The AntiChrist by F. W. Nietzsche - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

PREFACE

This book belongs to the most rare of men. Perhaps not one of them is yet alive. It is possible that they may be among

those who understand my "Zarathustra": how could I confound myself with those who are now sprouting ears?—First the

day after tomorrow must come for me. Some men are born posthumously.

The conditions under which any one understands me, and necessarily understands me—I know them only too well.

Even to endure my seriousness, my passion, he must carry intellectual integrity to the verge of hardness. He must be

accustomed to living on mountain tops—and to looking upon the wretched gabble of politics and nationalism as beneath

him. He must have become indifferent; he must never ask of the truth whether it brings profit to him or a fatality to him…

He must have an inclination, born of strength, for questions that no one has the courage for; the courage for the

forbidden; predestination for the labyrinth. The experience of seven solitudes. New ears for new music. New eyes for

what is most distant. A new conscience for truths that have hitherto remained unheard. And the will to economize in the

grand manner—to hold together his strength, his enthusiasm… Reverence for self; love of self; absolute freedom of

self…

Very well, then! of that sort only are my readers, my true readers, my readers foreordained: of what account are the

rest?—The rest are merely humanity.—One must make one’s self superior to humanity, in power, in loftiness of soul,—in

contempt.

FRIEDRICH W. NIETZSCHE.

1.

—Let us look each other in the face. We are Hyperboreans—we know well enough how remote our place is. "Neither by

land nor by water will you find the road to the Hyperboreans": even Pindar,[ 1 i ]

n his day, knew that much about us.

Beyond the North, beyond the ice, beyond death—our life, our happiness… We have discovered that happiness; we

know the way; we got our knowledge of it from thousands of years in the labyrinth. Who else has found it?—The man of

today?—"I don’t know either the way out or the way in; I am whatever doesn’t know either the way out or the way in"—so

sighs the man of today… This is the sort of modernity that made us ill,—we sickened on lazy peace, cowardly

compromise, the whole virtuous dirtiness of the modern Yea and Nay. This tolerance and largeur of the heart that

"forgives" everything because it "understands" everything is a sirocco to us. Rather live amid the ice than among modern

virtues and other such south–winds!… We were brave enough; we spared neither ourselves nor others; but we were a

long time finding out where to direct our courage. We grew dismal; they called us fatalists. Our fate—it was the fulness,

the tension, the storing up of powers. We thirsted for the lightnings and great deeds; we kept as far as possible from the

happiness of the weakling, from "resignation"… There was thunder in our air; nature, as we embodied it, became

overcast—for we had not yet found the way. The formula of our happiness: a Yea, a Nay, a straight line, a goal…

2.

What is good?—Whatever augments the feeling of power, the will to power, power itself, in man.

What is evil?—Whatever springs from weakness.

What is happiness?—The feeling that power increases—that resistance is overcome.

Not contentment, but more power; not peace at any price, but war; not virtue, but efficiency (virtue in the Renaissance

sense, virtu, virtue free of moral acid).

The weak and the botched shall perish: first principle of our charity. And one should help them to it.

What is more harmful than any vice?—Practical sympathy for the botched and the weak—Christianity…

3.

The problem that I set here is not what shall replace mankind in the order of living creatures (—man is an end—): but

what type of man must be bred, must be willed, as being the most valuable, the most worthy of life, the most secure

guarantee of the future.

This more valuable type has appeared often enough in the past: but always as a happy accident, as an exception,

never as deliberately willed. Very often it has been precisely the most feared; hitherto it has been almost the terror of

terrors;—and out of that terror the contrary type has been willed, cultivated and attained: the domestic animal, the herd

animal, the sick brute–man—the Christian…

4.

Mankind surely does not represent an evolution toward a better or stronger or higher level, as progress is now

understood. This "progress" is merely a modern idea, which is to say, a false idea. The European of today, in his

essential worth, falls far below the European of the Renaissance; the process of evolution does not necessarily mean

elevation, enhancement, strengthening.

True enough, it succeeds in isolated and individual cases in various parts of the earth and under the most widely

different cultures, and in these cases a higher type certainly manifests itself; something which, compared to mankind in

the mass, appears as a sort of superman. Such happy strokes of high success have always been possible, and will

remain possible, perhaps, for all time to come. Even whole races, tribes and nations may occasionally represent such

lucky accidents.

5.

We should not deck out and embellish Christianity: it has waged a war to the death against this higher type of man, it has

put all the deepest instincts of this type under its ban, it has developed its concept of evil, of the Evil One himself, out of

these instincts—the strong man as the typical reprobate, the "outcast among men." Christianity has taken the part of all

the weak, the low, the botched; it has made an ideal out of antagonism to all the self–preservative instincts of sound life;

it has corrupted even the faculties of those natures that are intellectually most vigorous, by representing the highest

intellectual values as sinful, as misleading, as full of temptation. The most lamentable example: the corruption of Pascal,

who believed that his intellect had been destroyed by original sin, whereas it was actually destroyed by Christianity!—

6.

It is a painful and tragic spectacle that rises before me: I have drawn back the curtain from the rottenness of man. This

word, in my mouth, is at least free from one suspicion: that it involves a moral accusation against humanity. It is used—

and I wish to emphasize the fact again—without any moral significance: and this is so far true that the rottenness I speak

of is most apparent to me precisely in those quarters where there has been most aspiration, hitherto, toward "virtue" and

"godliness." As you probably surmise, I understand rottenness in the sense of décadence: my argument is that all the

values on which mankind now fixes its highest aspirations are décadence–values.

I call an animal, a species, an individual corrupt, when it loses its instincts, when it chooses, when it prefers, what is

injurious to it. A history of the "higher feelings," the "ideals of humanity"—and it is possible that I’ll have to write it—would

almost explain why man is so degenerate. Life itself appears to me as an instinct for growth, for survival, for the

accumulation of forces, for power: whenever the will to power fails there is disaster. My contention is that all the highest

values of humanity have been emptied of this will—that the values of décadence, of nihilism, now prevail under the

holiest names.

7.

Christianity is called the religion of pity.—Pity stands in opposition to all the tonic passions that augment the energy of

the feeling of aliveness: it is a depressant. A man loses power when he pities. Through pity that drain upon strength

which suffering works is multiplied a thousandfold. Suffering is made contagious by pity; under certain circumstances it

may lead to a total sacrifice of life and living energy—a loss out of all proportion to the magnitude of the cause (—the

case of the death of the Nazarene). This is the first view of it; there is, however, a still more important one. If one

measures the effects of pity by the gravity of the reactions it sets up, its character as a menace to life appears in a much

clearer light. Pity thwarts the whole law of evolution, which is the law of natural selection. It preserves whatever is ripe for

destruction; it fights on the side of those disinherited and condemned by life; by maintaining life in so many of the

botched of all kinds, it gives life itself a gloomy and dubious aspect. Mankind has ventured to call pity a virtue (—in every

superior moral system it appears as a weakness—); going still further, it has been called the virtue, the source and

foundation of all other virtues—but let us always bear in mind that this was from the standpoint of a philosophy that was

nihilistic, and upon whose shield the denial of life was inscribed. Schopenhauer was right in this: that by means of pity

life is denied, and made worthy of denial—pity is the technic of nihilism. Let me repeat: this depressing and contagious

instinct stands against all those instincts which work for the preservation and enhancement of life: in the rôle of protector

of the miserable, it is a prime agent in the promotion of décadence—pity persuades to extinction… Of course, one

doesn’t say "extinction": one says "the other world," or "God," or "the true life," or Nirvana, salvation, blessedness… This

innocent rhetoric, from the realm of religious–ethical balderdash, appears a good deal less innocent when one reflects

upon the tendency that it conceals beneath sublime words: the tendency to destroy life. Schopenhauer was hostile to

life: that is why pity appeared to him as a virtue… Aristotle, as every one knows, saw in pity a sickly and dangerous state

of mind, the remedy for which was an occasional purgative: he regarded tragedy as that purgative. The instinct of life

should prompt us to seek some means of puncturing any such pathological and dangerous accumulation of pity as that

appearing in Schopenhauer’s case (and also, alack, in that of our whole literary décadence, from St. Petersburg to Paris,

from Tolstoi to Wagner), that it may burst and be discharged… Nothing is more unhealthy, amid all our unhealthy

modernism, than Christian pity. To be the doctors here, to be unmerciful here, to wield the knife here—all this is our

business, all this is our sort of humanity, by this sign we are philosophers, we Hyperboreans!—

8.

It is necessary to say just whom we regard as our antagonists: theologians and all who have any theological blood in

their veins—this is our whole philosophy… One must have faced that menace at close hand, better still, one must have

had experience of it directly and almost succumbed to it, to realize that it is not to be taken lightly (—the alleged free–

thinking of our naturalists and physiologists seems to me to be a joke—they have no passion about such things; they

have not suffered—). This poisoning goes a great deal further than most people think: I find the arrogant habit of the

theologian among all who regard themselves as "idealists"—among all who, by virtue of a higher point of departure, claim

a right to rise above reality, and to look upon it with suspicion… The idealist, like the ecclesiastic, carries all sorts of lofty

concepts in his hand (—and not only in his hand!); he launches them with benevolent contempt against

"understanding,""the senses,""honor,""good living,""science"; he sees such things as beneath him, as pernicious and

seductive forces, on which "the soul" soars as a pure thing–in–itself—as if humility, chastity, poverty, in a word, holiness,

had not already done much more damage to life than all imaginable horrors and vices… The pure soul is a pure lie… So

long as the priest, that professional denier, calumniator and poisoner of life, is accepted as a higher variety of man, there

can be no answer to the question, What is truth? Truth has already been stood on its head when the obvious attorney of

mere emptiness is mistaken for its representative…

9.

Upon this theological instinct I make war: I find the tracks of it everywhere. Whoever has theological blood in his veins is

shifty and dishonourable in all things. The pathetic thing that grows out of this condition is called faith: in other words,

closing one’s eyes upon one’s self once for all, to avoid suffering the sight of incurable falsehood. People erect a

concept of morality, of virtue, of holiness upon this false view of all things; they ground good conscience upon faulty

vision; they argue that no other sort of vision has value any more, once they have made theirs sacrosanct with the

names of "God,""salvation" and "eternity." I unearth this theological instinct in all directions: it is the most widespread and

the most subterranean form of falsehood to be found on earth. Whatever a theologian regards as true must be false:

there you have almost a criterion of truth. His profound instinct of self–preservation stands against truth ever coming into

honour in any way, or even getting stated. Wherever the influence of theologians is felt there is a transvaluation of

values, and the concepts "true" and "false" are forced to change places: whatever is most damaging to life is there called

"true," and whatever exalts it, intensifies it, approves it, justifies it and makes it triumphant is there called "false."… When

theologians, working through the "consciences" of princes (or of peoples—), stretch out their hands for power, there is

never any doubt as to the fundamental issue: the will to make an end, the nihilistic will exerts that power…

10.

Among Germans I am immediately understood when I say that theological blood is the ruin of philosophy. The Protestant

pastor is the grandfather of German philosophy; Protestantism itself is its peccatum originale. Definition of Protestantism:

hemiplegic paralysis of Christianity—and of reason… One need only utter the words "Tübingen School" to get an

understanding of what German philosophy is at bottom—a very artful form of theology… The Suabians are the best liars

in Germany; they lie innocently… Why all the rejoicing over the appearance of Kant that went through the learned world

of Germany, three–fourths of which is made up of the sons of preachers and teachers—why the German conviction still

echoing, that with Kant came a change for the better? The theological instinct of German scholars made them see clearly

just what had become possible again… A backstairs leading to the old ideal stood open; the concept of the "true world,"

the concept of morality as the essence of the world (—the two most vicious errors that ever existed!), were once more,

thanks to a subtle and wily scepticism, if not actually demonstrable, then at least no longer refutable… Reason, the

prerogative of reason, does not go so far… Out of reality there had been made "appearance"; an absolutely false world,

that of being, had been turned into reality… The success of Kant is merely a theological success; he was, like Luther

and Leibnitz, but one more impediment to German integrity, already far from steady.—

11.

A word now against Kant as a moralist. A virtue must be our invention; it must spring out of our personal need and

defence. In every other case it is a source of danger. That which does not belong to our life menaces it; a virtue which

has its roots in mere respect for the concept of "virtue," as Kant would have it, is pernicious. "Virtue,""duty,""good for its

own sake," goodness grounded upon impersonality or a notion of universal validity—these are all chimeras, and in them

one finds only an expression of the decay, the last collapse of life, the Chinese spirit of Königsberg. Quite the contrary is

demanded by the most profound laws of self–preservation and of growth: to wit, that every man find his own virtue, his

own categorical imperative. A nation goes to pieces when it confounds its duty with the general concept of duty. Nothing

works a more complete and penetrating disaster than every "impersonal" duty, every sacrifice before the Moloch of

abstraction.—To think that no one has thought of Kant’s categorical imperative as dangerous to life!… The theological

instinct alone took it under protection!—An action prompted by the life–instinct proves that it is a right action by the

amount of pleasure that goes with it: and yet that Nihilist, with his bowels of Christian dogmatism, regarded pleasure as

an objection… What destroys a man more quickly than to work, think and feel without inner necessity, without any deep

personal desire, without pleasure—as a mere automaton of duty? That is the recipe for décadence, and no less for

idiocy… Kant became an idiot.—And such a man was the contemporary of Goethe! This calamitous spinner of cobwebs

passed for the German philosopher—still passes today!… I forbid myself to say what I think of the Germans… Didn’t

Kant see in the French Revolution the transformation of the state from the inorganic form to the organic? Didn’t he ask

himself if there was a single event that could be explained save on the assumption of a moral faculty in man, so that on

the basis of it, "the tendency of mankind toward the good" could be explained, once and for all time? Kant’s answer:

"That is revolution." Instinct at fault in everything and anything, instinct as a revolt against nature, German décadence as

a philosophy—that is Kant!—

12.

I put aside a few sceptics, the types of decency in the history of philosophy: the rest haven’t the slightest conception of

intellectual integrity. They behave like women, all these great enthusiasts and prodigies—they regard "beautiful feelings"

as arguments, the "heaving breast" as the bellows of divine inspiration, conviction as the criterion of truth. In the end,

with "German" innocence, Kant tried to give a scientific flavour to this form of corruption, this dearth of intellectual

conscience, by calling it "practical reason." He deliberately invented a variety of reasons for use on occasions when it

was desirable not to trouble with reason—that is, when morality, when the sublime command "thou shalt," was heard.

When one recalls the fact that, among all peoples, the philosopher is no more than a development from the old type of

priest, this inheritance from the priest, this fraud upon self, ceases to be remarkable. When a man feels that he has a

divine mission, say to lift up, to save or to liberate mankind—when a man feels the divine spark in his heart and believes

that he is the mouthpiece of supernatural imperatives—when such a mission inflames him, it is only natural that he

should stand beyond all merely reasonable standards of judgment. He feels that he is himself sanctified by this mission,

that he is himself a type of a higher order!… What has a priest to do with philosophy! He stands far above it!—And

hitherto the priest has ruled!—He has determined the meaning of "true" and "not true"!…

13.

Let us not underestimate this fact: that we ourselves, we free spirits, are already a "transvaluation of all values," a

visualized declaration of war and victory against all the old concepts of "true" and "not true." The most valuable intuitions

are the last to be attained; the most valuable of all are those which determine methods. All the methods, all the principles

of the scientific spirit of today, were the targets for thousands of years of the most profound contempt; if a man inclined to

them he was excluded from the society of "decent" people—he passed as "an enemy of God," as a scoffer at the truth, as

one "possessed." As a man of science, he belonged to the Chandala[ 2 ]

… We have had the whole pathetic stupidity of

mankind against us—their every notion of what the truth ought to be, of what the service of the truth ought to be—their

every "thou shalt" was launched against us… Our objectives, our methods, our quiet, cautious, distrustful manner—all

appeared to them as absolutely discreditable and contemptible.—Looking back, one may almost ask one’s self with

reason if it was not actually an aesthetic sense that kept men blind so long: what they demanded of the truth was

picturesque effectiveness, and of the learned a strong appeal to their senses. It was our modesty that stood out longest

against their taste… How well they guessed that, these turkey–cocks of God!

14.

We have unlearned something. We have become more modest in every way. We no longer derive man from the "spirit,"

from the "godhead"; we have dropped him back among the beasts. We regard him as the strongest of the beasts

because he is the craftiest; one of the results thereof is his intellectuality. On the other hand, we guard ourselves against

a conceit which would assert itself even here: that man is the great second thought in the process of organic evolution.

He is, in truth, anything but the crown of creation: beside him stand many other animals, all at similar stages of

development… And even when we say that we say a bit too much, for man, relatively speaking, is the most botched of all

the animals and the sickliest, and he has wandered the most dangerously from his instincts—though for all that, to be

sure, he remains the most interesting!—As regards the lower animals, it was Descartes who first had the really admirable

daring to describe them as machina; the whole of our physiology is directed toward proving the truth of this doctrine.

Moreover, it is illogical to set man apart, as Descartes did: what we know of man today is limited precisely by the extent

to which we have regarded him, too, as a machine. Formerly we accorded to man, as his inheritance from some higher

order of beings, what was called "free will"; now we have taken even this will from him, for the term no longer describes

anything that we can understand. The old word "will" now connotes only a sort of result, an individual reaction, that

follows inevitably upon a series of partly discordant and partly harmonious stimuli—the will no longer "acts," or

"moves."… Formerly it was thought that man’s consciousness, his "spirit," offered evidence of his high origin, his divinity.

That he might be perfected, he was advised, tortoise–like, to draw his senses in, to have no traffic with earthly things, to

shuffle off his mortal coil—then only the important part of him, the "pure spirit," would remain. Here again we have

thought out the thing better: to us consciousness, or "the spirit," appears as a symptom of a relative imperfection of the

organism, as an experiment, a groping, a misunderstanding, as an affliction which uses up nervous force unnecessarily

—we deny that anything can be done perfectly so long as it is done consciously. The "pure spirit" is a piece of pure

stupidity: take away the nervous system and the senses, the so–called "mortal shell," and the rest is miscalculation—

that is all!…

15.

Under Christianity neither morality nor religion has any point of contact with actuality. It offers purely imaginary causes

("God,""soul,""ego,""spirit,""free

will"—or

even

"unfree"),

and

purely

imaginary effects

("sin,""salvation,""grace,""punishment,""forgiveness

of

sins").

Intercourse

between

imaginary beings

("God,""spirits,""souls"); an imaginary natural history (anthropocentric; a total denial of the concept of natural causes); an

imaginary psychology (misunderstandings of self, misinterpretations of agreeable or disagreeable general feelings—for

example, of the states of the nervus sympathicus with the help of the sign–language of religio–ethical balderdash—,

"repentance,""pangs of conscience,""temptation by the devil,""the presence of God"); an imaginary teleology (the

"kingdom of God,""the last judgment,""eternal life").—This purely fictitious world, greatly to its disadvantage, is to be

differentiated from the world of dreams; the latter at least reflects reality, whereas the former falsifies it, cheapens it and

denies it. Once the concept of "nature" had been opposed to the concept of "God," the word "natural" necessarily took on

the meaning of "abominable"—the whole of that fictitious world has its sources in hatred of the natural (—the real!—),

and is no more than evidence of a profound uneasiness in the presence of reality… This explains everything. Who alone

has any reason for living his way out of reality? The man who suffers under it. But to suffer from reality one must be a

botched reality… The preponderance of pains over pleasures is the cause of this fictitious morality and religion: but such

a preponderance also supplies the formula for décadence…

16.

A criticism of the Christian concept of God leads inevitably to the same conclusion.—A nation that still believes in itself

holds fast to its own god. In him it does honour to the conditions which enable it to survive, to its virtues—it projects its

joy in itself, its feeling of power, into a being to whom one may offer thanks. He who is rich will give of his riches; a proud

people need a god to whom they can make sacrifices… Religion, within these limits, is a form of gratitude. A man is

grateful for his own existence: to that end he needs a god.—Such a god must be able to work both benefits and injuries;

he must be able to play either friend or foe—he is wondered at for the good he does as well as for the evil he does. But