The Human Condition by Hannah Arendt - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

world of use things and fall back upon the subjectivity of use itself.

Only in a strictly anthropocentric world, where the user, that is,

man himself, becomes the ultimate end which puts a stop to the

unending chain of ends and means, can utility as such acquire the

dignity of meaningfulness. Yet the tragedy is that in the moment

homo faber seems to have found fulfilment in terms of his own ac-

tivity, he begins to degrade the world of things, the end and end

product of his own mind and hands; if man the user is the highest

end, "the measure of all things," then not only nature, treated by

homo faber as the almost "worthless material" upon which to

work, but the "valuable" things themselves have become mere

means, losing thereby their own intrinsic "value."

The anthropocentric utilitarianism of homo faber has found its

greatest expression in the Kantian formula that no man must ever

become a means to an end, that every human being is an end in

himself. Although we find earlier (for instance, in Locke's in-

sistence that no man can be permitted to possess another man's

body or use his bodily strength) an awareness of the fateful con-

sequences which an unhampered and unguided thinking in terms of

means and ends must invariably entail in the political realm, it is

only in Kant that the philosophy of the earlier stages of the modern

age frees itself entirely of the common sense platitudes which we

r i s s )

The Human Condition

always find where homo faber rules the standards of society. The

reason is, of course, that Kant did not mean to formulate or con-

ceptualize the tenets of the utilitarianism of his time, but on the

contrary wanted first of all to relegate the means-end category to

its proper place and prevent its use in the field of political action.

His formula, however, can no more deny its origin in utilitarian

thinking than his other famous and also inherently paradoxical in-

terpretation of man's attitude toward the only objects that are not

"for use," namely works of art, in which he said we take "pleasure

without any interest."20 For the same operation which establishes

man as the "supreme end" permits him "if he can [to] subject the

whole of nature to it,"21 that is, to degrade nature and the world

into mere means, robbing both of their independent dignity. Not

even Kant could solve the perplexity or enlighten the blindness of

homo faber with respect to the problem of meaning without turning

to the paradoxical "end in itself," and this perplexity lies in the

fact that while only fabrication with its instrumentality is capable

of building a world, this same world becomes as worthless as the

employed material, a mere means for further ends, if the standards

which governed its coming into being are permitted to rule it after

its establishment.

Man, in so far as he is homo faber, instrumentalizes, and his in-

strumentalization implies a degradation of all things into means,

their loss of intrinsic and independent value, so that eventually not

only the objects of fabrication but also "the earth in general and

all forces of nature," which clearly came into being without the

help of man and have an existence independent of the human world,

lose their "value because [they] do not present the reification

which comes from work."22 It was for no other reason than this

attitude of homo fa her to the world that the Greeks in their classical

period declared the whole field of the arts and crafts, where men

work with instruments and do something not for its own sake but

20. Kant's term is "ein Wohlgefallen ohne alles Interesse" (Kritik der Urteils-kraft [Cassirer ed.], V, 272).

21. Ibid., p. 515.

22. "Der Wasserfall, wie die Erde uberhaupt, wie alle Naturkraft hat keinen

Wert, weil er keine in ihm vergegenstandlichte Arbeit darstellt" (Das Kapital, HI [Marx-Engels Gesamtausgabe, Abt. II, Zurich, 1933], 698).

[ M ]

Work

in order to produce something else, to be banausic, a term perhaps

best translated by "philistine," implying vulgarity of thinking

and acting in terms of expediency. The vehemence of this contempt

will never cease to startle us if we realize that the great masters of

Greek sculpture and architecture were by no means excepted from

the verdict.

The issue at stake is, of course, not instrumentality, the use of

means to achieve an end, as such, but rather the generalization of

the fabrication experience in which usefulness and utility are estab-

lished as the ultimate standards for life and the world of men. This

generalization is inherent in the activity of homo jaber because the

experience of means and end, as it is present in fabrication, does

not disappear with the finished product but is extended to its

ultimate destination, which is to serve as a use object. The instru-

mentalization of the whole world and the earth, this limitless de-

valuation of everything given, this process of growing meaning-

lessness where every end is transformed into a means and which

can be stopped only by making man himself the lord and master of

all things, does not directly arise out of the fabrication process; for

from the viewpoint of fabrication the finished product is as much

an end in itself, an independent durable entity with an existence of

its own, as man is an end in himself in Kant's political philosophy.

Only in so far as fabrication chiefly fabricates use objects does the

finished product again become a means, and only in so far as the

life process takes hold of things and uses them for its purposes does

the productive and limited instrumentality of fabrication change

into the limitless instrumentalization of everything that exists.

It is quite obvious that the Greeks dreaded this devaluation of

world and nature with its inherent anthropocentrism—the "ab-

surd" opinion that man is the highest being and that everything

else is subject to the exigencies of human life (Aristotle)—no less

than they despised the sheer vulgarity of all consistent utilitarian-

ism. To what extent they were aware of the consequences of seeing

in homo jaber the highest human possibility is perhaps best illus-

trated by Plato's famous argument against Protagoras and his ap-

parently self-evident statement that "man is the measure of all use

things (chremata), of the existence of those that are, and of the non-

[ K7 ]

The Human Condition

existence of those that are not."23 (Protagoras evidently did not

say: "Man is the measure of all things," as tradition and the stand-

ard translations have made him say.) The point of the matter is

that Plato saw immediately that if one makes man the measure of

all things for use, it is man the user and instrumentalizer, and not

man the speaker and doer or man the thinker, to whom the world

is being related. And since it is in the nature of man the user and

instrumentalizer to look upon everything as means to an end—

upon every tree as potential wood—this must eventually mean

that man becomes the measure not only of things whose existence

depends upon him but of literally everything there is.

In this Platonic interpretation, Protagoras in fact sounds like the

earliest forerunner of Kant, for if man is the measure of all things,

then man is the only thing outside the means-end relationship, the

only end in himself who can use everything else as a means. Plato

knew quite well that the possibilities of producing use objects and

of treating all things of nature as potential use objects are as limit-

less as the wants and talents of human beings. If one permits the

standards of homo faber to rule the finished world as they must

necessarily rule the coming into being of this world, then homo

faber will eventually help himself to everything and consider every-

thing that is as a mere means for himself. He will judge every thing

as though it belonged to the class of chremata, of use objects, so

that, to follow Plato's own example, the wind will no longer be un-

derstood in its own right as a natural force but will be considered

exclusively in accordance with human needs for warmth or refresh-

ment—which, of course, means that the wind as something objec-

tively given has been eliminated from human experience. It is be-

cause of these consequences that Plato, who at the end of his life

recalls once more in the Laws the saying of Protagoras, replies

with an almost paradoxical formula: not man—who because of his

23. Theaetetus 152, and Cratylus 385E. In these instances, as well as in other ancient quotations of the famous saying, Protagoras is always quoted as follows:

panton chrematon metron estin anthropos (see Diels, Fragmente der Vorsokratiker

[4th ed.; 1922], frag. Bl). The word chremata by no means signifies "all things,"

but specifically things used or needed or possessed by men. The supposed

Protagorean saying, "Man is the measure of all things," would be rendered in Greek rather as anthropos metron panton, corresponding for instance to Heraclitus'

polemos pater ponton ("strife is the father of all things").

[ 158 ]

Work

wants and talents wishes to use everything and therefore ends by

depriving all things of their intrinsic worth—-but "the god is the

measure [even] of mere use objects."24

22

T H E E X C H A N G E MARKET

Marx—in one of many asides which testify to his eminent histori-

cal sense—once remarked that Benjamin Franklin's definition of

man as a toolmaker is as characteristic of "Yankeedom," that is, of

the modern age, as the definition of man as a political animal was

for antiquity.26 The truth of this remark lies in the fact that the

modern age was as intent on excluding political man, that is, man

who acts and speaks, from its public realm as antiquity was on ex-

cluding homofaber. In both instances the exclusion was not a matter

of course, as was the exclusion of laborers and the propertyless

classes until their emancipation in the nineteenth century. The

modern age was of course perfectly aware that the political realm

was not always and need not necessarily be a mere function of

"society," destined to protect the productive, social side of human

nature through governmental administration; but it regarded ev-

erything beyond the enforcement of law and order as "idle talk"

and "vain-glory." The human capacity on which it based its claim

of the natural innate productivity of society was the unquestion-

able productivity of homo faber. Conversely, antiquity knew full

well types of human communities in which not the citizen of the

polis and not the res publica as such established and determined the content of the public realm, but where the public life of the ordinary man was restricted to "working for the people" at large,

that is, to being a demiourgos, a worker for the people as distin-

guished from an oiketes, a household laborer and therefore a slave.26

24. Laws 716D quotes the saying of Protagoras textually, except that for the word "man" (anthropos), "the god" (ho theos) appears.

25. Capital (Modern Library ed.), p. 358, n. 3.

26. Early medieval history, and particularly the history of the craft guilds,

offers a good illustration of the inherent truth in the ancient understanding of

laborers as household inmates, as against craftsmen, who were considered work-

ers for the people at large. For the "appearance [of the guilds] marks the second

[ /« ]

The Human Condition

The hallmark of these non-political communities was that their

public place, the agora, was not a meeting place of citizens, but a

market place where craftsmen could show and exchange their

products. In Greece, moreover, it was the ever-frustrated ambi-

tion of all tyrants to discourage the citizens from worrying about

public affairs, from idling their time away in unproductive ago-

reuein and politeuesthai, and to transform the agora into an assemblage of shops like the bazaars of oriental despotism. What char-

acterized these market places, and later characterized the medieval

cities' trade and craft districts, was that the display of goods for

sale was accompanied by a display of their production. "Con-

spicuous production" (if we may vary Veblen's term) is, in fact,

no less a trait of a society of producers than "conspicuous con-

sumption" is a characteristic of a laborers' society.

Unlike the animal laborans, whose social life is worldless and

herdlike and who therefore is incapable of building or inhabiting a

public, worldly realm, homo faber is fully capable of having a pub-

lic realm of his own, even though it may not be a political realm,

properly speaking. His public realm is the exchange market, where

he can show the products of his hand and receive the esteem which

is due him. This inclination to showmanship is closely connected

with and probably no less deeply rooted than the "propensity to

truck, barter and exchange one thing for another," which, accord-

ing to Adam Smith, distinguishes man from animal.27 The point

is that homo faber, the builder of the world and the producer of

things, can find his proper relationship to other people only by ex-

changing his products with theirs, because these products them-

stage in the history of industry, the transition from the family system to the

artisan or guild system. In the former there was no class of artisans properly so

called . . . because all the needs of a family or other domestic groups . . . were

satisfied by the labours of the members of the group itself" (W. J. Ashley, An Introduction to English Economic History and Theory [1931], p. 76).

In medieval German, the word Storer is an exact equivalent to the Greek word demiourgos. "Der griechische demiourgos heisst 'Storer', er geht beim Volk arbeiten, er geht auf die Stor." Stbr means demos ("people"). (See Jost Trier, "Arbeit und Gemeinschaft," Studium Generate, Vol. Ill, No. 11 [November, 1950].) 27. He adds rather emphatically: "Nobody ever saw a dog make a fair and

deliberate exchange of one bone for another with another dog" (Wealth of Nations

[Everyman's ed.]( I, 12).

[ 160 ]

Work

selves are always produced in isolation. The privacy which the

early modern age demanded as the supreme right of each member

of society was actually the guaranty of isolation, without which no

work can be produced. Not the onlookers and spectators on the

medieval market places, where the craftsman in his isolation was

exposed to the light of the public, but only the rise of the social

realm, where the others are not content with beholding, judging,

and admiring but wish to be admitted to the company of the crafts-

man and to participate as equals in the work process, threatened

the "splendid isolation" of the worker and eventually undermined

the very notions of competence and excellence. This isolation from

others is the necessary life condition for every mastership which

consists in being alone with the "idea," the mental image of the

thing to be. This mastership, unlike political forms of domination,

is primarily a mastery of things and material and not of people.

The latter, in fact, is quite secondary to the activity of craftsman-

ship, and the words "worker" and "master"— ouvrier and maitre—

were originally used synonymously.28

The only company that grows out of workmanship directly is in

the need of the master for assistants or in his wish to educate others

in his craft. But the distinction between his skill and the unskilled

help is temporary, like the distinction between adults and children.

There can be hardly anything more alien or even more destructive

to workmanship than teamwork, which actually is only a variety

of the division of labor and presupposes the "breakdown of opera-

tions into their simple constituent motions."29 The team, the multi-

28. E. Levasseur, Histoire des classes ouvrieres et de Vindustrie en France truant 1789 (1900): "Les mots maitre et ouvrier etaient encore pris comme synonymes au 14e siecle" (p. 564, n. 2), whereas "au 15e siecle ... la maitrise est devenue un titre auquel il n'est permis a tous d'aspirer" (p. 572). Originally, "le mot ouvrier s'appliquait d'ordinaire k quiconque ouvrait, faisait ouvrage, maitre ou valet" (p. 309). In the workshops themselves and outside them in social life,

there was no great distinction between the master or the owner of the shop and

the workers (p. 313). (See also Pierre Brizon, Histoire du travail et des travailkurs

[4th ed.; 1926], pp. 39 ff.)

29. Charles R, Walker and Robert H. Guest, The Man on the Assembly Line

(1952), p. 10. Adam Smith's famous description of this principle in pin-making

(op. cit., I, 4 ff.) shows clearly how machine work was preceded by the division of labor and derives its principle from it.

[ 161 ]

The Human Condition

headed subject of all production carried out according to the prin-

ciple of division of labor, possesses the same togetherness as the

parts which form the whole, and each attempt of isolation on the

part of the members of the team would be fatal to the production

itself. But it is not only this togetherness which the master and

workman lacks while actively engaged in production; the spe-

cifically political forms of being together with others, acting in

concert and speaking with each other, are completely outside the

range of his productivity. Only when he stops working and his

product is finished can he abandon his isolation.

Historically, the last public realm, the last meeting place which

is at least connected with the activity of homo faber, is the ex-

change market on which his products are displayed. The commer-

cial society, characteristic of the earlier stages of the modern age

or the beginnings of manufacturing capitalism, sprang from this

"conspicuous production" with its concomitant hunger for uni-

versal possibilities of truck and barter, and its end came with the

rise of labor and the labor society which replaced conspicuous pro-

duction and its pride with "conspicuous consumption" and its

concomitant vanity.

The people who met on the exchange market, to be sure, were

no longer the fabricators themselves, and they did not meet as

persons but as owners of commodities and exchange values, as

Marx abundantly pointed out. In a society where exchange of

products has become the chief public activity, even the laborers,

because they are confronted with "money or commodity owners,"

become proprietors, "owners of their labor power." It is only at

this point that Marx's famous self-alienation, the degradation of

men into commodities, sets in, and this degradation is characteristic

of labor's situation in a manufacturing society which judges men

not as persons but as producers, according to the quality of their

products. A laboring society, on the contrary, judges men accord-

ing to the functions they perform in the labor process; while labor

power in the eyes of homo faber is only the means to produce the

necessarily higher end, that is, either a use object or an object for

exchange, laboring society bestows upon labor power the same

higher value it reserves for the machine. In other words, this so-

ciety is only seemingly more "humane," although it is true that

[ 162 ]

___________________ Work

under its conditions the price of human labor rises to such an extent

that it may seem to be more valued and more valuable than any

given material or matter; in fact, it only foreshadows something

even more "valuable," namely, the smoother functioning of the

machine whose tremendous power of processing first standardizes

and then devaluates all things into consumer goods.

Commercial society, or capitalism in its earlier stages when it

was still possessed by a fiercely competitive and acquisitive spirit,

is still ruled by the standards of homo faber. When homo faber

comes out of his isolation, he appears as a merchant and trader and

establishes the exchange market in this capacity. This market

must exist prior to the rise of a manufacturing class, which then

produces exclusively for the market, that is, produces exchange

objects rather than use things. In this process from isolated crafts-

manship to manufacturing for the exchange market, the finished

end product changes its quality somewhat but not altogether. Dura-

bility, which alone determines if a thing can exist as a thing and

endure in the world as a distinct entity, remains the supreme cri-

terion, although it no longer makes a thing fit for use but rather fit

to "be stored up beforehand" for future exchange.30

This is the change in quality reflected in the current distinction

between use and exchange value, whereby the latter is related to

the former as the merchant and trader is related to the fabricator

and manufacturer. In so far as homo faber fabricates use objects, he

not only produces them in the privacy of isolation but also for the

privacy of usage, from which they emerge and appear in the public

realm when they become commodities in the exchange market. It

has frequently been remarked and unfortunately as frequently been

forgotten that value, being "an idea of proportion between the pos-

session of one thing and the possession of another in the conception

of man,"31 "always means value in exchange."32 For it is only in

the exchange market, where everything can be exchanged for

something else, that all things, whether they are products of labor

30. Adam Smith, op. cit., II, 241.

31. This definition was given by the Italian economist Abbey Galiani. I quote

from Hannah R. Sewall, The Theory of Value before Adam Smith (1901) ("Publications of the American Economic Association," 3d Ser., Vol. II, No. 3), p. 92.

32. Alfred Marshall, Principles of Economics (1920), I, 8.

[ 163 ]

The Human Condition

or work, consumer goods or use objects, necessary for the life of

the body or the convenience of living or the life of the rnind, be-

come "values." This value consists solely in the esteem of the

public realm where the things appear as commodities, and it is

neither labor, nor work, nor capital, nor profit, nor material,

which bestows such value upon an object, but only and exclusively

the public realm where it appears to be esteemed, demanded, or

neglected. Value is the quality a thing can never possess in privacy

but acquires automatica