Sextus Empiricus and Greek scepticism by Mary Mills Patrick - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

In the same manner as we teach the Tropes of [Greek: epochê], 180

some set forth Tropes through which we oppose the Dogmatics,

by expressing doubt in regard to the aetiology of which they are

especially proud. So Aenesidemus teaches eight Tropes, by which

he thinks that he can prove all the dogmatic aetiology useless.

The first of these Tropes, he said, relates to the character 181

of aetiology in general, which does not give incontestable

testimony in regard to phenomena, because it treats of unseen

things. The second Trope states that although abundant resources

exist by which to investigate the cause of a thing in question,

some Dogmatics investigate it in one way only. The third Trope 182

states that the Dogmatics assign causes which do not show

any order for things which have taken place in an orderly

manner. The fourth Trope states that the Dogmatics, accepting

phenomena as they take place, think that they also understand

how unseen things take place, although perhaps the unseen things

have taken place in the same way as the phenomena, and perhaps

in some other way peculiar to themselves. The fifth Trope states 183

that they all, so to speak, assign causes according to their

own hypotheses about the elements, but not according to any

commonly accepted methods. The sixth states that they often

explain things investigated according to their own hypotheses,

but ignore opposing hypotheses which have equal probability. The

seventh states that they often give reasons for things that 184

not only conflict with phenomena, but also with their own

hypotheses. The eighth states that although that which seems

manifest, and that which is to be investigated, are often

equally inscrutable, they build up a theory from the one about

the other, although both are equally inscrutable. It is not

impossible, Aenesidemus said also, that some Dogmatics 185

should fail in their theories of causality from other combinations of reasons deducible from the Tropes given above.

Perhaps also the five Tropes of [Greek: epochê] are sufficient

to refute aetiology, for he who proposes a cause will propose

one which is either in harmony with all the sects of philosophy,

with Scepticism, and with phenomena, or one that is not.

Perhaps, however, it is not possible that a cause should be in

harmony with them, for phenomena and unknown things altogether

disagree with each other. If it is not in harmony with them, the

reason of this will also be demanded of the one who proposed 186

it; and if he accepts a phenomenon as the cause of a phenomenon,

or something unknown as the cause of the unknown, he will be

thrown into the _regressus in infinitum_; if he uses one cause

to account for another one, into the _circulus in probando_; but

if he stops anywhere, he will either say that the cause that he

proposes holds good so far as regards the things that have been

said, and introduce relation, abolishing an absolute standpoint;

or if he accepts anything by hypothesis, he will be attacked by

us. Therefore it is perhaps possible to put the temerity of the

Dogmatics to shame in aetiology by these Tropes.

CHAPTER XVIII.

_The Sceptical Formulae._

When we use any one of these Tropes, or the Tropes of 187

[Greek: epochê], we employ with them certain formulae which show

the Sceptical method and our own feeling, as for instance, the

sayings, "No more," "One must determine nothing," and certain

others. It is fitting therefore to treat of these in this place.

Let us begin with "No more."

CHAPTER XIX.

_The Formula "No more."_

We sometimes express this as I have given it, and sometimes 188

thus, "Nothing more." For we do not accept the "No more," as

some understand it, for the examination of the special, and

"Nothing more" for that of the general, but we use "No more" and

"Nothing more" without any difference, and we shall at present

treat of them as one and the same expression. Now this formula

is defective, for as when we say a double one we really mean a

double garment, and when we say a broad one we really mean a

broad road; so when we say "No more" we mean really no more than

this, or in every way the same. But some of the Sceptics use 189

instead of the interrogation "No?" the interrogation

"What, this

rather than this?" using the word "what" in the sense of

"what

is the reason," so that the formula means, "What is the reason

for this rather than for this?" It is a customary thing, however, to use an interrogation instead of a statement, as "Who

of the mortals does not know the wife of Jupiter?" and also to

use a statement instead of an interrogation, as "I seek where

Dion dwells," and "I ask why one should admire a poet."

The word

"what" is also used instead of "what for" by Menander--

"(For)

what did I remain behind?" The formula "Not more this than this"

expresses our own condition of mind, and signifies that 190

because of the equality of the things that are opposed to each

other we finally attain to a state of equilibrium of soul. We

mean by equality that equality which appears to us as probable,

by things placed in opposition to each other we mean simply

things which conflict with each other, and by a state of equilibrium we mean a state in which we do not assent to one

thing more than to another. Even if the formula "Nothing 191

more" seems to express assent or denial, we do not use it so,

but we use it loosely, and not with accuracy, either instead of

an interrogation or instead of saying, "I do not know to which

of these I would assent, and to which I would not." What lies

before us is to express what appears to us, but we are indifferent to the words by which we express it. This must be

understood, however, that we use the formula "Nothing more"

without affirming in regard to it that it is wholly sure and

true, but we present it as it appears to us.

CHAPTER XX.

_Aphasia._

We explain Aphasia as follows: The word [Greek: phasis]

is used 192

in two ways, having a general and a special signification.

According to the general signification, it expresses affirmation

or negation, as "It is day" or "It is not day"; according to the

special signification, it expresses an affirmation only, and

negations are not called [Greek: phaseis]. Now Aphasia is the

opposite of [Greek: phasis] in its general signification, which,

as we said, comprises both affirmation and negation. It follows

that Aphasia is a condition of mind, according to which we say

that we neither affirm nor deny anything. It is evident from

this that we do not understand by Aphasia something that 193

inevitably results from the nature of things, but we mean that

we now find ourselves in the condition of mind expressed by it

in regard to the things that are under investigation. It is

necessary to remember that we do not say that we affirm or deny

any of those things that are dogmatically stated in regard to

the unknown, for we yield assent only to those things which

affect our feelings and oblige us to assent to them.

CHAPTER XXI.

_"Perhaps," and "It is possible," and "It may be."_

The formulae "Perhaps," and "Perhaps not," and "It is 194

possible," and "It is not possible," and "It may be,"

and "It

may not be," we use instead of "Perhaps it is," and

"Perhaps it

is not," and "It is possible that it is," and "It is possible

that it is not," and "It may be that it is," and "It may be that

it is not." That is, we use the formula "It is not possible" for

the sake of brevity, instead of saying "It is not possible to

be," and "It may not be" instead of "It may not be that it is,"

and "Perhaps not" instead of "Perhaps it is not." Again, we do

not here dispute about words, neither do we question if the 195

formulae mean these things absolutely, but we use them loosely,

as I said before. Yet I think it is evident that these formulae

express Aphasia. For certainly the formula "Perhaps it is"

really includes that which seems to contradict it, _i.e._ the

formula "Perhaps it is not," because it does not affirm in in

regard to anything that it is really so. It is the same also in

regard to the others.

CHAPTER XXII.

[Greek: epochê] _or the Suspension of Judgment._

When I say that I suspend my judgment, I mean that I cannot 196

say which of those things presented should be believed, and

which should not be believed, showing that things appear equal

to me in respect to trustworthiness and untrustworthiness. Now

we do not affirm that they are equal, but we state what appears

to us in regard to them at the time when they present themselves

to us. [Greek: epochê] means the holding back of the opinion, so

as neither to affirm nor deny anything because of the equality

of the things in question.

CHAPTER XXIII.

_The Formula "I determine Nothing."_

In regard to the formula "I determine nothing," we say the 197

following: By "determine" we mean, not simply to speak, but to

give assent to an affirmation with regard to some unknown thing.

For it will soon be found that the Sceptic determines nothing,

not even the formula "I determine nothing," for this formula is

not a dogmatic opinion, that is an assent to something unknown,

but an expression declaring what our condition of mind is. When,

for example, the Sceptic says, "I determine nothing," he means

this: "According to my present feeling I can assert or deny

nothing dogmatically regarding the things under investigation,"

and in saying this he expresses what appears to him in reference

to the things under discussion. He does not express himself

positively, but he states what he feels.

CHAPTER XXIV.

_The Formula "Every thing is Undetermined."_

The expression "Indetermination" furthermore shows a state 198

of mind in which we neither deny nor affirm positively anything

regarding things that are investigated in a dogmatic way, that

is the things that are unknown. When then the Sceptic says

"Every thing is undetermined," he uses "is undetermined," in the

sense of "it appears undetermined to him." The words

"every

thing" do not mean all existences, but those that he has examined of the unknown things that are investigated by the

Dogmatists. By "undetermined," he means that there is no preference in the things that are placed in opposition to each

other, or that they simply conflict with each other in respect

to trustworthiness or untrustworthiness. And as the one who 199

says "I am walking" really means "It is I that am walking," so

he who says "Every thing is undetermined" means at the same

time, according to our teachings, "as far as I am concerned," or

"as it appears to me," as if he were saying "As far as I have

examined the things that are under investigation in a dogmatic

manner, it appears to me that no one of them excels the one

which conflicts with it in trustworthiness or untrustworthiness."

CHAPTER XXV.

_The Formula "Every thing is Incomprehensible."_

We treat the formula "Every thing is incomprehensible"

in 200

the same way. For "every thing" we interpret in the same way as

above, and we supply the words "to me" so that what we say is

this: "As far as I have inspected the unknown things which are

dogmatically examined, it appears to me that every thing is

incomprehensible." This is not, however, to affirm that the

things which are examined by the Dogmatists are of such a nature

as to be necessarily incomprehensible, but one expresses his own

feeling in saying "I see that I have not thus far comprehended

any of those things because of the equilibrium of the things

that are placed in opposition to each other." Whence it seems to

me that every thing that has been brought forward to dispute our

formulae has fallen wide of the mark.

CHAPTER XXVI.

_The Formulae "I do not comprehend" and "I do not understand."_

The formulae "I do not comprehend" and "I do not understand" 201

show a condition of mind in which the Sceptic stands aloof for

the present from asserting or denying anything in regard to the

unknown things under investigation, as is evident from what we

said before about the other formulae.

CHAPTER XXVII.

_The Formula "To place an equal Statement in opposition to every Statement."_

Furthermore, when we say "Every statement may have an equal 202

statement placed in opposition to it," by "every," we mean all

the statements that we have examined; we do not use the word

"statement" simply, but for a statement which seeks to prove

something dogmatically about things that are unknown, and not at

all one that shows a process of reasoning from premises and

conclusions, but something which is put together in any sort of

way. We use the word "equal" in reference to trustworthiness or

untrustworthiness. "Is placed in opposition" we use instead of

the common expression "to conflict with," and we supply

"as it

appears to me." When therefore one says, "It seems to me 203

that every statement which I have examined, which proves something dogmatically, may have another statement placed in

opposition to it which also proves something dogmatically, and

which is equal to it in trustworthiness and untrustworthiness,"

this is not asserted dogmatically, but is an expression of human

feeling as it appears to the one who feels it. Some Sceptics 204

express the formula as follows: "Every statement should have an

equal one placed in opposition to it," demanding it authoritatively thus: "Let us place in opposition to every

statement that proves something dogmatically another conflicting

statement which also seeks to prove something dogmatically, and

is equal to it in trustworthiness and untrustworthiness."

Naturally this is directed to the Sceptics, but the infinitive

should be used instead of the imperative, that is, "to oppose"

instead of "let us oppose." This formula is recommended to the 205

Sceptic, lest he should be deceived by the Dogmatists and

give up his investigations, and rashly fail of the

[Greek:

ataraxia] which is thought to accompany [Greek: epochê]

in

regard to everything, as we have explained above.

CHAPTER XXVIII.

_General Observations on the Formulae of the Sceptics._

We have treated of a sufficient number of these formulae for 206

an outline, especially since what we have said about those

mentioned applies also to others that we have omitted.

In regard

to all the Sceptical formulae, it must be understood in advance

that we do not affirm them to be absolutely true, because we say

that they can even refute themselves, since they are themselves

included in those things to which they refer, just as cathartic

medicines not only purge the body of humors, but carry off

themselves with the humors. We say then that we use these 207

formulae, not as literally making known the things for which

they are used, but loosely, and if one wishes, inaccurately. It

is not fitting for the Sceptic to dispute about words, especially as it contributes to our purpose to say that these

formulae have no absolute meaning; their meaning is a relative

one, that is, relative to the Sceptics. Besides, it is to be 208

remembered that we do not say them about all things in general,

but about the unknown, and things that are dogmatically investigated, and that we say what appears to us, and that we do

not express ourselves decidedly about the nature of external

objects. By this means I think that every sophism brought

against the Sceptical formulae can be overturned. We have now 209

shown the character of Scepticism by examining its idea, its

parts, its criterion and aim, and also the Tropes of

[Greek:

epochê], and by treating of the Sceptical formulae. We think it

therefore appropriate to enter briefly into the distinction

between Scepticism and the nearly related schools of philosophy

in order to more clearly understand the Sceptical School. We

will begin with the philosophy of Heraclitus.

CHAPTER XXIX.

_In what does the Sceptical School differ from the Philosophy

of Heraclitus?_

Now that this school differs from ours is evident, for 210

Heraclitus expresses himself about many unknown things dogmatically, which we do not, as has been said.

Aenesidemus and

his followers said that the Sceptical School is the way to the

philosophy of Heraclitus. They gave as a reason for this that

the statement that contradictory predicates appear to be applicable to the same thing, leads the way to the statement

that contradictory predicates are in reality applicable to the

same thing; and as the Sceptics say that contradictory predicates appear to be applicable to the same thing, the

Heraclitans proceed from this to the doctrine that such predicates are in reality applicable. We reply to this that the

statement that contradictory predicates appear to be applicable

to the same thing is not a dogma of the Sceptics, but is a fact

that presents itself not only to the Sceptics, but to other

philosophers, and to all men. No one, for instance, would 211

venture to say that honey does not taste sweet to those in

health, and bitter to those who have the jaundice, so that the

Heraclitans start from a preconception common to all men, as do

we also, and perhaps the other schools of philosophy likewise.

If, however, they had attributed the origin of the statement

that contradictory predicates are present in the same thing to

any of the Sceptical teachings, as, for example, to the formula

"Every thing is incomprehensible," or "I determine nothing," or

any of the other similar ones, it may be that which they say

would follow; but since they start from that which is a common

experience, not only to us, but to other philosophers, and in

life, why should one say that our school is a path to the

philosophy of Heraclitus more than any of the other schools of

philosophy, or than life itself, as we all make use of the same

subject matter? On the other hand, the Sceptical School may not 212

only fail to help towards the knowledge of the philosophy of

Heraclitus, but may even hinder it! For the Sceptic attacks all

the dogmas of Heraclitus as having been rashly given, and

opposes on the one hand the doctrine of conflagration, and on

the other, the doctrine that contradictory predicates in reality

apply to the same thing, and in regard to every dogma of Heraclitus he scorns his dogmatic rashness, and then, in the

manner that I have before referred to, adduces the formulae "I

do not understand" and "I determine nothing," which conflict

with the Heraclitan doctrines. It is absurd to say that this

conflicting school is a path to the very sect with which it

conflicts. It is then absurd to say that the Sceptical School is

a path to the philosophy of Heraclitus.

CHAPTER XXX.

_In what does the Sceptical School differ from the Philosophy

of Democritus?_

The philosophy of Democritus is also said to have community 213

with Scepticism, because it seems to use the same matter that we

do. For, from the fact that honey seems sweet to some and bitter

to others, Democritus reasons, it is said, that honey is neither

sweet nor bitter, and therefore he accords with the formula "No

more," which is a formula of the Sceptics. But the Sceptics and

the Democritans use the formula "No more" differently from each

other, for they emphasise the negation in the expression, but

we, the not knowing whether both of the phenomena exist or

neither one, and so we differ in this respect. The distinction,

however, becomes most evident when Democritus says that 214

atoms and empty space are real, for by real he means existing in

reality. Now, although he begins with the anomaly in phenomena,

yet, since he says that atoms and empty space really exist, it

is superfluous, I think, even to say that he differs from us.

CHAPTER XXXI.

_In what does Scepticism differ from the Cyrenaic Philosophy?_

Some say that the Cyrenaic School is the same as the 215

Sceptical, because that school also claims to comprehend only

conditions of mind. It differs, however, from it, because, while

the former makes pleasure and the gentle motion of the flesh its

aim, we make [Greek: ataraxia] ours, and this is opposed to the

aim of their school. For whether pleasure is present or not,

confusion awaits him who maintains that pleasure is an aim, as I

have shown in what I said about the aim. And then, in addition,

we suspend our judgment as far as the reasoning with regard to

external objects is concerned, but the Cyrenaics pronounce the

nature of these inscrutable.

CHAPTER XXXII.

_In what does Scepticism differ from the Philosophy of Protagoras?_

Protagoras makes man the measure of all things, of things 216

that are that they are, and things that are not that they are

not, meaning by measure, criterion, and by things, events, that

is to say really, man is the criterion for all events, of things

that are that they are, and of things that are not that they are

not. And for that reason he accepts only the phenomena that

appear to each man, and thus he introduces relation.

Therefore 217

he seems to have community with the Pyrrhoneans. He differs,

You may also like...