Studies in the psychology of sex, volume VI. Sex in Relation to Society by Havelock Ellis. - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

chapter on

marriage of his _Origin and Development of the Moral

Ideas_ (vol.

ii, p. 398) with the statement that "when both

husband and wife

desire to separate, it seems to many enlightened

minds that the

State has no right to prevent them from dissolving

the marriage

contract, provided the children are properly cared

for; and that,

for the children, also, it is better to have the

supervision of

one parent only than of two who cannot agree."

In France the leaders of the movement of social

reform seem to be

almost, or quite, unanimous in believing that the

next step in

regard to divorce is the establishment of divorce by

mutual

consent. This was, for instance, the result reached

in a

symposium to which thirty-one distinguished men and

women

contributed. All were in favor of divorce by mutual

consent; the

only exception was Madame Adam, who said she had

reached a state

of skepticism with regard to political and social

forms, but

admitted that for nearly half a century she had been

a strong

advocate of divorce. A large number of the

contributors were in

favor of divorce at the desire of one party only

(_La Revue_,

March 1, 1901). In other countries, also, there is a

growing

recognition that this solution of the question, with

due

precautions to avoid any abuses to which it might

otherwise be

liable, is the proper and inevitable solution.

As to the exact method by which divorce by mutual

consent should

be effected, opinions differ, and the matter is

likely to be

differently arranged in different countries. The

Japanese plan

seems simple and judicious (see _ante_, p. 461).

Paul and Victor

Margueritte (_Quelques Idées_, pp. 3 et seq.), while

realizing

that the conflict of feeling in the matter of

personal

associations involves decisions which are entirely

outside the

competence of legal tribunals, recognize that such

tribunals are

necessary in order to deal with the property of

divorced persons,

and also, in the last resort, with the question of

the care of

the children. They should not act in public. These

writers

propose that each party should choose a

representative, and that

these two should choose a third; and that this

tribunal should

privately investigate, and if they agreed should

register the

divorce, which should take place six or twelve

months later, or

three years later, if only desired by one of the

parties. Dr.

Shufeldt ("Psychopathia Sexualis and Divorce") proposes that a

divorce-court judge should conduct, alone, the

hearing of any

cases of marital discord, the husband and wife

appearing directly

before him, without counsel, though with their

witnesses, if

necessary; should medical experts be required the

judge alone

would be empowered to call them.

When we realize that the long delay in the acceptance of so just and

natural a basis of divorce is due to an artificial

tension created by the

pressure of the dead hand of Canon law--a tension

confined exclusively to

Christendom--we may also realize that with the final

disappearance of that

tension the just and natural order in this relationship will spring back

the more swiftly because that relief has been so long

delayed. "Nature

abhors a vacuum nowhere more than in a marriage," Ellen Key remarks in the

language of antiquated physical metaphor; the vacuum

will somehow be

filled, and if it cannot be filled in a natural and

orderly manner it will

be filled in an unnatural and disorderly manner. It is the business of

society to see that no laws stand in the way of the

establishment of

natural order.

Reform upon a reasonable basis has been made difficult by the unfortunate

retention of the idea of delinquency. With the

traditions of the Canonists

at the back of our heads we have somehow persuaded

ourselves that there

cannot be a divorce unless there is a delinquent, a real serious

delinquent who, if he had his deserts, would be

imprisoned and consigned

to infamy. But in the marriage relationship, as in all other

relationships, it is only in a very small number of

cases that one party

stands towards the other as a criminal, even a

defendant. This is often

obvious in the early stages of conjugal alienation. But it remains true in

the end. The wife commits adultery and the husband as a matter of course

assumes the position of plaintiff. But we do not inquire how it is that he

has not so won her love that her adultery is out of the question; such

inquiry might lead to the conclusion that the real

defendant is the

husband. And similarly when the husband is accused of

brutal cruelty the

law takes no heed to inquire whether in the infliction of less brutal but

not less poignant wounds, the wife also should not be

made defendant.

There are a few cases, but only a few, in which the

relationship of

plaintiff and defendant is not a totally false and

artificial

relationship, an immoral legal fiction. In most cases, if the truth were

fully known, husband and wife should come side by side to the divorce

court and declare: "We are both in the wrong: we have not been able to

fulfil our engagements to each other; we have erred in choosing each

other." The long reports of the case in open court, the mutual

recriminations, the detectives, the servant girls and

other witnesses, the

infamous inquisition into intimate secrets--all these

things, which no

necessity could ever justify, are altogether

unnecessary.

It is said by some that if there were no impediments to divorce a man

might be married in succession to half a dozen women.

These simple-minded

or ignorant persons do not seem to be aware that even

when marriage is

absolutely indissoluble a man can, and frequently does, carry on sexual

relationships not merely successively, but, if he

chooses, even

simultaneously, with half a dozen women. There is,

however, this important

difference that, in the one case, the man is encouraged by the law to

believe that he need only treat at most one of the six women with anything

approaching to justice and humanity; in the other case the law insists

that he shall fairly and openly fulfil his obligations towards all the six

women. It is a very important difference, and there

ought to be no

question as to which state of things is moral and which immoral. It is no

concern of the State to inquire into the number of

persons with whom a man

or a woman chooses to have sexual relationships; it is a private matter

which may indeed affect their own finer spiritual

development but which it

is impertinent for the State to pry into. It is,

however, the concern of

the State, in its own collective interest and that of

its members, to see

that no injustice is done.

But what about the children? That is necessarily a very important

question. The question of the arrangements made for the children in cases

of divorce is always one to which the State must give

its regulative

attention, for it is only when there are children that the State has any

real concern in the matter.

At one time it was even supposed by some that the

existence of children

was a serious argument against facility of divorce. A

more reasonable view

is now generally taken. It is, in the first place,

recognized that a very

large proportion of couples seeking divorce have no

children. In England

the proportion is about forty per cent.; in some other countries it is

doubtless larger still. But even when there are children no one who

realizes what the conditions are in families where the parents ought to be

but are not divorced can have any doubt that usually

those conditions are

extremely bad for the children. The tension between the parents absorbs

energy which should be devoted to the children. The

spectacle of the

grievances or quarrels of their parents is demoralizing for the children,

and usually fatal to any respect towards them. At the

best it is

injuriously distressing to the children. One effective parent, there

cannot be the slightest doubt, is far better for a child than two

ineffective parents. There is a further point, often

overlooked, for

consideration here. Two people when living together at variance--one of

them perhaps, it is not rarely the case, nervously

abnormal or

diseased--are not fitted to become parents, nor in the best condition for

procreation. It is, therefore, not merely an act of

justice to the

individual, but a measure called for in the interests of the State, that

new citizens should not be brought into the community

through such

defective channels.[353] From this point of view all the interests of the

State are on the side of facility of divorce.

There is a final argument which is often brought forward against facility

of divorce. Marriage, it is said, is for the protection of women;

facilitate divorce and women are robbed of that

protection. It is obvious

that this argument has little application as against

divorce by mutual

consent. Certainly it is necessary that divorce should only be arranged

under conditions which in each individual case have

received the approval

of the law as just. But it must always be remembered

that the essential

fact of marriage is not naturally, and should never

artificially be made,

an economic question. It is possible--that is a question which society

will have to consider--that a woman should be paid for being a mother on

the ground that she is rearing new citizens for the

State. But neither the

State nor her husband nor anyone else ought to pay her for exercising

conjugal rights. The fact that such an argument can be brought forward

shows how far we are from the sound biological attitude towards sexual

relationships. Equally unsound is the notion that the

virgin bride brings

her husband at marriage an important capital which is

consumed in the

first act of intercourse and can never be recovered.

That is a notion

which has survived into civilization, but it belongs to barbarism and not

to civilization. So far as it has any validity it lies within a sphere of

erotic perversity which cannot be taken into

consideration in an

estimation of moral values. For most men, however, in

any case, whether

they realize it or not, the woman who has been initiated into the

mysteries of love has a higher erotic value than the

virgin, and there

need be no anxiety on this ground concerning the wife

who has lost her

virginity. It is probably a significant fact that this anxiety for the

protection of women by the limitation of divorce is

chiefly brought

forward by men and not by women themselves. A woman at marriage is

deprived by society and the law of her own name. She has been deprived

until recently of the right to her own earnings. She is deprived of the

most intimate rights in her own person. She is deprived under some

circumstances of her own child, against whom she may

have committed no

offence whatever. It is perhaps scarcely surprising that she is not

greatly appreciative of the protection afforded her by the withholding of

the right to divorce her husband. "Ah, no, no

protection!" a brilliant

French woman has written. "We have been protected long enough. The only

protection to grant women is to cease protecting

them."[354] As a matter

of fact the divorce movement appears to develop, on the whole, with that

development of woman's moral responsibility traced in

the previous

chapter, and where divorce is freest women occupy the

highest position.

We cannot fail to realize as we grasp the nature and

direction of the

modern movement of divorce that the final tendency of

that movement is to

efface itself. Necessary as the Divorce Court has been as the inevitable

corollary of an impossible ecclesiastical conception of marriage, no

institution is now more hideous, more alien to the

instinctive feelings

generated by a fine civilization, and more opposed to

the dignity of

womanhood.[355] Its disappearance and its substitution by private

arrangements, effected on their contractive sides,

especially if there are

children to provide for, under legal and if necessary

judicial

supervision, is, and always has been, the natural result of the attainment

of a reasonably high stage of civilization. The Divorce Court has merely

been a phase in the history of modern marriage, and a

phase that has

really been repugnant to all concerned in it. There is no need to view the

project of its ultimate disappearance with anything but satisfaction. It

was merely the outcome of an artificial conception of

marriage. It is time

to return to the consideration of that conception.

We have seen that when the Catholic development of the archaic conception

of marriage as a sacrament, slowly elaborated and

fossilized by the

ingenuity of the Canonists, was at last nominally

dethroned, though not

destroyed, by the movement associated with the

Reformation, it was

replaced by the conception of marriage as a contract.

This conception of

marriage as a contract still enjoys a considerable

amount of credit

amongst us.

There must always be contractive elements, implicit or explicit, in a

marriage; that was well recognized even by the

Canonists. But when we

treat marriage as all contract, and nothing but

contract, we have to

realize that we have set up a very peculiar form of

contract, not

voidable, like other contracts, by the agreement of the parties to it, but

dissoluble as a sort of punishment of delinquency rather than by the

voluntary annulment of a bond.[356] When the Protestant Reformers seized

on the idea of marriage as a contract they were not

influenced by any

reasoned analysis of the special characteristics of a

contract; they were

merely anxious to secure a plausible ground, already

admitted even by the

Canonists to cover certain aspects of the matrimonial

union, on which they

could declare that marriage is a secular and not an

ecclesiastical matter,

a civil bond and not a sacramental process.[357]

Like so much else in the Protestant revolt, the strength of this attitude

lay in the fact that it was a protest, based on its

negative side on

reasonable and natural grounds. But while Protestantism was right in its

attempt--for it was only an attempt--to deny the

authority of Canon law,

that attempt was altogether unsatisfactory on the

positive side. As a

matter of fact marriage is not a true contract and no

attempt has ever

been made to convert it into a true contract.

Various writers have treated marriage as an actual

contract or

argued that it ought to be converted into a true

contract. Mrs.

Mona Caird, for instance ("The Morality of

Marriage,"

_Fortnightly Review_, 1890), believes that when

marriage becomes

really a contract "a couple would draw up their

agreement, or

depute the task to their friends, as is now

generally done as

regards marriage settlements. They agree to live

together on such

and such terms, making certain stipulations within

the limits of

the code." The State, she holds, should, however, demand an

interval of time between notice of divorce and the

divorce

itself, if still desired when that interval has

passed.

Similarly, in the United States Dr. Shufeldt

("Needed Revision of

the Laws of Marriage and Divorce," _Medico-Legal

Journal_, Dec.,

1897) insists that marriage must be entirely put

into the hands

of the legal profession and "made a civil contract, explicit in

detail, and defining terms of divorce, in the event

that a

dissolution of the contract is subsequently

desired." He adds

that medical certificates of freedom from hereditary

and acquired

disease should be required, and properly regulated

probationary

marriages also be instituted.

In France, a deputy of the Chamber was, in 1891, so

convinced

that marriage is a contract, like any other

contract, that he

declared that "to perform music at the celebration of a marriage

is as ridiculous as it would be to send for a tenor

to a notary's

to celebrate a sale of timber." He was of quite

different mind

from Pepys, who, a couple of centuries earlier, had

been equally

indignant at the absence of music from a wedding,

which, he said,

made it like a coupling of dog and bitch.

A frequent demand of those who insist that marriage

must be

regarded as a contract is marriage contracted for a

term of

years. Marriages could be contracted for a term of

five years or

less in old Japan, and it is said that they were

rarely or never

dissolved at the end of the term. Goethe, in his

_Wahlverwandtschaften_ (Part I, Ch. X) incidentally

introduced a

proposal for marriages for a term of five years and

attached much

moral significance to the prolongation of the

marriage beyond

that term without external compulsion. (Bloch

considers that

Goethe had probably heard of the Japanese custom,

_Sexual Life of

Our Time_, p. 241.) Professor E.D. Cope ("The

Marriage Problem,"

_Open Court_, Nov. 15 and 22, 1888), likewise, in

order to remove

matrimony from the domain of caprice and to permit

full and fair

trial, advocated "a system of civil marriage

contracts which

shall run for a definite time. These contracts

should be of the

same value and effect as the existing marriage

contract. The time

limits should be increased rapidly, so as to prevent

women of

mature years being deprived of support. The first

contract ought

not to run for less than five years, so as to give

ample

opportunity for acquaintance, and for the recovery

from temporary

disagreements." This first contract, Cope held,

should be

terminable at the wish of either party; the second

contract, for

ten or fifteen years, should only be terminable at

the wish of

both parties, and the third should be permanent and

indissoluble.

George Meredith, the distinguished novelist, also,

more recently,

threw out the suggestion that marriages should be

contracted for

a term of years.

It can scarcely be said that marriages for a term of

years

constitute a very satisfactory solution of the

difficulties at

present encountered. They would not commend

themselves to young

lovers, who believe that their love is eternal, nor,

so long as

the union proves satisfactory, is there any need to

introduce the

disturbing idea of a legal termination of the

contract. On the

other hand, if the union proves unhappy, it is not

reasonable to

insist on the continuation for ten or even five

years of an empty

form which corresponds to no real marriage union.

Even if

marriage is placed on the most prosaic contractive

basis it is a

mistake, and indeed an impossibility, to pre-ordain

the length of

its duration. The system of fixing the duration of

marriage

beforehand for a term of years involves exactly the

same

principle as the system of fixing it beforehand for

life. It is

open to the same objection that it is incompatible

with any

vital relationship. As the demand for vital reality

and

effectiveness in social relationships grows, this

fact is

increasingly felt. We see exactly the same change

among us in

regard to the system of inflicting fixed sentences

of

imprisonment on criminals. To send a man to prison

for five years

or for life, without any regard to the unknown

problem of the

vital reaction of imprisonment on the man--a

reaction which will

be different in every individual case--is slowly

coming to be

regarded as an absurdity.

If marriage were really placed on the basis of a

contract, not only would

that contract be voidable at the will of the two parties concerned,

without any question of delinquency coming into the

question, but those

parties would at the outset themselves determine the

conditions regulating

the contract. But nothing could be more unlike our

actual marriage. The

two parties are bidden to accept each other as husband and wife; they are

not invited to make a contract; they are not even told that, little as

they may know it, they have in fact made a very

complicated and elaborate

contract that was framed on lines laid down, for a large part, thousands

of years before they were born. Unless they have studied law they are

totally ignorant, also, that this co