The psychology of Nations by G.E. Partridge - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

CHAPTER X

POLITICAL AND HISTORICAL FACTORS

We think of political causes of war mainly as an aspect of the fact

that nations desire always certain _geographical objectives_. These

desires are represented in part by the policies of governments and

leaders, but we must also think of nations as a whole as having

desires, and as being moved by profound purposes. At once the question

arises whether we shall think of these political objectives, and the

wars the desires for them cause, as essentially the objects and the

work of individuals. Do individuals in any real sense create history?

This, of course, is a profound question and involves fundamental

theories of history. Shall we accept the "great man"

theory of

history, and say that history is mainly the work of a few who are able

to shape events with reference to policies of their own, or shall we

think that forces that determine history reside rather in the

instincts or desires of the common life of the people?

A psychological study of history inclines us to the belief that the

forces that make history are mainly forces that do not exist as

conscious purposes and are therefore not essentially political forces.

One of the conditions of leadership seems to be that the leader shall

seek his own personal ends and realize his own purposes for his

country only within the field of the traditional and common objectives

which are held by the people as a whole as their purpose in history.

These are the materials with which the leader must work.

Historically

his work may seem decisive. Psychologically it is to be regarded as a

complex effect of lawfully related social reactions. The motives of

leader and people must have large common factors. The leader holds

his power and his prestige by embodying in his own will and

representing in his own conscious policies the will of the people and

their idea of country as an historic entity. The leader is leader only

in so far as he is recognized as representing the will of the "herd."

As genius, this leader is manifestly creative, but the true genius in

statesmanship is even rarer than genius elsewhere. The great leader is

an artist. He must take certain vague or clear ambitions of the

people, must accept the nation's historic objectives as the

foundations of his policies, and working with these objects and

desires make his own page of history. His glory and his prestige

depend upon his fulfilling deep desires of his people.

The forces with

which he deals are plastic, but only within narrow limits. Leadership

at best is a fragile thing. However autocratic the power, it is after

all dependent upon the good will of the people, and the acceptance of

the leader as one who is serving the interests of the people.

When we consider the nature and the objects of the ambitions and

desires that the statesman or leader must fulfill, we see why the

relations of ruler to people are difficult to understand. Nations do

not know with clearness either what they desire or why at heart they

desire the objectives that seem of most importance.

People give

economic and political reasons, but the consciousness of nations is

subject to deep moods, and is influenced by remote events and

traditions. Nations have generic desires as well as specific ones.

They always crave empire; they all desire to have rank.

They are

always ambitious, jealous and watchful of one another.

These general

and more or less subconscious desires make their desires for specific

objects intense, but they also make them peculiarly irrational. The

heroic examples of history, hereditary emotions and the effects of

specific events in the history of peoples complicate their politics,

and often make rational politics impossible. Nations will not act in

their own best interests, because they are governed by irrational

motives. In this way certain disparities are often produced between

the people and their practical statesmen, but history seems to show us

that when these disparities exist in the region of fundamental desires

and policies it is the leader who must yield. History seems to show us

also that wars, coming in general out of the deeper motives of

nations, do not belong to such an extent as is often supposed to the

realm of politics. Political causes are often incidental causes and

determine the time and place of wars but do not create them. Cramb

(66) says that wars persist in spite of their unreason, because there

is something transcendental that supports them, and this transcendental purpose is the desire for empire. Powers (75) says that

nations fight for tangible things and also for intangible things. The

tangible things are existence, commerce, independence, territory;

nations also desire objects that are not useful, the worth of which

consists in their satisfaction of taste. The ambition to own colonies,

Powers thinks, is of this nature. Colonies are quite as much

ornamental as they are useful. They convey the feeling and impression

of power.

That these deep desires of nations as expressed in the ambition to

reach certain geographical objectives are exceedingly strong, often if

not always irrational, brutally arrogant and tenacious, the whole

course of history teaches us. These desires are indeed the forces

behind historical movements. They create politics and policies. War

preexists in these irrational purposes. These purposes are charged

with emotion, with prejudice, and tradition. It is with these motives

that all practical politics must contend, and these motives are the

forces that the statesman must use and make more rational.

The purposes of nations are usually if not always we say obscure and

deep, existing in the form of ideals and tendencies, and likely to

take the form of visions of empire wholly unrealizable.

And yet there

are always certain perfectly clear objectives upon which all the

force of these half understood motives impinge. These objectives may

or may not be economically rational or morally justifiable. We always

know with certainty certain of these objectives for which any nation

will if necessary fight. These objectives have often a long history

behind them. They are surrounded by tradition, sincerely and even

religiously sought. They are ideal objects which nations feel they

have a right to possess. Every nation apparently believes itself the

logical possessor of something it does not now hold (99). All peoples

have their longings for these possessions, which are their vision of a

greater self. These objects are often desired for reasons that are

clear enough to all; but they are also often but the symbols of deeper

desires. As such, nations act toward them with almost instinctive

compulsion.

We may suppose that no great historical event is ever enacted that is

not determined more by traditional desires than by conscious politics.

A thousand years of strife have provided the motives for the great

European war. Memories of time-honored objectives have arisen in the

consciousness of many peoples, and these memories cannot be recalled

without exciting passions that make all rational politics unavailing.

Europe has been fighting over again her battles of the past, and at

the moment of the present writing is carrying them into the conference

of peace. The plans of statesmen and the intrigues of finance have but

little success in contending against these forces. Since the leaders

themselves are not free from the prejudices and the compulsion of

traditions and the unconscious desires and deep impulses which move

their people, they can with but dubious success bring international

politics into the sphere of reason. They do not represent merely the

selfish desires of their people. They are not merely spokesmen of the

interests of class or individual. They are embodiments of the whole

history of their nations.

All history, and all the present relations of nations to one another

may, of course, be considered in terms of the desires for specific

objectives caused by the imperial desires of peoples, these desires

themselves being regarded as a sum of motives, the effects of past

political relations, and containing both rational and irrational

elements. The world is a vast field of stress in which the powers at

work are national wills rather than political forces as the projects

of rulers and the diplomats. These powers, when fully aroused, are

quite beyond the control of statesmen acting in their ordinary

capacities, and their final issues no historian ought now to try to

predict. History has been full of surprises because of the nature of

the forces which create history, and these surprises seem to have been

sometimes the greatest for those who were most intimately concerned in

making history. Events seldom run smoothly according to well laid

plans.

It would not fall within the scope of a psychological study of war to

describe or analyze the complex system of strains that exist in the

world to-day, and to point out the conditions that led to the great

war would be for the most part unnecessary, since they must be obvious

to all. The main items in such a study of history, however, may well

be recalled to mind. One would need to show the effects of England's

irresistible development through several centuries; the struggle for

the control of the Mediterranean; Germany's efforts to extend her

empire toward the East, and the closing of doors against Germany's

advance; Russia's pressure upon the Teutonic peoples, the ancient and

terrible dread of Russia on the part of the nations of Western Europe,

the shadow under which Turkey, Germany, and England had lived because

of the presence of the great Slavic state, with its mysticism, its

dynastic ambitions and its great growth force, its need of open ports,

and vital interest in the amalgamation of the South Slavic peoples,

and the determination to own Constantinople and to succeed to the

place of the Turkish Empire. We should need to take into account the

long history of the struggle for colonies, the colonial trust of

Russia, England and France, the ambitions of France for empire in

Africa, the operations of French finance in the Balkans and elsewhere,

Austria's aggressive hatred of Serbia, and her effort to prevent the

revival of Poland, the conflicts of Germany and Austria with Italy in

regard to the Ægean and the Adriatic and their shores, the fierce

irredentism of Italy, and the ambitions of Italy that have brought her

into conflict with the Teutonic powers and with Turkey, all the

conflicting purposes and ambitions of Greece, Roumania, Bulgaria, and

Serbia, and the added strain in the Balkans because of the vital

interests of all the Great Powers there, and many other conflicts and

causes of conflicts. These conflicts we see repeated in kind in the

relations of Japan, China and Russia and the other powers interested

in the geography of Asia, and in the waters of the Pacific, and once

more in the growing strains between the East and the West (99).

Taking our world as we find it, and viewing the nature of nations in

the light of their history and of their persistent antagonisms, one

might readily believe that the causes of war and war itself will

continue into a far future. No war, the pessimist might well argue,

will destroy national vitality or neutralize the many points of

strain. There may be great coalitions and even Leagues of Nations, but

these may only make wars more terrible when they come.

The friendship

of nations will still be insecure and shifting. The great strategic

points of the world will remain. Small countries will continue to be

ambitious and jealous of one another. Island countries will still be

faced by coasts that contain possibilities of danger.

The

Constantinoples and the Gibraltars will remain; Suez and Panama will

be left, and Verdun will still be something more than a historic

memory (99).

That these objectives might all be brought into a permanent state of

equilibrium, by some ideal world politics, that nations _ought_ to

abandon their ideas of empire or at least see how crude these ideas

are, how out of relation to our modern ideas of value, and how out of

place in a practical world--all this we can readily understand, but

who will expect nations to become very different from what they are

now, and who shall say how many imperial eggs there are in the world

yet to be hatched? There are many ways of justifying these

ambitions--Germany justifies hers by reason, and the researches of her

great historians--the Treitschkes and the Mommsens; Russia bases her

claims upon her religion and her ethos; Japan brings her divinity and

her traditions, her vitality and her intelligence; England offers her

justice and above all her proved genius for government as a

justification of empire. But after all, these desires for empire lie

deeper than proof and reason can go. Poetic, dramatic and religious

elements enter into them. There are geniuses among nations. The

creative force in a nation is its life force, its essence and its

reality. In some sense the desire to be an empire is the whole meaning

of a nation, for without the ambition to be supreme, peoples, some of

them, would be nothing. It is the vision of empire, however forlorn

and hopeless, that keeps many nations alive, perhaps all. Nations seek

to express in visible form the evidence of their inner and potential

greatness. The historic and time-honored art of empire-building is the

only art they know. Whether this is the tragedy of history, the

world's fate and the condemnation of it to perpetual warfare--or is

but a term in the logic by which nations rise to other and higher

forms; or finally is a crime or a mistake which it is within the power

of the will of man to abandon or amend--these are problems of the

philosophy of history.

_Historical Causes_

Historical causes of war are in part the sequences of events that the

political causes of war produce (political as the causes inherent in

the wills of nations), and we must suppose they are mainly this.

History, from this point of view, is the working out of the motives or

the desires contained in these national wills. The causes of our late

war, for example, are to be sought mainly in the wills of the great

powers that are concerned in it. Economic forces, the laws of the

growth of nations (both psychological and physical laws), the

conditions of the geographical distributions of peoples over the

earth--all these are involved in the cause of wars.

There are also

great personages whose actions must to some extent be considered apart

from these general laws; these personages contribute factors to the

causation of any given war that are not entirely inherent in the laws

of growth or the psychology of nations. Shall we say also that there

are fortuitous factors, historical causes that are not contained in

any logic of human desires? Can we say, perhaps, that these fortuitous

causes are indeed the main causes--in a word that wars are not

desired, mainly, but are the product, indeed, either of the mere logic

of chance, or of a design that transcends human will altogether? Are

wars willed, or are they the results of the complex, the illogical and

uncontrollable factors of the world's existence and movement? These

may not be practical problems, but they are serious problems, since in

the end they implicate the whole of philosophy.

What place shall we give, in the laws of history, to the sudden and

chance turn of affairs; to the quick shift of the wheels of fortune;

to the incidents, the accidents, the mis-judgments of rulers and the

slips of the diplomats? Are wars after all a product of the logic of

life, or are they mere fortuitous syntheses of events which in their

particular combination make a total that is not involved, either as

desire or as tendency, in the sum of the particulars that enter into

the whole? How completely, in a word, do the interests and purposes of

nations determine wars? May we speak of motives that always tend to

produce wars, but never seem to will them?

History seems to show us that wars are less directly willed than we

have sometimes supposed, and perhaps that there is a large element of

chance in them as regards a given war at any time and in any place.

War in general is inherent in, or is a natural effect of, the laws of

development of nations. Wars as historical events are not completely

describable in terms of these laws. It is the old contrast between the

historical and the scientific explanation of things that appears here.

Nations have deep and vague desires, we say. They want satisfaction of

their honor; they crave a dramatic life, even military prestige and

glory, but we do not often find war itself definitely willed. The

desires of nations, we repeat, tend to be too fundamental to be

specific. Their specific desires are indeed and for that reason likely

to be contradictory. They desire both war and peace at the same time,

and have interests that may be served by both. They live in indecision

like individuals. Motives conflict. They hesitate, and doubt, and

fear. They shrink from taking the plunge. It requires the sharp and

clear event, the chance event, most often, to precipitate them into

wars. It is always to-morrow that they are to wage wars.

So wars do

not usually occur by the rational plans and devices of any man or any

historical sequences of men, we may believe, and it is a question

whether wars are very often intended in a real sense by any one. Wars

occur as crises in events. The strains that produce them are certainly

inherent in the relations of nations at all times, and even in the

motives of personal politics, but in general these relations as

consciously governed relations are in the direction of seeking the

greatest advantage with the least show of force. The conditions must

all be present, both the match and the powder, before war can take

place. There must be a condition of strain, having certain

psychological features none of which can be missing, the condition

being something complex and not readily analyzable, at any given time.

In addition to these strains events must take place which, in all

their appearances, are fortuitous.

One might argue from this that the cure of war consists in eternal

watchfulness to see that the match does not touch the powder, that we

must watch these events that precipitate wars and safeguard peoples

from being affected by them. This, of course, is more or less the

method of diplomacy; to some minds the league of nations is a device

for doing this on a larger and more systematic scale.

But when we

study history and see what these war-causing incidents are, how

numerous and how variable, we can see that diplomacy and statesmanship

undertake an impossible task when they try to steer the world along

its narrow historical course, with only historical landmarks for

guides.

The war that is so vividly in mind now furnishes us with an

illustration of the complexity of the causes of war, and allows us to

see clearly contrasting views of the causal factors in great wars in

general. We see here a closely fitting series of events, each in

itself having but little reference to the great crisis, all fitting

together, and for want of any one of which, if one takes the purely

historical view, we might suppose the war would never have happened,

or might have been postponed indefinitely. If Venezelos, to go back no

further than that, had remained in Crete and had been content to be an

island politician, would not the course of events in the Balkans have

been very different? Out of his course came events which no one could

have foreseen, but which, without similar actions on the part of

individuals producing other links in the chain, would not have taken

place. If some diplomat or some foreign office had made a decision

slightly different from what was actually decided; if the three

emperors had had a little more reliable information about one

another; if the statisticians of the German service had computed a

little better England's resources, and had put the moral factor into

the sum--would the war have happened at all?

In this direction, of course, lies the chaos of history and its

madness--and also its philosophy. We may be driven on the one hand to

think of all history as a matter of the chance relations of

individuals and of detached particular events, having significance as

a series but never planned or controlled as a whole, or we may resort

to the opposite way of thinking, and say that all of history, in every

particular and detail, is divinely planned and prearranged, and each

event fits into a rational whole. This, of course, is our final

problem of history, we say, as it is the final problem of every

question that considers life as concrete events having value precisely

as the particular sequence that it is--when we view life historically,

in a word, rather than by the methods of the quantitative sciences, or

by the genetic methods such as are used mainly in the psychological

sciences, and which we may say stand between history and the sciences

of matter.