The psychology of Nations by G.E. Partridge - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

CHAPTER VIII

RELIGIOUS AND MORAL INFLUENCES

That war and religion have always been closely associated with one

another is one of the outstanding facts of history. This is true both

of primitive warfare and of warfare to-day. Yet we cannot say that

religion as such has been a cause of war. Religious wars are almost

invariably also political wars, and as soon as religion and politics

are separated, religion no longer appears to be a war motive. When

religion becomes associated with worldly ideas which it supports and

makes dynamic it may become a strong factor in the spirit of war, but

as a means of segregating men, and giving them unity of action

religion can no longer be regarded as a power, if it ever was. Any

motive that will not so segregate men and break up all other bonds

cannot be said to be a very fertile cause of war.

Religion as a cause

of war belongs to a day in which the spirit of nationalism was weak,

and when religious empire had a visible and political position in the

world. Nationalism, growing stronger, became the supreme force

dominating the motives and interests of men and governing the

formation of groups, or at least the actions of groups as interrelated

units. In the recent war we have seen how the sense of national unity

has been able to hold in check all other motives.

Neither religion nor

any class or clan or guild interests could trace the faintest line of

cleavage so long as the motive of war remained.

The mood of war always contains a religious element. Not only is this

shown in primitive wars, where the relations of religion, war and art

are indicated in such phenomena as the war dance, which is of the

nature of a magic weapon, but we see it also in the complex moods of

the present war spirit of the world. The idea and mood of valor have a

religious significance. Cramb says that we can trace in Germany before

the war, showing through the transient mists of industrialism and

socialism, the vision of the religion of valor which runs through all

German history. The craving for a valorous life, for reality, the

desire to lose one's own individuality--these moods of war are

religious or mystic whatever else they may be or contain. The

inseparable relation of war and death necessarily inspires a religious

consciousness. Without exalted moods which in some way contain

religious faith--faith on the part of the individual in the eternal

values which he represents and in his own security in the hands of

fate, and in the immortality of the country which he serves, war could

not exist.

The mood of war always contains a religious sanction, and every

important religion sanctions war. This explicit relation between

religion and war is seen very early. Wherever there is ghost worship,

and the warriors justify war and fortify themselves for it by

believing that their ancestors still participate in the combats of

their children, and that in waging war they are doing a duty in

keeping up the traditional feuds of their race there is found the root

of the relation between war and religion. Every war is a holy war; it

is but a change in degree from these primitive wars in which the ideas

of ghosts must have had almost the clearness of reality to our modern

wars with their deeper but more indefinite religious sanctions. Since

war always creates the need of moral justification, the war mood at

all times tends to seek religious sanctions.

Christianity, the

doctrine of peace and good will, very readily lends its support to

war, since wars are almost invariably regarded as defensive by all who

participate in them. War in the service of the weak and endangered

can always invoke the spirit of Christianity. The logical ground for

this has been laid for us by many writers; Drawbridge (19), one of the

most recent, finds no support in Christianity for the doctrines of

pacifism. All nations, when they fight, fight for God, for liberty and

the right, with the implied belief that their own country has a

mission in the world, supported by divine authority.

All governments have in them a strain of theocracy. We see this in

many degrees and forms, from the original totemistic belief in descent

from animals that are also gods to the vaguest remnants of the habit

of interpreting national interests as guarded by divine powers that we

often see in the language of practical statesmen. The doctrine of the

divine rights of kings of course had its origin in that of divine

descent. The most striking revelation of the place such theories may

have, even in modern times and in enlightened nations, is to be seen

in the revival and deliberate use of the doctrine of divine descent as

a fundamental principle of the government and theory of State in the

New Japan. All nations hold something of this philosophy; God and

State are always related and all wars, whatever else they may be, are

waged in the service of religion and with the sanction of it. This

spirit is not wanting even in the most modern democracy.

The

historians of Germany have shown us to what an extent the theory of

the divinity of state and its divine mission may be intermingled with

practical politics and have helped to bring to light the psychology of

this movement in history.

Several writers, but especially Le Bon (42), have written about the

relation of mysticism to war. Le Bon said indeed that the main causes

of war, including the most recent one, are mystical causes. By

mysticism he means unconscious factors which are religious in quality

and which contain a race ideal which is both powerful and irrational.

German mysticism appears to have attracted much attention during the

years of the war. Germany has presented the picture, we are told, of

a people becoming dangerous by couching national ambition and honor in

terms of religion. This mysticism of the German contains a powerful

belief in race superiority, and in the supremacy of the culture of

their own nation, beliefs which have the clear marks of mysticism

about them. The traces of the theory of divine origin still cling to

them. Boutroux (13) says the Prussian State is a synthesis of the

divine and the human. Another writer observes that the Germans believe

in the altogether unique and quasi-divine excellence of the German

race, and of Germanism, and that the Germans have a new religion which

they believe in spreading by the sword. Some see in Germany a serious

demand for the revival of the religion of Odin and Thor, the religion

of conflict of primeval forces, and of the triumph of might. Literary

expressions of this religion are certainly to be found, and it may

fairly be maintained that Germany has never become Christianized to

the extent that most modern nations have.

That mysticism has been a large factor in the war spirit of the

Germans in the late war can hardly be doubted, or at least that a

religious element of some kind has played a great part in it. The war

began as Germany's holy war. A cult of State and of self-worship are

involved in it. If not, innumerable expressions of Germany's cause

among German writers are simply literary exaggerations.

The Germans

have believed that they are God's chosen people, that they represent

God, and since the German civilization grew up in antagonism to the

Graeco-Roman civilization, God must have adopted the one and discarded

the other. One German writer says that we must eliminate from our

belief the last drop of faith in the idea of a progressive movement of

humanity as a whole. Reality is represented in one nation at a time,

and the chosen nation is the leader of all the rest.

While such mysticism as this (if it be mysticism) is most conspicuous

in aristocratic and imperialistic nations, we find it elsewhere. It is

a powerful force in imperialistic Japan and in Russia.

We find it

everywhere in history in some form. In France it is still the "saintly

figure" of France that inspires the soldier and induces a religious

mood. There is no longer a vision of an empire of the future, perhaps,

and this mysticism of France has not in recent history shown itself in

the form of aggression, but French mysticism clings to the ideal and

the hope of a glorious future for a deathless France soon to be

renewed. All peoples that have declined or suffered an adverse fate,

even the pathetic remnants of the American Indians, expect the return

of their lost power. Such mysticism is, we may think, the only

condition under which national life in many cases can continue. The

religious or the mystical mood of nations is created by the need of

making belief dynamic, of overcoming doubts and fears.

Hence the

exaggerated and irrational claims peoples make in regard to the value

of their culture and about their mission on earth. By their mysticism

nations justify their aggressive wars and fortify themselves in their

defensive wars. Thus nations acquire a feeling of security. They

believe in their star of destiny. They feel that their life which is

of supreme value to the world cannot perish. It is this spirit that

nations take with them into battle. It is a mystic force, and this

mystic force is, in great part, we may believe, one of the by-products

of the tragedy of history. Faith and hope have one of their roots at

least in fear and pessimism.

_Moral Motives and War_

That the attitude of nations toward one another is not, generally

speaking, an ethical attitude and that moral principles do not

motivate the conduct of peoples we have already suggested. Sumner (70)

says that the whole history of mankind is a series of acts open to

doubt, dispute and criticism as to their right and justice.

Differences end in force, and the defeated side always protests that

the results are unjust. And yet wars are always conducted with moral

justification and in the belief that moral principles are involved.

These moral principles, however, are not the points of difference upon

which the beginning of wars depends. Nations never go to war for

purely moral reasons. Moral feeling may coincide with the interests of

state, and a defensive war may of course be conducted in the spirit of

deep moral right and duty, but plainly it is never the sense of right

and duty alone that is the motive of defense. Perhaps after all this

question of the moral element in the causes of war is a futile one,

and leads to casuistry. There are always political and other practical

questions involved, whenever strain occurs between nations, so that

wholly moral issues can never arise.

If wars are not moral in the making they are always justified morally,

whatever the motives may have been that caused them.

Without this

moral sanction it is doubtful whether wars could be conducted at all,

although this moral sanction may be based upon very superficial

grounds. The higher patriotic feeling runs, says Veblen (97), the

thinner may be the moral sanction that satisfies the public

conscience. On the other hand moral sentiment may often be strong and

deep in the minds of the masses of people in a nation, and the public

feeling of obligation to enter a war may be strong, but in general

such moral feeling does not lead to war. Righteous indignation lacks

initiative. Honor as moral obligation requires the aid of honor as

national pride and dignity. The relations among allies may at first

thought seem to be moral relations, but when we observe closely we see

that usually nations go to war together because their common interests

are endangered. When their common interests are not involved they

usually break treaties and so do not stay together.

Actions directed

offensively against one member of a coalition are usually directed

against the others, so that in most cases the allies of a nation have

no choice, but must defend themselves.

The relative importance of moral principles in the motives of war may

be observed by comparing the motives assigned by the nations that

participated in the late war with the motives which a study of the

history and political situations of these countries reveals. There are

wide disparities between these historical causes and the assigned

causes. These need not, however, lead us to take a cynical view of

history as many sociologists and students of politics do. We have as

yet no organized world in which moral principle can operate. The

world, we might say, is still infantile or immature. The world is

still unmoral. We cannot say that nationalism as the principle of the

conduct of nations is a wholly selfish principle as contrasted with a

moral or altruistic motive, since such an analogy with individual

morality fails to take into account the complex nature of nationalism,

and overlooks the social qualities of patriotism.

England's purpose in entering the war has been freely discussed in

England. The popular impression is that England declared war upon

Germany in order to defend Belgium and to keep her treaty obligations.

If we consider conduct in a certain abstraction from the practical

setting in which it is performed such a conclusion can be drawn. There

was a moral stirring in England, and several writers have commented

upon the fact that England subverted her own conscious purposes by her

unconscious and instinctive morality. There was a strong feeling

against war, even a widespread moral sense that England had become too

civilized to wage war. There was a shrinking from the economic

hardships that war would entail. Against these strong tendencies there

prevailed, at least in popular sentiment, a profound feeling that in

some way Germany's civilization was incompatible with England's, and

this feeling was in part of the nature of moral aversion. Dillion

(55), at least, sees a profound ethical motive in Italy in the late

war. After a pro-German party had won out in favor of war, he says, a

_deus ex machina_ in the shape of an indignant nation descended upon

the scene. But after making allowance for all moral feeling and the

unusual and dramatic manner in which moral issues, to a greater degree

than ever before in modern history, were brought to the front, we must

admit that the political and diplomatic interests and manners of

nations have taken their usual course in the war.

Nations have been

governed by the motives that have always dominated the relations of

groups to one another.

Germany presents the most glaring example of the contrast between

public opinion and expressed motives and political facts. Such

expressions as these: that Germany's ideal is one that does violence

to no one; that humanity and all human blessings stand under the

protection of German arms; that, where the German spirit obtains

supremacy, there freedom reigns; that in regard to England's downfall,

there can be but one opinion--it is the very highest mission of German

culture; that Germany's war is a holy war--such expressions as these,

which are psychologically explicable without questioning their

sincerity, seem out of harmony, to say the least, with what we know of

Germany's political aspirations. Germany's desire for England's

downfall does not appear to us to be based upon a moral motive;

Germany's war seems far from being a holy war, and it is hard to see

in it a means of spreading culture abroad in the world.

We cannot give

any place in the causes of this war to a moral desire to make the

world better. However much Germany may have been convinced that

Germany was destined to be a civilizing force in the world, the moral

obligation thus aroused, we may be sure, did not become the real

motive of the war.

The moral justifications of war are very numerous, and that this

belief in war has some effect upon the spirit of war and helps to

perpetuate it, and is not a mere reflection of the warlike spirit

itself, may of course be admitted. Many believe that war accomplishes

work in the world; war is a great organizing force.

There is also a

view that war is good as a moral stimulant, or as a creative moral

force. War is often regarded as the means of moral revival of a people

that has become sordid and dull. Schmitz (29) says that war gives

reality to a country. War strengthens national character, some think.

It purges nations. In war people grow hard but pure.

Irwin (25) says

that such war philosophy as this is to be heard broadly in Europe,

chiefly in Germany, but also in France and in England.

Mach (95) says

that disintegration takes place in times of peace.

Schoonmaker says

that war has taught men socialization. Again we hear that wars are

just and right because they are necessary. Redier (30) says that war

is a way of giving back courage to the men of our times.

This praise

of war which comes from the depths of feelings, we must suppose helps

to give continuity and force to these feelings.

_Institutional Factors_

If the spirit of war is to any extent educable, and is created in

national life and is not merely something instinctive, it is

presumably modified in one way and another by all those institutions

that are educational in their effect. Perhaps one of the most pressing

problems of education in the near future will be that of the relation

of education to war. We shall need to know what the school has done to

cause wars, what changes should be made in the future with reference

to this influence of education upon the fundamental motives of

national life. The schoolmaster has been indicted among other

instigators of war. We must see how much truth there is in this

allegation. We must understand also how the whole educational

process, as we may see it now after the war, may be made if possible

to become a greater factor in life than it has been in the past, if it

is at all an important element in the development and the control of

the psychic powers of nations.

Schmitz (29) says that the eighteenth century and the French

Revolution were dominated by the phrase, the nineteenth by money, and

that there was a danger that the twentieth century would be dominated

by the schoolmaster and by the concept, but that this danger is past

because life has become so full of realities. Russell says, we know,

that men fight because they have been governed in their beliefs and in

their conduct by authority. If this be true the authority exercised

upon the mind of the child by all his teachers may be suspected of

having been in one way or another an influence in creating the moral

attitudes that prevail in regard to war and peace. We have heard the

question raised as to whether in the past the teaching of history as

the story of wars, and the presentation of the facts of history from

the nationalistic point of view, have not been morally wrong.

German schools, and the method of public education the sinister

effects of which we have abundantly felt--that is, the propaganda,

show us educational phenomena that are psychologically of great

interest and which are also unique from the educational point of view.

The influence of schools seems in general so negative, and there is so

little connection between what is learned as fact and conduct in the

practical life that, even in the case of the German teaching of war

philosophy we must suspect that this teaching has been successful only

because it has gone with the strong tide of feeling in the popular

mind. That the German schools have directly and indirectly fostered

the development of ideas that lead in the direction of war there is no

doubt. Even more influential than the specific ideas that have been

implanted, is the spirit of these schools: it is their militaristic

and routine life, the great authority assumed by the teacher, the

specialization, that has helped to nourish the warlike spirit of

Germany, quite as much as the fact, for example, that Daniel's

Geography teaches that Germany is the heart of Europe, surrounded by

countries that were once a part of Germany and will be again.

German education, we say, seems to be unique in the extent to which it

influences public sentiment and national conduct. In general,

education has appeared among the influences that lead to war rather by

default of positive teaching than by anything positive it has done.

Even in Germany, we should say, the spirit of war has been made to

flourish less by the teaching of a narrow nationalism, by inculcating

hatred, and implanting wrong conceptions of German history than by

failing to provide youth with means of deep satisfaction, by failing

to coordinate deep desires of the individual, and to organize

individuals in a normal social life. This is true everywhere.

Education has not affected life as a whole, and it has not thus far

been an influence which, to any appreciable extent, has accelerated

the development of peoples in their especially national aspects and

relations. It has nowhere fostered any conception of the whole world

as an object of social feeling. It has everywhere accepted a certain

provincialism as natural and necessary, and has tacitly assumed that

national boundaries are the horizon of the practical life of the

child. The school has in fact failed to take advantage of its

unmatched opportunity to use the imagination of the child to develop

his social powers. Sociologists say that if sociologists had been more

diligent in spreading abroad information about the social life, the

great war would perhaps never have happened. That we may certainly

doubt; something more profound must be done by education than to

disseminate knowledge, if it would undertake to be a power in the

world and to do anything more than add its influence to the tendencies

of the day, or perhaps temporarily change the direction of these

tendencies.