brotherly fashion, because he had found grace. Yes, that’s

characteristic.”

“That pamphlet is translated into Russian by some Russian philanthropists

of aristocratic rank and evangelical aspirations, and has been distributed

gratis for the enlightenment of the people. The case of Richard is interest-

ing because it’s national. Though to us it’s absurd to cut off a man’s head,

because he has become our brother and has found grace, yet we have our

own specialty, which is all but worse. Our historical pastime is the direct

satisfaction of inflicting pain. There are lines in Nekrassov describing how

a peasant lashes a horse on the eyes, ‘on its meek eyes,’ everyone must

182

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 17. “The Problem of Evil ” by Fyodor Dostoevsky

have seen it. It’s peculiarly Russian. He describes how a feeble little nag

has foundered under too heavy a load and cannot move. The peasant beats

it, beats it savagely, beats it at last not knowing what he is doing in the

intoxication of cruelty, thrashes it mercilessly over and over again. ‘How-

ever weak you are, you must pull, if you die for it.’ The nag strains, and

then he begins lashing the poor defenceless creature on its weeping, on its

‘meek eyes.’ The frantic beast tugs and draws the load, trembling all over,

gasping for breath, moving sideways, with a sort of unnatural spasmodic

action—it’s awful in Nekrassov. But that only a horse, and God has horses

to be beaten. So the Tatars have taught us, and they left us the knout as

a remembrance of it. But men, too, can be beaten. A well-educated, cul-

tured gentleman and his wife beat their own child with a birch-rod, a girl

of seven. I have an exact account of it. The papa was glad that the birch

was covered with twigs. ‘It stings more,’ said he, and so be began sting-

ing his daughter. I know for a fact there are people who at every blow

are worked up to sensuality, to literal sensuality, which increases progres-

sively at every blow they inflict. They beat for a minute, for five minutes,

for ten minutes, more often and more savagely. The child screams. At last

the child cannot scream, it gasps, ‘Daddy daddy!’ By some diabolical un-

seemly chance the case was brought into court. A counsel is engaged. The

Russian people have long called a barrister ‘a conscience for hire.’ The

counsel protests in his client’s defence. ‘It’s such a simple thing,’ he says,

‘an everyday domestic event. A father corrects his child. To our shame

be it said, it is brought into court.’ The jury, convinced by him, give a

favourable verdict. The public roars with delight that the torturer is acquit-

ted. Ah, pity I wasn’t there! I would have proposed to raise a subscription

in his honour! Charming pictures. But I’ve still better things about chil-

dren. I’ve collected a great, great deal about Russian children, Alyosha.

There was a little girl of five who was hated by her father and mother,

‘most worthy and respectable people, of good education and breeding.’

You see, I must repeat again, it is a peculiar characteristic of many people,

this love of torturing children, and children only. To all other types of hu-

manity these torturers behave mildly and benevolently, like cultivated and

humane Europeans; but they are very fond of tormenting children, even

fond of children themselves in that sense. it’s just their defencelessness

that tempts the tormentor, just the angelic confidence of the child who has

no refuge and no appeal, that sets his vile blood on fire. In every man, of

course, a demon lies hidden—the demon of rage, the demon of lustful heat

at the screams of the tortured victim, the demon of lawlessness let off the

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

183

index-202_1.jpg

Chapter 17. “The Problem of Evil ” by Fyodor Dostoevsky

chain, the demon of diseases that follow on vice, gout, kidney disease, and

so on.”

Four Children in Hayfield, Russia, Library of Congress

“This poor child of five was subjected to every possible torture by those

cultivated parents. They beat her, thrashed her, kicked her for no reason till

her body was one bruise. Then, they went to greater refinements of cru-

elty—shut her up all night in the cold and frost in a privy, and because she

didn’t ask to be taken up at night (as though a child of five sleeping its an-

gelic, sound sleep could be trained to wake and ask), they smeared her face

and filled her mouth with excrement, and it was her mother, her mother did

this. And that mother could sleep, hearing the poor child’s groans! Can you

understand why a little creature, who can’t even understand what’s done

to her, should beat her little aching heart with her tiny fist in the dark and

the cold, and weep her meek unresentful tears to dear, kind God to protect

her? Do you understand that, friend and brother, you pious and humble

novice? Do you understand why this infamy must be and is permitted?

Without it, I am told, man could not have existed on earth, for he could

not have known good and evil. Why should he know that diabolical good

184

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 17. “The Problem of Evil ” by Fyodor Dostoevsky

and evil when it costs so much? Why, the whole world of knowledge is not

worth that child’s prayer to dear, kind God! I say nothing of the sufferings

of grown-up people, they have eaten the apple, damn them, and the devil

take them all! But these little ones! I am making you suffer, Alyosha, you

are not yourself. I’ll leave off if you like.”

“Nevermind. I want to suffer too,” muttered Alyosha.

[The Death of an Innocent Child]

“One picture, only one more, because it’s so curious, so characteristic,

and I have only just read it in some collection of Russian antiquities. I’ve

forgotten the name. I must look it up. It was in the darkest days of serf-

dom at the beginning of the century, and long live the Liberator of the

People! There was in those days a general of aristocratic connections, the

owner of great estates, one of those men—somewhat exceptional, I be-

lieve, even then—who, retiring from the service into a life of leisure, are

convinced that they’ve earned absolute power over the lives of their sub-

jects. There were such men then. So our general, settled on his property

of two thousand souls, lives in pomp, and domineers over his poor neigh-

bours as though they were dependents and buffoons. He has kennels of

hundreds of hounds and nearly a hundred dog-boys—all mounted, and in

uniform. One day a serf-boy, a little child of eight, threw a stone in play

and hurt the paw of the general’s favourite hound. ‘Why is my favourite

dog lame?’ He is told that the boy threw a stone that hurt the dog’s paw. ‘So

you did it.’ The general looked the child up and down. ‘Take him.’ He was

taken—taken from his mother and kept shut up all night. Early that morn-

ing the general comes out on horseback, with the hounds, his dependents,

dog-boys, and huntsmen, all mounted around him in full hunting parade.

The servants are summoned for their edification, and in front of them all

stands the mother of the child. The child is brought from the lock-up. It’s

a gloomy, cold, foggy, autumn day, a capital day for hunting. The general

orders the child to be undressed; the child is stripped naked. He shivers,

numb with terror, not daring to cry. . . ‘Make him run,’ commands the gen-

eral. ‘Run! run!’ shout the dog-boys. The boy runs. . . ‘At him!’ yells the

general, and he sets the whole pack of hounds on the child. The hounds

catch him, and tear him to pieces before his mother’s eyes!. . . I believe the

general was afterwards declared incapable of administering his estates.

Well—what did he deserve? To be shot? To be shot for the satisfaction of

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

185

Chapter 17. “The Problem of Evil ” by Fyodor Dostoevsky

our moral feelings? Speak, Alyosha!”

“To be shot,” murmured Alyosha, lifting his eyes to Ivan with a pale,

twisted smile.

“Bravo!” cried Ivan delighted. “If even you say so. . . You’re a pretty

monk! So there is a little devil sitting in your heart, Alyosha Karamazov!”

“What I said was absurd, but. . . ”

“That’s just the point, that ‘but’!” cried Ivan. “Let me tell you, novice, that

the absurd is only too necessary on earth. The world stands on absurdities,

and perhaps nothing would have come to pass in it without them. We know

what we know!”

“What do you know?”

“I understand nothing,” Ivan went on, as though in delirium. “I don’t want

to understand anything now. I want to stick to the fact. I made up my mind

long ago not to understand. If I try to understand anything, I shall be false

to the fact, and I have determined to stick to the fact.”

“Why are you trying me?” Alyosha cried, with sudden distress. “Will you

say what you mean at last?”

From the reading. . .

“And so I hasten to give back my entrance ticket, and if I am an honest

man I am bound to give it back as soon as possible.”

“Of course, I will; that’s what I’ve been leading up to. You are dear to me,

I don’t want to let you go, and I won’t give you up to your Zossima.”

Ivan for a minute was silent, his face became all at once very sad.

[The Problem of Evil]

“Listen! I took the case of children only to make my case clearer. Of the

other tears of humanity with which the earth is soaked from its crust to

its centre, I will say nothing. I have narrowed my subject on purpose. I

am a bug, and I recognise in all humility that I cannot understand why the

186

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 17. “The Problem of Evil ” by Fyodor Dostoevsky

world is arranged as it is. Men are themselves to blame, I suppose; they

were given paradise, they wanted freedom, and stole fire from heaven,

though they knew they would become unhappy, so there is no need to pity

them. With my pitiful, earthly, Euclidian understanding, all I know is that

there is suffering and that there are none guilty; that cause follows effect,

simply and directly; that everything flows and finds its level—but that’s

only Euclidian nonsense, I know that, and I can’t consent to live by it!

What comfort is it to me that there are none guilty and that cause follows

effect simply and directly, and that I know it?—I must have justice, or

I will destroy myself. And not justice in some remote infinite time and

space, but here on earth, and that I could see myself. I have believed in

it. I want to see it, and if I am dead by then, let me rise again, for if it all

happens without me, it will be too unfair. Surely I haven’t suffered simply

that I, my crimes and my sufferings, may manure the soil of the future

harmony for somebody else. I want to see with my own eyes the hind lie

down with the lion and the victim rise up and embrace his murderer. I

want to be there when everyone suddenly understands what it has all been

for. All the religions of the world are built on this longing, and I am a

believer. But then there are the children, and what am I to do about them?

That’s a question I can’t answer. For the hundredth time I repeat, there are

numbers of questions, but I’ve only taken the children, because in their

case what I mean is so unanswerably clear. Listen! If all must suffer to

pay for the eternal harmony, what have children to do with it, tell me,

please? It’s beyond all comprehension why they should suffer, and why

they should pay for the harmony. Why should they, too, furnish material

to enrich the soil for the harmony of the future? I understand solidarity in

sin among men. I understand solidarity in retribution, too; but there can be

no such solidarity with children. And if it is really true that they must share

responsibility for all their fathers’ crimes, such a truth is not of this world

and is beyond my comprehension. Some jester will say, perhaps, that the

child would have grown up and have sinned, but you see he didn’t grow

up, he was torn to pieces by the dogs, at eight years old. Oh, Alyosha,

I am not blaspheming! I understand, of course, what an upheaval of the

universe it will be when everything in heaven and earth blends in one

hymn of praise and everything that lives and has lived cries aloud: ‘Thou

art just, O Lord, for Thy ways are revealed.’ When the mother embraces

the fiend who threw her child to the dogs, and all three cry aloud with

tears, ‘Thou art just, O Lord!’ then, of course, the crown of knowledge

will be reached and all will be made clear. But what pulls me up here is

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

187

Chapter 17. “The Problem of Evil ” by Fyodor Dostoevsky

that I can’t accept that harmony. And while I am on earth, I make haste to

take my own measures. You see, Alyosha, perhaps it really may happen

that if I live to that moment, or rise again to see it, I, too, perhaps, may cry

aloud with the rest, looking at the mother embracing the child’s torturer,

‘Thou art just, O Lord!’ but I don’t want to cry aloud then. While there is

still time, I hasten to protect myself, and so I renounce the higher harmony

altogether. It’s not worth the tears of that one tortured child who beat itself

on the breast with its little fist and prayed in its stinking outhouse, with its

unexpiated tears to ‘dear, kind God’! It’s not worth it, because those tears

are unatoned for. They must be atoned for, or there can be no harmony.

But how? How are you going to atone for them? Is it possible? By their

being avenged? But what do I care for avenging them? What do I care for

a hell for oppressors? What good can hell do, since those children have

already been tortured? And what becomes of harmony, if there is hell?

I want to forgive. I want to embrace. I don’t want more suffering. And

if the sufferings of children go to swell the sum of sufferings which was

necessary to pay for truth, then I protest that the truth is not worth such a

price. I don’t want the mother to embrace the oppressor who threw her son

to the dogs! She dare not forgive him! Let her forgive him for herself, if

she will, let her forgive the torturer for the immeasurable suffering of her

mother’s heart. But the sufferings of her tortured child she has no right to

forgive; she dare not forgive the torturer, even if the child were to forgive

him! And if that is so, if they dare not forgive, what becomes of harmony?

Is there in the whole world a being who would have the right to forgive

and could forgive? I don’t want harmony. From love for humanity I don’t

want it. I would rather be left with the unavenged suffering. I would rather

remain with my unavenged suffering and unsatisfied indignation, even if

I were wrong. Besides, too high a price is asked for harmony; it’s beyond

our means to pay so much to enter on it. And so I hasten to give back my

entrance ticket, and if I am an honest man I am bound to give it back as

soon as possible. And that I am doing. It’s not God that I don’t accept,

Alyosha, only I most respectfully return him the ticket.”

“That’s rebellion,” murmured Alyosha, looking down.

From the reading. . .

“I don’t want harmony. From love of humanity I don’t want it.”

188

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

index-207_1.jpg

Chapter 17. “The Problem of Evil ” by Fyodor Dostoevsky

“Rebellion? I am sorry you call it that,” said Ivan earnestly. “One can

hardly live in rebellion, and I want to live. Tell me yourself, I challenge

your answer. Imagine that you are creating a fabric of human destiny with

the object of making men happy in the end, giving them peace and rest

at last, but that it was essential and inevitable to torture to death only one

tiny creature—that baby beating its breast with its fist, for instance—and

to found that edifice on its unavenged tears, would you consent to be the

architect on those conditions? Tell me, and tell the truth.”

“No, I wouldn’t consent,” said Alyosha softly.

Kasan Cathedral, St. Petersburg, Library of Congress

Related Ideas

TPM Online (http://www.philosophers.co.uk/portal_article.php?id=33).

Free to Do Evil: An Interview with Richard Swinbirne . Philosopher and

theologian Richard Swinburne explains his theodicy, i.e. , his attempt to

reconcile God’s goodness with the presence of evil in the world.

Dostoevsky Research Station (http://www.kiosek.com/dostoevsky/) . If

you wish to track down anything about Dostoevsky, this site constructed

by Christiaan Stange is a good place to begin.

Dostoevsky as Philosopher, Lecture Notes, Philosophy 151 (http://www-

philosophy.ucdavis.edu/phi151/NOV28LEC.HTM). A guest lecture at the

University of California—Davis by Jay Gallagher.

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

189

Chapter 17. “The Problem of Evil ” by Fyodor Dostoevsky

Dostoevsky

on

Freedom,

Lecture

Notes,

Philosophy

151

(http://www-philosophy.ucdavis.edu/phi151/nov30lec.htm). Lecture at

the University of California on the problem of evil.

Topics Worth Investigating

1. The problem of evil is often put in this form of a dilemma:

If God is perfectly good, then God would seek to abolish all evil.

If God is all-powerful, then God could abolish all evil

Yet, evil exists.

Therefore, either God is not perfectly good or God is not all powerful or both.

From a logical point of view, what kind is dilemma is the problem

of evil? It does not appear to be either a constructive or a destructive

dilemma.

2. Many medieval thinkers thought of evil as a privation or the absence

of good. Since a privation or absence has no cause, God is not causally

implicated in the existence of evil. Discuss the adequacy of this argu-

ment.

3. Joseph de Maistre states, “If there were no moral evil upon earth, there

would be no physical evil.”2 What must we assume for this conditional

statement to be true?

4. In the Apology, Socrates states, “No evil can happen to a good man,

either in life or after death.” Given Ivan’s story of the death of an

innocent child, how can this be so?

2.

Joseph de Maistre. “First Dialogue” in The Works of Joseph de Maistre. Ed. by

Jack Lively. New York: Schocken Books, 1965.

190

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

index-209_1.jpg

Part III. Philosophical

Ethics

Auction’s End, Douglas Georgia, Library of Congress

Even though philosophy apparently cannot prove conclusively the exis-

tence of God, still the question of how we should lead our lives is a ques-

tion of the utmost gravity. Whether I can “live well and do well” in the af-

fairs of the world, as Aristotle suggests, or whether I have no free choices

as Spinoza thought, is intrinsically related to what it is to be human.

In this section of our introductory readings, the close relation between phi-

losophy and psychology is explored from the standpoint as to what con-

stitutes a good life. Readings from the philosophies of Baruch Spinoza,

William James, Plato, Aristotle, Jeremy Bentham, Friedrich Nietzsche,

and Jean Paul Sartre suggest a number of insights into the questions of

human existence—especially those concerning free will and determinism,

egoism and altruism, obligation and hedonism, as well as the individual’s

relation to society.

We begin Part III of the readings with a thumbnail sketch of some of the

main philosophic positions on the free will-determinism issue. The crux of

this problem is sometimes related as the dilemma known as Hume’s Fork.

This dilemma recognizes, on the one hand, if my actions are entirely sub-

ject to causal laws, then I cannot be responsible for my actions—anymore

than an apple can be responsible for falling from a tree. (Notice on this

view, an uncaused event would be the same thing as what is called “a mir-

acle”— i.e. , an event without cause or explanation.) On the other hand, if

my actions are not causally determined then my actions are uncaused and

so must be random events. In that case also I could not be responsible for

my actions because outcomes of random processes cannot be controlled

by willing or choosing. Therefore, whether or not events are caused, I can-

not be held accountable for my actions. Viewed in this manner, the heart

of the philosophical problems of ethics becomes the clarification of the

notion of choice.

Baruch Spinoza argues in the first reading that there is a complete unity of

God with nature. The soul is part of God and, consequently, is not subject

to free will. Since God is “all that there is,” the world and everything in

it is perfect. William Jam