Studies in the psychology of sex, volume VI. Sex in Relation to Society by Havelock Ellis. - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

sacrificing the foetus whenever the interests of the

mother demand such a

sacrifice. General medical opinion is not, however,

prepared at present to

go further, and is distinctly disinclined to aid the

parents in exerting

an unqualified control over the foetus in the womb, nor is it yet disposed

to practice abortion on eugenic grounds. It is obvious, indeed, that

medicine cannot in this matter take the initiative, for it is the primary

duty of medicine to save life. Society itself must

assume the

responsibility of protecting the race.

Dr. S. Macvie ("Mother _versus_ Child,"

_Transactions Edinburgh

Obstetrical Society_, vol. xxiv, 1899) elaborately

discusses the

respective values of the foetus and the adult on the

basis of

life-expectancy, and concludes that the foetus is

merely

"a parasite performing no function whatever," and that "unless

the life-expectancy of the child covers the years in

which its

potentiality is converted into actuality, the

relative values of

the maternal and foetal life will be that of actual

as against

potential." This statement seems fairly sound.

Ballantyne

(_Manual of Antenatal Pathology: The Foetus_, p.

459)

endeavors to make the statement more precise by

saying that "the

mother's life has a value, because she is what she

is, while the

foetus only has a possible value, on account of what

it may

become."

Durlacher, among others, has discussed, in careful

and cautious

detail, the various conditions in which the

physician should, or

should not, induce abortion in the interests of the

mother ("Der

Künstliche Abort," _Wiener Klinik_, Aug. and Sept., 1906); so

also, Eugen Wilhelm ("Die Abtreibung und das Recht des Arztes zur

Vernichtung der Leibesfrucht," _Sexual-Probleme_, May and June,

1909). Wilhelm further discusses whether it is

desirable to alter

the laws in order to give the physician greater

freedom in

deciding on abortion. He concludes that this is not

necessary,

and might even act injuriously, by unduly hampering

medical

freedom. Any change in the law should merely be, he

considers, in

the direction of asserting that the destruction of

the foetus is

not abortion in the legal sense, provided it is

indicated by the

rules of medical science. With reference to the

timidity of some

medical men in inducing abortion, Wilhelm remarks

that, even in

the present state of the law, the physician who

conscientiously

effects abortion, in accordance with his best

knowledge, even if

mistakenly, may consider himself safe from all legal

penalties,

and that he is much more likely to come in conflict

with the law

if it can be proved that death followed as a result

of his

neglect to induce abortion.

Pinard, who has discussed the right to control the

foetal

life (_Annales de Gynécologie_, vols. lii and liii,

1899 and

1900), inspired by his enthusiastic propaganda for

the salvation

of infant life, is led to the unwarranted conclusion

that no one

has the rights of life and death over the foetus;

"the infant's

right to his life is an imprescriptible and sacred

right, which

no power can take from him." There is a mistake

here, unless

Pinard deliberately desires to place himself, like

Tolstoy, in

opposition to current civilized morality. So far

from the infant

having any "imprescriptible right to life," even the adult has,

in human societies, no such inalienable right, and

very much less

the foetus, which is not strictly a human being at

all. We assume

the right of terminating the lives of those

individuals whose

anti-social conduct makes them dangerous, and, in

war, we

deliberately terminate, amid general applause and

enthusiasm, the

lives of men who have been specially selected for

this purpose on

account of their physical and general efficiency. It

would be

absurdly inconsistent to say that we have no rights

over the

lives of creatures that have, as yet, no part in

human society at

all, and are not so much as born. We are here in

presence of a

vestige of ancient theological dogma, and there can

be little

doubt that, on the theoretical side at all events,

the

"imprescriptible right" of the embryo will go the same way as the

"imprescriptible right" of the spermatozöon. Both rights are

indeed "imprescriptible."

Of recent years a new, and, it must be admitted,

somewhat unexpected,

aspect of this question of abortion has been revealed.

Hitherto it has

been a question entirely in the hands of men, first,

following the Roman

traditions, in the hands of Christian ecclesiastics, and later, in those

of the professional castes. Yet the question is in

reality very largely,

and indeed mainly, a woman's question, and now, more

especially in

Germany, it has been actively taken up by women. The

Gräfin Gisela

Streitberg occupies the pioneering place in this

movement with her book

_Das Recht zur Beiseitigung Keimenden Lebens_, and was speedily followed,

from 1897 onwards, by a number of distinguished women

who occupy a

prominent place in the German woman's movement, among

others Helene

Stöcker, Oda Olberg, Elisabeth Zanzinger, Camilla

Jellinek. All these

writers insist that the foetus is not yet an independent human being, and

that every woman, by virtue of the right over her own

body, is entitled to

decide whether it shall become an independent human

being. At the Woman's

Congress held in the autumn of 1905, a resolution was

passed demanding

that abortion should only be punishable when effected by another person

against the wish of the pregnant women herself.[441] The acceptance of

this resolution by a representative assembly is

interesting proof of the

interest now taken by women in the question, and of the strenuous attitude

they are tending to assume.

Elisabeth Zanzinger ("Verbrechen gegen die

Leibesfrucht,"

_Geschlecht und Gesellschaft_, Bd. II, Heft 5, 1907)

ably and

energetically condemns the law which makes abortion

a crime. "A

woman herself is the only legitimate possessor of

her own body

and her own health.... Just as it is a woman's

private right, and

most intimate concern, to present her virginity as

her best gift

to the chosen of her heart, so it is certainly a

pregnant woman's

own private concern if, for reasons which seem good

to her, she

decides to destroy the results of her action." A

woman who

destroys the embryo which might become a burden to

the community,

or is likely to be an inferior member of society,

this writer

urges, is doing a service to the community, which

ought to reward

her, perhaps by granting her special privileges as

regards the

upbringing of her other children. Oda Olberg, in a

thoughtful

paper ("Ueber den Juristischen Schutz des Keimenden Lebens," _Die

Neue Generation_, June, 1908), endeavors to make

clear all that

is involved in the effort to protect the developing

embryo

against the organism that carries it, to protect a

creature, that

is, against itself and its own instincts. She

considers that most

of the women who terminate their pregnancies

artificially would

only have produced undesirables, for the normal,

healthy, robust

woman has no desire to effect abortion. "There are women who are

psychically sterile, without being physically so,

and who possess

nothing of motherhood but the ability to bring

forth. These, when

they abort, are simply correcting a failure of

Nature." Some of

them, she remarks, by going on to term, become

guilty of the far

worse offence of infanticide. As for the women who

desire

abortion merely from motives of vanity, or

convenience, Oda

Olberg points out that the circles in which these

motives rule

are quite able to limit their children without

having to resort

to abortion. She concludes that society must protect

the young

life in every way, by social hygiene, by laws for

the protection

of the workers, by spreading a new morality on the

basis of the

laws of heredity. But we need no law to protect the

young

creature against its own mother, for a thousand

natural forces

are urging the mother to protect her own child, and

we may be

sure that she will not disobey these forces without

very good

reasons. Camilla Jellinek, again (_Die

Strafrechtsreform_, etc.,

Heidelberg, 1909), in a powerful and well-informed

address before

the Associated German Frauenvereine, at Breslau,

argues in the

same sense.

The lawyers very speedily came to the assistance of

the women in

this matter, the more readily, no doubt, since the

traditions of

the greatest and most influential body of law

already pointed, on

one side at all events, in the same direction. It

may, indeed, be

claimed that it was from the side of law--and in

Italy, the

classic land of legal reform--that this new movement

first begun.

In 1888, Balestrini published, at Turin, his

_Aborto,

Infanticidio ed Esposizione d'Infante_, in which he

argued that

the penalty should be removed from abortion. It was

a very able

and learned book, inspired by large ideas and a

humanitarian

spirit, but though its importance is now recognized,

it cannot be

said that it attracted much attention on

publication.

It is especially in Germany that, during recent

years, lawyers

have followed women reformers, by advocating, more

or less

completely, the abolition of the punishment for

abortion. So

distinguished an authority as Von Liszt, in a

private letter to

Camilla Jellinek (op. cit.), states that he regards

the

punishment of abortion as "very doubtful," though he considers

its complete abolition impracticable; he thinks

abortion might be

permitted during the early months of pregnancy, thus

bringing

about a return of the old view. Hans Gross states

his opinion

(_Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie_, Bd. XII, p.

345) that the

time is not far distant when abortion will no longer

be punished.

Radbruch and Von Lilienthal speak in the same sense.

Weinberg has

advocated a change in the law (_Mutterschutz_, 1905,

Heft 8),

and Kurt Hiller (_Die Neue Generation_, April,

1909), also from

the legal side, argues that abortion should only be

punishable

when effected by a married woman, without the

knowledge and

consent of her husband.

The medical profession, which took the first step in

modern times in the

authorization of abortion, has not at present taken any further step. It

has been content to lay down the principle that when the interests of the

mother are opposed to those of the foetus, it is the

latter which must be

sacrificed. It has hesitated to take the further step of placing abortion

on the eugenic basis, and of claiming the right to

insist on abortion

whenever the medical and hygienic interests of society demand such a step.

This attitude is perfectly intelligible. Medicine has in the past been

chiefly identified with the saving of lives, even of

worthless and worse

than worthless lives; "Keep everything alive! Keep everything alive!"

nervously cried Sir James Paget. Medicine has confined itself to the

humble task of attempting to cure evils, and is only today beginning to

undertake the larger and nobler task of preventing them.

"The step from killing the child in the womb to

murdering a

person when out of the womb, is a dangerously narrow

one," sagely

remarks a recent medical author, probably speaking

for many

others, who somehow succeed in blinding themselves

to the fact

that this "dangerously narrow step" has been taken by mankind,

only too freely, for thousands of years past, long

before

abortion was known in the world.

Here and there, however, medical authors of repute

have advocated

the further extension of abortion, with precautions,

and under

proper supervision, as an aid to eugenic progress.

Thus,

Professor Max Flesch (_Die Neue Generation_, April,

1909) is in

favor of a change in the law permitting abortion

(provided it is

carried out by the physician) in special cases, as

when the

mother's pregnancy has been due to force, when she

has been

abandoned, or when, in the interests of the

community, it is

desirable to prevent the propagation of insane,

criminal,

alcoholic, or tuberculous persons.

In France, a medical man, Dr. Jean Darricarrère, has

written a

remarkable novel, _Le Droit d'Avortement_ (1906),

which advocates

the thesis that a woman always possesses a complete

right to

abortion, and is the supreme judge as to whether she

will or not

undergo the pain and risks of childbirth. The

question is, here,

however, obviously placed not on medical, but on

humanitarian and

feminist grounds.

We have seen that, alike on the side of practice and of theory, a great

change has taken place during recent years in the

attitude towards

abortion. It must, however, clearly be recognized that, unlike the control

of procreation by methods for preventing conception,

facultative abortion

has not yet been embodied in our current social

morality. If it is

permissible to interpolate a personal opinion, I may say that to me it

seems that our morality is here fairly reasonable.[442]

I am decidedly of

opinion that an unrestricted permission for women to

practice abortion in

their own interests, or even for communities to practice it in the

interests of the race, would be to reach beyond the

stage of civilization

we have at present attained. As Ellen Key very forcibly argues, a

civilization which permits, without protest, the

barbarous slaughter of

its carefully selected adults in war has not yet won the right to destroy

deliberately even its most inferior vital products in

the womb. A

civilization guilty of so reckless a waste of life

cannot safely be

entrusted with this judicial function. The blind and

aimless anxiety to

cherish the most hopeless and degraded forms of life,

even of unborn life,

may well be a weakness, and since it often leads to

incalculable

suffering, even a crime. But as yet there is an

impenetrable barrier

against progress in this direction. Before we are

entitled to take life

deliberately for the sake of purifying life, we must

learn how to preserve

it by abolishing such destructive influences--war,

disease, bad industrial

conditions--as are easily within our social power as

civilized

nations.[443]

There is, further, another consideration which seems to me to carry

weight. The progress of civilization is in the direction of greater

foresight, of greater prevention, of a diminished need for struggling with

the reckless lack of prevision. The necessity for

abortion is precisely

one of those results of reckless action which

civilization tends to

diminish. While we may admit that in a sounder state of civilization a few

cases might still occur when the induction of abortion would be desirable,

it seems probable that the number of such cases will

decrease rather than

increase. In order to do away with the need for

abortion, and to

counteract the propaganda in its favor, our main

reliance must be placed,

on the one hand, on increased foresight in the

determination of conception

and increased knowledge of the means for preventing

conception,[444] and

on the other hand, on a better provision by the State

for the care of

pregnant women, married and unmarried alike, and a

practical recognition

of the qualified mother's claim on society.[445] There can be little doubt

that, in many a charge of criminal abortion, the real

offence lies at the

door of those who have failed to exercise their social and professional

duty of making known the more natural and harmless

methods for preventing

conception, or else by their social attitude have made the pregnant

woman's position intolerable. By active social reform in these two

directions, the new movement in favor of abortion may be kept in check,

and it may even be found that by stimulating such reform that movement has

been beneficial.

We have seen that the deliberate restraint of conception has become a part

of our civilized morality, and that the practice and

theory of facultative

abortion has gained a footing among us. There remains a third and yet more

radical method of controlling procreation, the method of preventing the

possibility of procreation altogether by the performance of castration or

other slighter operation having a like inhibitory effect on reproduction.

The other two methods only effect a single act of union or its results,

but castration affects all subsequent acts of sexual

union and usually

destroys the procreative power permanently.

Castration for various social and other purposes is an ancient and

widespread practice, carried out on men and on animals.

There has,

however, been on the whole a certain prejudice against it when applied to

men. Many peoples have attached a very sacred value to the integrity of

the sexual organs. Among some primitive peoples the

removal of these

organs has been regarded as a peculiarly ferocious

insult, only to be

carried out in moments of great excitement, as after a battle. Medicine

has been opposed to any interference with the sexual

organs. The oath

taken by the Greek physicians appears to prohibit

castration: "I will not

cut."[446] In modern times a great change has taken place, the castration

of both men and women is commonly performed in diseased conditions; the

same operation is sometimes advocated and occasionally performed in the

hope that it may remove strong and abnormal sexual

impulses. And during

recent years castration has been invoked in the cause of negative

eugenics, to a greater extent, indeed, on account of its more radical

character, than either the prevention of conception or abortion.

The movement in favor of castration appears to have

begun in the United

States, where various experiments have been made in

embodying it in law.

It was first advocated merely as a punishment for

criminals, and

especially sexual offenders, by Hammond, Everts, Lydston and others. From

this point of view, however, it seems to be

unsatisfactory and perhaps

illegitimate. In many cases castration is no punishment at all, and indeed

a positive benefit. In other cases, when inflicted

against the subject's

will, it may produce very disturbing mental effects,

leading in already

degenerate or unbalanced persons to insanity,

criminality, and anti-social

tendencies generally, much more dangerous than the

original state.

Eugenic considerations, which were later brought

forward, constitute a

much sounder argument for castration; in this case the castration is

carried out, by no means in order to inflict a barbarous and degrading

punishment, but, with the subject's consent, in order to protect the

community from the risk of useless or mischievous

members.

The fact that castration can no longer be properly

considered a

punishment, is shown by the possibility of

deliberately seeking

the operation simply for the sake of convenience, as

a preferable

and most effective substitute for the adoption of

preventive

methods in sexual intercourse. I am only at present

acquainted

with one case in which this course has been adopted.

This subject

is a medical man (of Puritan New England ancestry)

with whose

sexual history, which is quite normal, I have been

acquainted for

a long time past. His present age is thirty-nine. A

few years

since, having a sufficiently large family, he

adopted preventive

methods of intercourse. The subsequent events I

narrate in his

own words: "The trouble, forethought, etc., rendered necessary by

preventive measures, grew more and more irksome to

me as the

years passed by, and finally, I laid the matter

before another

physician, and on his assurances, and after mature

deliberation

with my wife, was operated on some time since, and

rendered

sterile by having the