Sextus Empiricus and Greek scepticism by Mary Mills Patrick - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

general, and the other special. The general method is that by

which we set forth the character of Scepticism, declaring what

its idea is, what its principles are, its mode of reasoning, its

criterion, and its aim. It presents also, the aspects of doubt,

[Greek: hoi tropoi tês epochês], and the way in which we should

understand the Sceptical formulae, and the distinction between

Scepticism and the related Schools of philosophy. The special

method, on the contrary, is that by which we 6 speak against 6

each part of so-called philosophy. Let us then treat Scepticism

at first in the general way, beginning our delineation with the

nomenclature of the Sceptical School.

CHAPTER III.

_The Nomenclature of Scepticism._

The Sceptical School is also called the "Seeking School," from 7

its spirit of research and examination; the "Suspending School,"

from the condition of mind in which one is left after the

search, in regard to the things that he has examined; and the

"Doubting School," either because, as some say, the Sceptics

doubt and are seeking in regard to everything, or because they

never know whether to deny or affirm. It is also called the

Pyrrhonean School, because Pyrrho appears to us the best representative of Scepticism, and is more prominent than all who

before him occupied themselves with it.

CHAPTER IV.

_What is Scepticism?_

The [Greek: dynamis] of the Sceptical School is to place the 8

phenomenal in opposition to the intellectual "in any way whatever," and thus through the equilibrium of the reasons and

things ([Greek: isostheneia tôn logôn]) opposed to each other,

to reach, first the state of suspension of judgment,

[Greek:

epochê] and afterwards that of imperturbability, [Greek: ataraxia]. We do not use the word [Greek: dynamis] in any 9

unusual sense, but simply, meaning the force of the system. By

the phenomenal, we understand the sensible, hence we place the

intellectual in opposition to it. The phrase "in any way whatever," may refer to the word [Greek: dynamis] in order that

we may understand that word in a simple sense as we said, or it

may refer to the placing the phenomenal and intellectual in

opposition. For we place these in opposition to each other in a

variety of ways, the phenomenal to the phenomenal, and the

intellectual to the intellectual, or reciprocally, and we say

"in any way whatever," in order that all methods of opposition

may be included. Or "in any way whatever" may refer to the

phenomenal and the intellectual, so that we need not ask how

does the phenomenal appear, or how are the thoughts conceived,

but that we may understand these things in a simple sense. By

"reasons opposed to each other," we do not by any means 10

understand that they deny or affirm anything, but simply that

they offset each other. By equilibrium, we mean equality in

regard to trustworthiness and untrustworthiness, so that of the

reasons that are placed in opposition to each other, one should

not excel another in trustworthiness. [Greek: epochê] is a

holding back of the opinion, in consequence of which we neither

deny nor affirm anything. [Greek: ataraxia] is repose and

tranquillity of soul. We shall explain how [Greek: ataraxia]

accompanies [Greek: epochê] when we speak of the aim.

CHAPTER V.

_The Sceptic._

What is meant by a Pyrrhonean philosopher can be understood from 11

the idea of the Sceptical School. He is a Pyrrhonean, namely,

who identifies himself with this system.

CHAPTER VI.

_The Origin of Scepticism._

Scepticism arose in the beginning from the hope of attaining 12

[Greek: ataraxia]; for men of the greatest talent were perplexed

by the contradiction of things, and being at a loss what to

believe, began to question what things are true, and what false,

hoping to attain [Greek: ataraxia] as a result of the decision.

The fundamental principle of the Sceptical system is especially

this, namely, to oppose every argument by one of equal weight,

for it seems to us that in this way we finally reach the position where we have no dogmas.

CHAPTER VII.

_Does the Sceptic Dogmatise?_

We say that the Sceptic does not dogmatise. We do not say 13

this, meaning by the word dogma the popular assent to certain

things rather than others (for the Sceptic does assent to

feelings that are a necessary result of sensation, as for

example, when he is warm or cold, he cannot say that he thinks

he is not warm or cold), but we say this, meaning by dogma the

acceptance of any opinion in regard to the unknown things

investigated by science. For the Pyrrhonean assents to nothing

that is unknown. Furthermore, he does not dogmatise even when 14

he utters the Sceptical formulae in regard to things that are

unknown, such as "Nothing more," or "I decide nothing,"

or any

of the others about which we shall speak later. For the one who

dogmatises regards the thing about which he is said to dogmatise, as existing in itself; the Sceptic does not however

regard these formulae as having an absolute existence, for he

assumes that the saying "All is false," includes itself with

other things as false, and likewise the saying "Nothing is

true"; in the same way "Nothing more," states that together with

other things it itself is nothing more, and cancels itself

therefore, as well as other things. We say the same also in

regard to the other Sceptical expressions. In short, if he who 15

dogmatises, assumes as existing in itself that about which he

dogmatises, the Sceptic, on the contrary, expresses his sayings

in such a way that they are understood to be themselves included, and it cannot be said that he dogmatises in saying

these things. The principal thing in uttering these formulae is

that he says what appears to him, and communicates his own

feelings in an unprejudiced way, without asserting anything in

regard to external objects.

CHAPTER VIII.

_Is Scepticism a Sect?_

We respond in a similar way if we are asked whether 16

Scepticism is a sect or not. If the word sect is defined as

meaning a body of persons who hold dogmas which are in conformity with each other, and also with phenomena, and dogma

means an assent to anything that is unknown, then we reply that

we have no sect. If, however, one means by sect, a school 17

which follows a certain line of reasoning based on phenomena,

and that reasoning shows how it is possible to apparently live

rightly, not understanding "rightly" as referring to virtue

only, but in a broader sense; if, also, it leads one to be able

to suspend the judgment, then we reply that we have a sect. For

we follow a certain kind of reasoning which is based upon

phenomena, and which shows us how to live according to the

habits, laws, and teachings of the fatherland, and our own

feelings.

CHAPTER IX.

_Does the Sceptic Study Natural Science?_

We reply similarly also to the question whether the Sceptic 18

should study natural science. For we do not study natural

science in order to express ourselves with confidence regarding

any of the dogmas that it teaches, but we take it up in order to

be able to meet every argument by one of equal weight, and also

for the sake of [Greek: ataraxia]. In the same way we study the

logical and ethical part of so-called philosophy.

CHAPTER X.

_Do the Sceptics deny Phenomena?_

Those who say that the Sceptics deny phenomena appear to me to 19

be in ignorance of our teachings. For as we said before, we do

not deny the sensations which we think we have, and which lead

us to assent involuntarily to them, and these are the phenomena.

When, however, we ask whether the object is such as it appears

to be, while we concede that it appears so and so, we question,

not the phenomenon, but in regard to that which is asserted of

the phenomenon, and that is different from doubting the phenomenon itself. For example, it appears to us that honey is

sweet. This we concede, for we experience sweetness through 20

sensation. We doubt, however, whether it is sweet by reason of

its essence, which is not a question of the phenomenon, but of

that which is asserted of the phenomenon. Should we, however,

argue directly against the phenomena, it is not with the intention of denying their existence, but to show the rashness

of the Dogmatics. For if reasoning is such a deceiver that it

well nigh snatches away the phenomena from before your eyes, how

should we not distrust it in regard to things that are unknown,

so as not to rashly follow it?

CHAPTER XI.

_The Criterion of Scepticism._

It is evident that we pay careful attention to phenomena from 21

what we say about the criterion of the Sceptical School.

The

word criterion is used in two ways. First, it is understood as a

proof of existence or non-existence, in regard to which we shall

speak in the opposing argument. Secondly, when it refers to

action, meaning the criterion to which we give heed in life, in

doing some things and refraining from doing others, and it is

about this that we shall now speak. We say, consequently, that

the criterion of the Sceptical School is the phenomenon, and in

calling it so, we mean the idea of it. It cannot be doubted, 22

as it is based upon susceptibility and involuntary feeling.

Hence no one doubts, perhaps, that an object appears so and so,

but one questions if it is as it appears. Therefore, as we

cannot be entirely inactive as regards the observances of daily

life, we live by giving heed to phenomena, and in an unprejudiced way. But this observance of what pertains to the 23

daily life, appears to be of four different kinds.

Sometimes it

is directed by the guidance of nature, sometimes by the necessity of the feelings, sometimes by the tradition of laws

and of customs, and sometimes by the teaching of the arts. It is

directed by the guidance of nature, for by nature we are 24

capable of sensation and thought; by the necessity of the

feelings, for hunger leads us to food, and thirst to drink; by

the traditions of laws and customs, for according to them we

consider piety a good in daily life, and impiety an evil; by the

teaching of the arts, for we are not inactive in the arts we

undertake. We say all these things, however, without expressing

a decided opinion.

CHAPTER XII.

_What is the aim of Scepticism?_

It follows naturally in order to treat of the aim of the 25

Sceptical School. An aim is that for which as an end all things

are done or thought, itself depending on nothing, or in other

words, it is the ultimatum of things to be desired. We say,

then, that the aim of the Sceptic is [Greek: ataraxia]

in those

things which pertain to the opinion, and moderation in the

things that life imposes. For as soon as he began to 26

philosophise he wished to discriminate between ideas, and to

understand which are true and which are false, in order to

attain [Greek: ataraxia]. He met, however, with contradictions

of equal weight, and, being unable to judge, he withheld his

opinion; and while his judgment was in suspension

[Greek:

ataraxia] followed, as if by chance, in regard to matters of

opinion. For he who is of the opinion that anything is either 27

good or bad by nature is always troubled, and when he does not

possess those things that seem to him good he thinks that he is

tortured by the things which are by nature bad, and pursues

those that he thinks to be good. Having acquired them, however,

he falls into greater perturbation, because he is excited beyond

reason and without measure from fear of a change, and he does

everything in his power to retain the things that seem to him

good. But he who is undecided, on the contrary, regarding 28

things that are good and bad by nature, neither seeks nor avoids

anything eagerly, and is therefore in a state of [Greek: ataraxia]. For that which is related of Apelles the painter

happened to the Sceptic. It is said that as he was once painting

a horse he wished to represent the foam of his mouth in the

picture, but he could not succeed in doing so, and he gave it up

and threw the sponge at the picture with which he had wiped the

colors from the painting. As soon, however, as it touched the

picture it produced a good copy of the foam. The Sceptics

likewise hoped to gain [Greek: ataraxia] by forming judgments 29

in regard to the anomaly between phenomena and the things of

thought, but they were unable to do this, and so they suspended

their judgment; and while their judgment was in suspension

[Greek: ataraxia] followed, as if by chance, as the shadow

follows a body. Nevertheless, we do not consider the Sceptic

wholly undisturbed, but he is disturbed by some things that are

inevitable. We confess that sometimes he is cold and thirsty,

and that he suffers in such ways. But in these things even the

ignorant are beset in two ways, from the feelings themselves, 30

and not less also from the fact that they think these conditions

are bad by nature. The Sceptic, however, escapes more easily, as

he rejects the opinion that anything is in itself bad by nature.

Therefore we say that the aim of the Sceptic is [Greek: ataraxia] in matters of opinion, and moderation of feeling in

those things that are inevitable. Some notable Sceptics have

added also suspension of judgment in investigation.

CHAPTER XIII.

_The General Method of Scepticism._

Since we have said that [Greek: ataraxia] follows the suspension 31

of judgment in regard to everything, it behooves us to explain how the suspension of judgment takes place.

Speaking in

general it takes place through placing things in opposition to

each other. We either place phenomena in opposition to phenomena, or the intellectual in opposition to the intellectual, or reciprocally. For example, we place 32

phenomena in opposition to phenomena when we say that this tower

appears round from a distance but square near by; the intellectual in opposition to the intellectual, when to the one

who from the order of the heavens builds a tower of reasoning to

prove that a providence exists, we oppose the fact that adversity often falls to the good and prosperity to the evil,

and that therefore we draw the conclusion that there is no

providence. The intellectual is placed in opposition to 33

phenomena, as when Anaxagoras opposed the fact that snow is

white, by saying that snow is frozen water, and, as water is

black, snow must also be black. Likewise we sometimes place the

present in opposition to the present, similarly to the above-mentioned cases, and sometimes also the present in opposition to the past or the future. As for example, when

someone proposes an argument to us that we cannot refute, we say

to him, "Before the founder of the sect to which you belong 34

was born, the argument which you propose in accordance with it

had not appeared as a valid argument, but was dormant in nature,

so in the same way it is possible that its refutation also

exists in nature, but has not yet appeared to us, so that it is

not at all necessary for us to agree with an argument that now

seems to be strong." In order to make it clearer to us what 35

we mean by these oppositions, I will proceed to give the Tropes

([Greek: tropoi]), through which the suspension of judgment is

produced, without asserting anything about their meaning or

their number, because they may be unsound, or there may be more

than I shall enumerate.

CHAPTER XIV.

_The Ten Tropes._

Certain Tropes were commonly handed down by the older Sceptics, 36

by means of which [Greek: epochê] seems to take place.

They are ten in number, and are called synonymously

[Greek:

logoi] and [Greek: tropoi]. They are these: The first is based

upon the differences in animals; the second upon the differences

in men; the third upon the difference in the constitution of the

organs of sense; the fourth upon circumstances; the fifth upon

position, distance, and place; the sixth upon mixtures; the

seventh upon the quantity and constitution of objects; the

eighth upon relation; the ninth upon frequency or rarity of 37

occurences; the tenth upon systems, customs, laws, mythical

beliefs, and dogmatic opinions. We make this order ourselves. 38

These Tropes come under three general heads: the standpoint

of the judge, the standpoint of the thing judged, and the

standpoint of both together. Under the standpoint of the judge

come the first four, for the judge is either an animal, or a

man, or a sense, and exists under certain circumstances.

Under

the standpoint of that which is judged, come the seventh and the

tenth. Under the one composed of both together, come the fifth

and the sixth, the eighth and the ninth. Again, these three

divisions are included under the Trope of relation, because 39

that is the most general one; it includes the three special

divisions, and these in turn include the ten. We say these

things in regard to their probable number, and we proceed in the

following chapter to speak of their meaning.

THE FIRST TROPE.

The first Trope, we said, is the one based upon the 40

differences in animals, and according to this Trope, different

animals do not get the same ideas of the same objects through

the senses. This we conclude from the different origin of the

animals, and also from the difference in the constitution of

their bodies. In regard to the difference in origin, some

animals originate without mixture of the sexes, while others

originate through sexual intercourse. Of those which 41

originate without intercourse of the sexes, some come from fire,

as the little animals which appear in the chimneys, others from

stagnant water, as musquitoes, others from fermented wine, as

the stinging ants, others from the earth, others from the mud,

like the frogs, others from slime, as the worms, others from

donkeys, as the beetles, others from cabbage, as caterpillars,

others from fruit, as the gall insect from the wild figs, others

from putrified animals, as bees from bulls, and wasps from

horses. Again, of those originating from intercourse of the 42

sexes, some come from animals of the same kind, as in most

cases, and others from those of different kinds, as mules.

Again, of animals in general, some are born alive, as men,

others from eggs, as birds, and others are born a lump of flesh,

as bears. It is probable therefore, that the inequalities and 43

differences in origin cause great antipathies in the animals,

and the result is incompatibility, discord, and conflict between

the sensations of the different animals. Again, the differences

in the principal parts of the body, especially in those 44

fitted by nature to judge and to perceive, may cause the greatest differences in their ideas of objects, according to the

differences in the animals themselves. As for example, those who

have the jaundice call that yellow which appears to us white,

and those who have bloodshot eyes call it blood-red.

Accordingly, as some animals have yellow eyes, and others

blood-shot ones, and still others whitish ones, and others eyes

of other colors, it is probable, I think, that they have a

different perception of colors. Furthermore, when we look

steadily at the sun for a long time, and then look down at a 45

book, the letters seem to us gold colored, and dance around. Now

some animals have by nature a lustre in their eyes, and these

emit a fine and sparkling light so that they see at night, and

we may reasonably suppose that external things do not appear the

same to them as to us. Jugglers by lightly rubbing the wick 46

of the lamp with metal rust, or with the dark yellow fluid of

the sepia, make those who are present appear now copper-colored

and now black, according to the amount of the mixture used; if

this be so it is much more reasonable to suppose that because of

the mixture of different fluids in the eyes of animals, their

ideas of objects would be different. Furthermore, when we 47

press the eye on the side, the figures, forms and sizes of

things seen appear elongated and narrow. It is therefore probable that such animals as have the pupil oblique and long,

as goats, cats, and similar animals, have ideas different from

those of the animals which have a round pupil. Mirrors according

to their different construction, sometimes show the external 48

object smaller than reality, as concave ones, and sometimes long

and narrow, as the convex ones do; others show the head of the

one looking into it down, and the feet up. As some of the

vessels around the eye fall entirely outside the eye, on 49

account of their protuberance, while others are more sunken, and

still others are placed in an even surface, it is probable that

for this reason also the ideas vary, and dogs, fishes, lions,

men, and grasshoppers do not see the same things, either of the

same size, or of similar form, but according to the impression

on the organ of sight of each animal respectively. The same

thing is true in regard to the other senses; for how can it 50

be said that shell-fish, birds of prey, animals covered with

spines, those with feathers and those with scales would be

affected in the same way by the sense of touch? and how can the

sense of hearing perceive alike in animals which have the

narrowest auditory passages, and in those that are furnished

with the widest, or in those with hairy ears and those with

smooth ones? For we, even, hear differently when we partially

stop up the ears, from what we do when we use them naturally.

The sense of