Studies in the psychology of sex, volume VI. Sex in Relation to Society by Havelock Ellis. - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

at one with

the most recent biometrical eugenists of to-day

("the nation has

for years been putting its money on 'Environment,'

when

'Heredity' wins in a canter," as Karl Pearson

prefers to put it),

and at the same time revealed the breadth of his

vision in

comparison with the ordinary social reformer, who,

in that day,

was usually a fanatical believer in the influence of

training and

surroundings. Noyes sets forth the position of

Darwin on the

principles of breeding, and the step beyond Darwin,

which had

been taken by Galton. He then remarks that, when

Galton comes to

the point where it is necessary to advance from

theory to the

duties the theory suggests, he "subsides into the meekest

conservatism." (It must be remembered that this was written at an

early stage in Galton's work.) This conclusion was

entirely

opposed to Noyes' practical and religious

temperament. "Duty is

plain; we say we ought to do it--we want to do it;

but we cannot.

The law of God urges us on; but the law of society

holds us back.

The boldest course is the safest. Let us take an

honest and

steady look at the law. It is only in the timidity

of ignorance

that the duty seems impracticable." Noyes

anticipated Galton in

regarding eugenics as a matter of religion.

Noyes proposed to term the work of modern science in

propagation

"Stirpiculture," in which he has sometimes been followed by

others. He considered that it is the business of the

stirpiculturist to keep in view both quantity and

quality of

stocks, and he held that, without diminishing

quantity, it was

possible to raise the quality by exercising a very

stringent

discrimination in selecting males. At this point,

Noyes has been

supported in recent years by Karl Pearson and

others, who have

shown that only a relatively small portion of a

population is

needed to produce the next generation, and that, in

fact, twelve

per cent. of one generation in man produces fifty

per cent. of

the next generation. What we need to ensure is that

this small

reproducing section of the population shall be the

best adapted

for the purpose. "The _quantity_ of production will be in direct

proportion to the number of fertile females," as

Noyes saw the

question, "and the _value_ produced, so far as it depends on

selection, will be nearly in inverse proportion to

the number of

fertilizing males." In this matter, Noyes

anticipated Ehrenfels.

The two principles to be held in mind were, "Breed from the

best," and "Breed in-and-in," with a cautious and occasional

introduction of new strains. (It may be noted that

Reibmayr, in

his recent _Entwicklungsgeschichte des Genics und

Talentes_,

argues that the superior races, and superior

individuals, in the

human species, have been produced by an unconscious

adherence to

exactly these principles.) "By segregating superior families, and

by breeding these in-and-in, superior varieties of

human beings

might be produced, which would be comparable to the

thoroughbreds

in all the domestic races." He illustrates this by the early

history of the Jews.

Noyes finally criticises the present method, or lack

of method,

in matters of propagation. Our marriage system, he

states,

"leaves mating to be determined by a general

scramble." By

ignoring, also, the great difference between the

sexes in

reproductive power, it "restricts each man, whatever may be his

potency and his value, to the amount of production

of which one

woman, chosen blindly, may be capable." Moreover, he continues,

"practically it discriminates against the best, and in favor of

the worst; for, while the good man will be limited

by his

conscience to what the law allows, the bad man, free

from moral

check, will distribute his seed beyond the legal

limits, as

widely as he dares." "We are safe every way in saying that there

is no possibility of carrying the two precepts of

scientific

propagation into an institution which pretends to no

discrimination, allows no suppression, gives no more

liberty to

the best than to the worst, and which, in fact, must

inevitably

discriminate the wrong way, so long as the inferior

classes are

most prolific and least amenable to the admonitions

of science

and morality." In modifying our sexual institutions, Noyes

insists there are two essential points to remember:

the

preservation of liberty, and the preservation of the

home. There

must be no compulsion about human scientific

propagation; it must

be autonomous, directed by self-government, "by the free choice

of those who love science well enough to 'make

themselves eunuchs

for the Kingdom of Heaven's sake.'" The home, also, must be

preserved, since "marriage is the best thing for man as he is;"

but it is necessary to enlarge the home, for, "if all could learn

to love other children than their own, there would

be nothing to

hinder scientific propagation in the midst of homes

far better

than any that now exist."

This memorable pamphlet contains no exposition of

the precise

measures adopted by the Oneida Community to carry

out these

principles. The two essential points were, as we

know, "male

continence" (see _ante_ p. 553), and the enlarged family, in

which all the men were the actual or potential mates

of all the

women, but no union for propagation took place,

except as the

result of reason and deliberate resolve. "The

community," says

H.J. Seymour, one of the original members (_The

Oneida

Community_, 1894, p. 5), "was a _family_, as

distinctly separated

from surrounding society as ordinary households. The

tie that

bound it together was as permanent, and at least as

sacred, as

that of marriage. Every man's care, and the whole of

the common

property, was pledged for the maintenance and

protection of the

women, and the support and education of the

children." It is not

probable that the Oneida Community presented in

detail the model

to which human society generally will conform. But

even at the

lowest estimate, its success showed, as Lord Morely

has pointed

out (_Diderot_, vol. ii, p. 19), "how modifiable are some of

these facts of existing human character which are

vulgarly deemed

to be ultimate and ineradicable," and that "the discipline of the

appetites and affections of sex," on which the

future of

civilization largely rests, is very far from an

impossibility.

In many respects, the Oneida Community was ahead of

its

time,--and even of ours,--but it is interesting to

note that, in

the matter of the control of conception, our

marriage system has

come into line with the theory and practice of

Oneida; it cannot,

indeed, be said that we always control conception in

accordance

with eugenic principles, but the fact that such

control has now

become a generally accepted habit of civilization,

to some extent

deprives Noyes' criticism of our marriage system of

the force it

possessed half a century ago. Another change in our

customs--the

advocacy, and even the practice, of abortion and

castration--would not have met with his approval; he

was strongly

opposed to both, and with the high moral level that

ruled his

community, neither was necessary to the maintenance

of the

stirpiculture that prevailed.

The Oneida Community endured for the space of one

generation, and

came to an end in 1879, by no means through a

recognition of

failure, but by a wise deference to external

pressure. Its

members, many of them highly educated, continued to

cherish the

memory of the practices and ideals of the Community.

Noyes Miller

(the author of _The Strike of a Sex_, and

_Zugassant's

Discovery_) to the last, looked with quiet

confidence to the time

when, as he anticipated, the great discovery of

Noyes would be

accepted and adopted by the world at large. Another

member of the

Community (Henry J. Seymour) wrote of the Community

long

afterwards that "It was an anticipation and

imperfect miniature

of the Kingdom of Heaven on earth."

Perhaps the commonest type of proposal or attempt to

improve the

biological level of the race is by the exclusion of

certain classes of

degenerates from marriage, or by the encouragement of

better classes of

the community to marry. This seems to be, at present,

the most popular

form of eugenics, and in so far as it is not effected by compulsion but is

the outcome of a voluntary resolve to treat the question of the creation

of the race with the jealous care and guardianship which so tremendously

serious, so godlike, a task involves, it has much to be said in its favor

and nothing against it.

But it is quite another matter when the attempt is made to regulate such

an institution as marriage by law. In the first place we do not yet know

enough about the principles of heredity and the

transmissibility of

pathological states to enable us to formulate sound

legislative proposals

on this basis. Even so comparatively simple a matter as the relationship

of tuberculosis to heredity can scarcely be said to be a matter of common

agreement, even if it can yet be claimed that we possess adequate material

on which to attain a common agreement. Supposing,

moreover, that our

knowledge on all these questions were far more advanced than it is, we

still should not have attained a position in which we

could lay down

general propositions regarding the desirability or the undesirability of

certain classes of persons procreating. The question is necessarily an

individual question, and it can only be decided when all the circumstances

of the individual case have been fairly passed in

review.

The objection to any legislative and compulsory

regulation of the right to

marry is, however, much more fundamental than the

consideration that our

knowledge is at present inadequate. It lies in the

extraordinary

confusion, in the minds of those who advocate such

legislation, between

legal marriage and procreation. The persons who fall

into such confusion

have not yet learnt the alphabet of the subject they

presume to dictate

about, and are no more competent to legislate than a

child who cannot tell

A from B is competent to read.

Marriage, in so far as it is the partnership for mutual help and

consolation of two people who in such partnership are

free, if they

please, to exercise sexual union, is an elementary right of every person

who is able to reason, who is guilty of no fraud or

concealment, and who

is not likely to injure the partner selected, for in

that case society is

entitled to interfere by virtue of its duty to protect its members. But

the right to marry, thus understood, in no way involves the right to

procreate. For while marriage _per se_ only affects the two individuals

concerned, and in no way affects the State, procreation, on the other

hand, primarily affects the community which is

ultimately made up of

procreated persons, and only secondarily affects the two individuals who

are the instruments of procreation. So that just as the individual couple

has the first right in the question of marriage, the

State has the first

right in the question of procreation. The State is just as incompetent to

lay down the law about marriage as the individual is to lay down the law

about procreation.

That, however, is only one-half of the folly committed by those who would

select the candidates for matrimony by statute. Let us suppose--as is not

indeed easy to suppose--that a community will meekly

accept the abstract

prohibitions of the statute book and quietly go home

again when the

registrar of marriages informs them that they are shut out from legal

matrimony by the new table of prohibited degrees. An

explicit prohibition

to procreate within marriage is an implicit permission to procreate

outside marriage. Thus the undesirable procreation,

instead of being

carried out under the least dangerous conditions, is

carried out under the

most dangerous conditions, and the net result to the

community is not a

gain but a loss.

What seems usually to happen, in the presence of a

formal legislative

prohibition against the marriage of a particular class, is a combination

of various evils. In part the law becomes a dead letter, in part it is

evaded by skill and fraud, in part it is obeyed to give rise to worse

evils. This happened, for instance, in the Terek

district of the Caucasus

where, on the demand of a medical committee, priests

were prohibited from

marrying persons among whose relatives or ancestry any cases of leprosy

had occurred. So much and such various mischief was

caused by this order

that it was speedily withdrawn.[452]

If we remember that the Catholic Church was occupied for more than a

thousand years in the attempt to impose the prohibition of marriage on its

priesthood,--an educated and trained body of men, who

had every spiritual

and worldly motive to accept the prohibition, and were, moreover, brought

up to regard asceticism as the best ideal in life,[453]-

-we may realize

how absurd it is to attempt to gain the same end by mere casual

prohibitions issued to untrained people with no motives to obey such

prohibitions, and no ideals of celibacy.

The hopelessness and even absurdity of effecting the

eugenic improvement

of the race by merely placing on the statute book

prohibitions to certain

classes of people to enter the legal bonds of matrimony as at present

constituted, reveals the weakness of those who

undervalue the eugenic

importance of environment. Those who affirm that

heredity is everything

and environment nothing seem strangely to forget that it is precisely the

lower classes--those who are most subjected to the

influence of bad

environment--who procreate most copiously, most

recklessly, and most

disastrously. The restraint of procreation, and a

concomitant regard for

heredity, increase _pari passu_ with improvement of the environment and

rise in social well-being. If even already it can be

said that probably

fifty per cent. of sexual intercourse--perhaps the most procreatively

productive moiety--takes place outside legal marriage, it becomes obvious

that statutory prohibition to the unfit classes to

refrain from legal

marriage merely involves their joining the procreating classes outside

legal matrimony. It is also clear that if we are to

neglect the factor of

environment, and leave the lower social classes to the ignorance and

recklessness which are the result of such environment, the only practical

method of eugenics left open is that by castration and abortion. But this

method--if applied on a wholesale scale as it would need to be[454] and

without reference to the consent of the individual--is entirely opposed

to modern democratic feeling. Thus those short-sighted eugenists who

overlook the importance of environment are overlooking the only practical

channel through which their aims can be realized.

Attention to procreation

and attention to environment are not, as some have

supposed, antagonistic,

but they play harmoniously into each other's hands. The care for

environment leads to a restraint on reckless

procreation, and the

restraint of procreation leads to improved environment.

Legislation on marriage, to be effectual, must be

enacted in the home, in

the school, in the doctor's consulting room. Force is

helpless here; it is

education that is needed, not merely instruction, but

the education of the

conscience and will, and the training of the emotions.

Legal action may come in to further this process of

education, though it

cannot replace it. Thus it is very desirable that when there has been a

concealment of serious disease by a party to a marriage such concealment

should be a ground for divorce. Epilepsy may be taken as typical of the

diseases which should be a bar to procreation, and their concealment

equivalent to an annulment of marriage.[455] In the

United States the

Supreme Court of Errors of Connecticut laid it down in 1906 that the

Superior Court has the power to pass a decree of divorce when one of the

parties has concealed the existence of epilepsy. This

weighty deliverence,

it has been well said,[456] marks a forward step in

human progress. There

are many other seriously pathological conditions in

which divorce should

be pronounced, or indeed, occur automatically, except

when procreation has

been renounced, for in that case the State is no longer concerned in the

relationship, except to punish any fraud committed by

concealment.

The demand that a medical certificate of health

should be

compulsory on marriage, has been especially made in

France. In

1858, Diday, of Lyons, proposed, indeed, that all

persons,

without exception, should be compelled to possess a

certificate

of health and disease, a kind of sanitary passport.

In 1872,

Bertillon (Art. "Demographic," _Dictionnaire Encyclopédique des

Sciences Médicales_) advocated the registration, at

marriage, of

the chief anthropological and pathological traits of

the

contracting parties (height, weight, color of hair

and eyes,

muscular force, size of head, condition of vision,

hearing, etc.,

deformities and defects, etc.), not so much,

however, for the end

of preventing undesirable marriages, as to

facilitate the study

and comparison of human groups at particular

periods. Subsequent

demands, of a more limited and partial character,

for legal

medical certificates as a condition of marriage,

have been made

by Fournier (_Syphilis et Mariage_, 1890), Cazalis

(_Le Science

et le Mariage_, 1890), and Jullien (_Blenorrhagie et

Mariage_,

1898). In Austria, Haskovec, of Prague ("Contrat

Matrimonial et

L'Hygiène Publique," _Comptes-rendus Congrès

International de

Médecine_, Lisbon, 1906, Section VII, p. 600),

argues that, on

marriage, a medical certificate should be presented,

showing that

the subject is exempt from tuberculosis, alcoholism,

syphilis,

gonorrhoea, severe mental, or nervous, or other

degenerative

state, likely to be injurious to the other partner,

or to the

offspring. In America, Rosenberg and Aronstam argue

that every

candidate for marriage, male or female, should

undergo a strict

examination by a competent board of medical

examiners, concerning

(1) Family and Past History (syphilis, consumption,

alcoholism,

nervous, and mental diseases), and (2) Status

Presens (thorough

examination of all the organs); if satisfactory, a

certificate of

matrimonial eligibility would then be granted. It is

pointed out

that a measure of this kind would render unnecessary

the acts

passed by some States for the punishment by fine, or

imprisonment, of the concealment of disease. Ellen

Key also

considers (_Liebe und Ehe_, p. 436) that each party

at marriage

should produce a certificate of health. "It seems to me just as

necessary," she remarks, elsewhere (_Century of the Child_, Ch.

I), "to demand medical testimony concerning capacity for

marriage, as concerning capacity for military

service. In the one

case, it is a matter of giving life; in the other,

of taking it,

although certainly the latter occasion has hitherto

been

considered as much the more serious."

The certificate, as usually advocated, would be a

private but

necessary legitimation of the marriage in the eyes

of the civil

and religious authorities. Such a step, being

required for the

protection alike of the conjugal partner and of

posterity, would

involve a new legal organization of the matrimonial

contract.

That such demands are so frequently made, is a

significant sign

of the growth of moral consciousness in the

community, and it is

good that the public should be made acquainted with

the urgent

need for them. But it is highly undesirable that

they should, at

present, or, perhaps, ever, be embodied in legal

codes. What is

needed is the cultivation of the feeling of

individual

responsibility, and the development of social

antagonism towards

those individuals who fail to recognize their

responsibility. It

is the reality of marriage,