Studies in the psychology of sex, volume VI. Sex in Relation to Society by Havelock Ellis. - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

apart from the fact

that it is in the highest interests of the parents

themselves. It is

required in the interests of the child. It is required in the interests of

the State. A child can be bred, and well-bred, by one

effective parent.

But to equip a child adequately for its entrance into

life both parents

are usually needed. The State on its side--that is to

say, the community

of which parents and child alike form part--is bound to know who these

persons are who have become sponsors for a new

individual now introduced

into its midst. The most Individualistic State, the most Socialistic

State, are alike bound, if faithful to the interests,

both biological and

economic, of their constituent members generally, to

insist on the full

legal and recognized parentage of the father and mother of every child.

That is clearly demanded in the interests of the child; it is clearly

demanded also in the interests of the State.

The barrier which in Christendom has opposed itself to the natural

recognition of this fact, so injuring alike the child

and the State, has

clearly been the rigidity of the marriage system, more especially as

moulded by the Canon law. The Canonists attributed a

truly immense

importance to the _copula carnalis_, as they technically termed it. They

centred marriage strictly in the vagina; they were not greatly concerned

about either the presence or the absence of the child.

The vagina, as we

know, has not always proved a very firm centre for the support of

marriage, and that centre is now being gradually

transferred to the child.

If we turn from the Canonists to the writings of a

modern like Ellen Key,

who so accurately represents much that is most

characteristic and

essential in the late tendencies of marriage

development, we seem to have

entered a new world, even a newly illuminated world. For

"in the new

sexual morality, as in Corregio's _Notte_, the light

emanates from the

child."[369]

No doubt this change is largely a matter of sentiment, of, as we sometimes

say, mere sentiment, although there is nothing so

powerful in human

affairs as sentiment, and the revolution effected by

Jesus, the later

revolution effected by Rousseau, were mainly revolutions in sentiment. But

the change is also a matter of the growing recognition of interests and

rights, and as such it manifests itself in law. We can scarcely doubt that

we are approaching a time when it will be generally

understood that the

entrance into the world of every child, without

exception, should be

preceded by the formation of a marriage contract which, while in no way

binding the father and mother to any duties, or any

privileges, towards

each other, binds them both towards their child and at the same time

ensures their responsibility towards the State. It is

impossible for the

State to obtain more than this, but it should be

impossible for it to

demand less. A contract of such a kind "marries" the father and mother so

far as the parentage of the individual child is

concerned, and in no other

respect; it is a contract which leaves entirely

unaffected their past,

present, or future relations towards other persons,

otherwise it would be

impossible to enforce it. In all parts of the world this elementary demand

of social morality is slowly beginning to be recognized, and as it affects

hundreds of thousands of infants[370] who are yearly

branded as

"illegitimate" through no act of their own, no one can say that the

recognition has come too soon. As yet, indeed, it seems nowhere to be

complete.

Most attempts or proposals for the avoidance of

illegitimate

births are concerned with the legalizing of unions

of a less

binding degree than the present legal marriage. Such

unions would

serve to counteract other evils. Thus an English

writer, who has

devoted much study to sex questions, writes in a

private letter:

"The best remedy for the licentiousness of celibate men and the

mental and physical troubles of continence in woman

would be

found in a recognized honorable system of free

unions and

trial-marriages, in which preventive intercourse is

practiced

until the lovers were old enough to become parents,

and possessed

of sufficient means to support a family. The

prospect of a

loveless existence for young men and women of ardent

natures is

intolerable and as terrible as the prospect of

painful illness

and death. But I think the old order must change ere

long."

In Teutonic countries there is a strongly marked

current of

feeling in the direction of establishing legal

unions of a lower

degree than marriage. They exist in Sweden, as also

in Norway

where by a recent law the illegitimate child is

entitled to the

same rights in relation to both parents as the

legitimate child,

bearing the father's name and inheriting his

property (_Die Neue

Generation_, July, 1909, p. 303). In France the

well-known judge,

Magnard, so honorably distinguished for his attitude

towards

cases of infanticide by young mothers, has said: "I heartily wish

that alongside the institution of marriage as it now

exists we

had a free union constituted by simple declaration

before a

magistrate and conferring almost the same family

rights as

ordinary marriage." This wish has been widely

echoed.

In China, although polygamy in the strict sense

cannot properly

be said to exist, the interests of the child, the

woman, and the

State are alike safeguarded by enabling a man to

enter into a

kind of secondary marriage with the mother of his

child. "Thanks

to this system," Paul d'Enjoy states (_La Revue_, Sept., 1905),

"which allows the husband to marry the woman he

desires, without

being prevented by previous and undissolved unions,

it is only

right to remark that there are no seduced and

abandoned girls,

except such as no law could save from what is really

innate

depravity; and that there are no illegitimate

children except

those whose mothers are unhappily nearer to animals

by their

senses than to human beings by their reason and

dignity."

The new civil code of Japan, which is in many

respects so

advanced, allows an illegitimate child to be

"recognized" by

giving notice to the registrar; when a married man

so recognizes

a child, it appears, the child may be adopted by the

wife as her

own, though not actually rendered legitimate. This

state of

things represents a transition stage; it can

scarcely be said to

recognize the rights of the "recognized" child's mother. Japan,

it may be added, has adopted the principle of the

automatic

legitimation by marriage of the children born to the

couple

before marriage.

In Australia, where women possess a larger share

than elsewhere

in making and administering the laws, some attention

is beginning

to be given to the rights of illegitimate children.

Thus in South

Australia, paternity may be proved before birth, and

the father

(by magistrate's order) provides lodging for one

month before and

after birth, as well as nurse, doctor, and clothing,

furnishing

security that he will do so; after birth, at the

magistrate's

decision, he pays a weekly sum for the child's

maintenance. An

"illegitimate" mother may also be kept in a public institution at

the public expense for six months to enable her to

become

attached to her child.

Such provisions are developed from the widely

recognized right of

the unmarried woman to claim support for her child

from its

father. In France, indeed, and in the legal codes

which follow

the French example, it is not legally permitted to

inquire into

the paternity of an illegitimate child. Such a law

is, needless

to say, alike unjust to the mother, to the child,

and to the

State. In Austria, the law goes to the opposite,

though certainly

more reasonable, extreme, and permits even the

mother who has had

several lovers to select for herself which she

chooses to make

responsible for her child. The German code adopts an

intermediate

course, and comes only to the aid of the unmarried

mother who has

one lover. In all such cases, however, the aid given

is

pecuniary only; it insures the mother no recognition

or respect,

and (as Wahrmund has truly said in his _Ehe und

Eherecht_) it is

still necessary to insist on "the unconditional

sanctity of

motherhood, which is entitled, under whatever

circumstances it

arises, to the respect and protection of society."

It must be added that, from the social point of

view, it is not

the sexual union which requires legal recognition,

but the child

which is the product of that union. It would,

moreover, be

hopeless to attempt to legalize all sexual

connection, but it is

comparatively easy to legalize all children.

There has been much discussion in the past concerning

the particular form

which marriage ought to take. Many theorists have

exercised their

ingenuity in inventing and preaching new and unusual

marriage-arrangements

as panaceas for social ills; while others have exerted even greater energy

in denouncing all such proposals as subversive of the

foundations of human

society. We may regard all such discussions, on the one side or the other,

as idle.

In the first place marriage customs are far too

fundamental, far too

intimately blended with the primary substance of human and indeed animal

society, to be in the slightest degree shaken by the

theories or the

practices of mere individuals, or even groups of

individuals.

Monogamy--the more or less prolonged cohabitation of two individuals of

opposite sex--has been the prevailing type of sexual

relationship among

the higher vertebrates and through the greater part of human history. This

is admitted even by those who believe (without any sound evidence) that

man has passed through a stage of sexual promiscuity.

There have been

tendencies to variation in one direction or another, but at the lowest

stages and the highest stages, so far as can be seen,

monogamy represents

the prevailing rule.

It must be said also, in the second place, that the

natural prevalence of

monogamy as the normal type of sexual relationship by no means excludes

variations. Indeed it assumes them. "There is nothing precise in Nature,"

according to Diderot's saying. The line of Nature is a curve that

oscillates from side to side of the norm. Such

oscillations inevitably

occur in harmony with changes in environmental

conditions, and, no doubt,

with peculiarities of personal disposition. So long as no arbitrary and

merely external attempt is made to force Nature, the

vital order is

harmoniously maintained. Among certain species of ducks when males are in

excess polyandric families are constituted, the two

males attending their

female partner without jealousy, but when the sexes

again become equal in

number the monogamic order is restored. The natural

human deviations from

the monogamic order seem to be generally of this

character, and largely

conditioned by the social and economic environment. The most common

variation, and that which most clearly possesses a

biological foundation,

is the tendency to polygyny, which is found at all

stages of culture,

even, in an unrecognized and more or less promiscuous

shape, in the

highest civilization.[371] It must be remembered,

however, that recognized

polygyny is not the rule even where it prevails; it is merely permissive;

there is never a sufficient excess of women to allow

more than a few of

the richer and more influential persons to have more

than one wife.[372]

It has further to be borne in mind that a certain

elasticity of the formal

side of marriage while, on the one side, it permits

variations from the

general monogamic order, where such are healthful or

needed to restore a

balance in natural conditions, on the other hand

restrains such variations

in so far as they are due to the disturbing influence of artificial

constraint. Much of the polygyny, and polyandry also,

which prevails among

us to-day is an altogether artificial and unnatural form of polygamy.

Marriages which on a more natural basis would be

dissolved cannot legally

be dissolved, and consequently the parties to them,

instead of changing

their partners and so preserving the natural monogamic order, take on

other additional partners and so introduce an unnatural polygamy. There

will always be variations from the monogamic order and civilization is

certainly not hostile to sexual variation. Whether we

reckon these

variations as legitimate or illegitimate, they will

still take place; of

that we may be certain. The path of social wisdom seems to lie on the one

hand in making the marriage relationship flexible enough to reduce to a

minimum these deviations--not because such deviations

are intrinsically

bad but because they ought not to be forced into

existence--and on the

other hand in according to these deviations when they

occur such a measure

of recognition as will deprive them of injurious

influence and enable

justice to be done to all the parties concerned. We too often forget that

our failure to recognize such variations merely means

that we accord in

such cases an illegitimate permission to perpetrate

injustice. In those

parts of the world in which polygyny is recognized as a permissible

variation a man is legally held to his natural

obligations towards all his

sexual mates and towards the children he has by those

mates. In no part of

the world is polygyny so prevalent as in Christendom; in no part of the

world is it so easy for a man to escape the obligations incurred by

polygyny. We imagine that if we refuse to recognize the fact of polygyny,

we may refuse to recognize any obligations incurred by polygyny. By

enabling a man to escape so easily from the obligations of his polygamous

relationships we encourage him, if he is unscrupulous, to enter into them;

we place a premium on the immorality we loftily

condemn.[373] Our polygyny

has no legal existence, and therefore its obligations

can have no legal

existence. The ostrich, it was once imagined, hides its head in the sand

and attempts to annihilate facts by refusing to look at them; but there is

only one known animal which adopts this course of

action, and it is called

Man.

Monogamy, in the fundamental biological sense,

represents the natural

order into which the majority of sexual facts will

always naturally fall

because it is the relationship which most adequately

corresponds to all

the physical and spiritual facts involved. But if we

realize that sexual

relationships primarily concern only the persons who

enter into those

relationships, and if we further realize that the

interest of society in

such relationships is confined to the children which

they produce, we

shall also realize that to fix by law the number of

women with whom a man

shall have sexual relationships, and the number of men with whom a woman

shall unite herself, is more unreasonable than it would be to fix by law

the number of children they shall produce. The State has a right to

declare whether it needs few citizens or many; but in

attempting to

regulate the sexual relationships of its members the

State attempts an

impossible task and is at the same time guilty of an

impertinence.

There is always a tendency, at certain stages of

civilization, to

insist on a merely formal and external uniformity,

and a

corresponding failure to see not only that such

uniformity is

unreal, but also that it has an injurious effect, in

so far as it

checks beneficial variations. The tendency is by no

means

confined to the sexual sphere. In England there is,

for instance,

a tendency to make building laws which enjoin, in

regard to

places of human habitation, all sorts of provisions

that on the

whole are fairly beneficial, but which in practice

act

injuriously, because they render many simple and

excellent human

habitations absolutely illegal, merely because such

habitations

fail to conform to regulations which, under some

circumstances,

are not only unnecessary, but mischievous.

Variation is a fact that will exist whether we will

or no; it can

only become healthful if we recognize and allow for

it. We may

even have to recognize that it is a more marked

tendency in

civilization than in more primitive social stages.

Thus Gerson

argues (_Sexual-Probleme_, Sept., 1908, p. 538) that

just as the

civilized man cannot be content with the coarse and

monotonous

food which satisfies the peasant, so it is in sexual

matters; the

peasant youth and girl in their sexual relationships

are nearly

always monogamous, but civilized people, with their

more

versatile and sensitive tastes, are apt to crave for

variety.

Sénancour (_De l'Amour_, vol. ii, "Du Partage," p.

127) seems to

admit the possibility of marriage variations, as of

sharing a

wife, provided nothing is done to cause rivalry, or

to impair the

soul's candor. Lecky, near the end of his _History

of European

Morals_, declared his belief that, while the

permanent union of

two persons is the normal and prevailing type of

marriage, it by

no means follows that, in the interests of society,

it should be

the only form. Remy de Gourmont similarly (_Physique

de l'Amour_,

p. 186), while stating that the couple is the

natural form of

marriage and its prolonged continuance a condition

of human

superiority, adds that the permanence of the union

can only be

achieved with difficulty. So, also, Professor W.

Thomas (_Sex and

Society_, 1907, p. 193), while regarding monogamy as

subserving

social needs, adds: "Speaking from the biological standpoint

monogamy does not, as a rule, answer to the

conditions of highest

stimulation, since here the problematical and

elusive elements

disappear to some extent, and the object of

attention has grown

so familiar in consciousness that the emotional

reactions are

qualified. This is the fundamental explanation of

the fact that

married men and women frequently become interested

in others than

their partners in matrimony."

Pepys, whose unconscious self-dissection admirably

illustrates so

many psychological tendencies, clearly shows how--by

a logic of

feeling deeper than any intellectual logic--the

devotion to

monogamy subsists side by side with an irresistible

passion for

sexual variety. With his constantly recurring

wayward attraction

to a long series of women he retains throughout a

deep and

unchanging affection for his charming young wife. In

the privacy

of his _Diary_ he frequently refers to her in terms

of endearment

which cannot be feigned; he enjoys her society; he

is very

particular about her dress; he delights in her

progress in music,

and spends much money on her training; he is

absurdly jealous

when he finds her in the society of a man. His

subsidiary

relationships with other women recur irresistibly,

but he has no

wish either to make them very permanent or to allow

them to

engross him unduly. Pepys represents a common type

of civilized

"monogamist" who is perfectly sincere and extremely convinced in

his advocacy of monogamy, as he understands it, but

at the same

time believes and acts on the belief that monogamy

by no means

excludes the need for sexual variation. Lord

Morley's statement

(_Diderot_, vol. ii, p. 20) that "man is

instinctively

polygamous," can by no means be accepted, but if we interpret it

as meaning that man is an instinctively monogamous

animal with a

concomitant desire for sexual variation, there is

much evidence

in its favor.

Women must be as free as men to mould their own

amatory life.

Many consider, however, that such freedom on the