Reading for Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction to Philosophical Thinking by Lee Archie and John G. Archie - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

Decision Sciences: How the Game Is Played (http://www.nsf.gov \

/od/lpa/news/publicat/nsf0050/decision/decision.htm). National Science

Foundation. An introductory overview of utility and game theory,

including a discussion of its limitations.

Jeremy Bentham (http://www.utm.edu/research/ep/b/bentham.htm). In-

ternet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. An excellent encyclopedic overview

of Bentham’s life and thought.

From the Bentham’s The Commonplace Book

“The greatest happiness for the greatest number is the foundation of

morals and legislation.”

Houses of Parliament from the River, Library of Congress

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

263

Chapter 23. “Happiness Is the Greatest Good” by Jeremy Bentham

Topics Worth Investigating

1. Utilitarianism is often cited as a consequentialist or teleological

ethics. Consequentialism is the doctrine that the morally correct

action is an action maximizing the good; hence, consequentialism

is not so much concerned with the means used as it is concerned

with probable outcomes, ends, or goals of activities. Utilitarianism

holds only pleasure or happiness is an intrinsic good, whereas

consequentialism implies that there may well be other intrinsic

goods, such as knowledge, that some persons might not desire. In any

case, the question arises whether or not something instrumentally

bad can lead to something intrinsically good. Do we actually judge

the goodness of an action only by its consequences? Do the ends

justify the means in some cases? Construct and analyze a few

examples in support of your view.

2. Bentham seems to equate happiness with pleasure. Are there signifi-

cant differences between pleasure and happiness? Do the characteris-

tics of time, sensation, or emotion differ for each? Can one be happy

while in painful circumstances? Provide some specific examples in

support of some of the distinctions you notice.

3. If pleasure for Bentham is intrinsically good, would anything count

as being intrinsically bad? Bentham is often called a hedonist. He-

donism is the ethical view that pleasure alone is an intrinsic good

for persons. Does Bentham believe the descriptive generalization that

all persons in fact do seek pleasure (a view called psychological he-

donism), or does he believe that all persons should or ought to seek

pleasure, even though some persons might not (a view called ethical

hedonism)? Relate your answer to Bentham’s theory of motives.

4. When Bentham explains the principle of utility in terms of the in-

dividual and in terms of the community, does he commit the fallacy

of composition?3 He writes above, Chapter I, V, “It is in vain to talk

3.

The fallacy of composition involves the implication that a characteristic of a part

of a something is attributable as the same characteristic of the whole. For example, the

inference, “ Since human beings are mortal, someday the human race must come to

an end” is an instance of this fallacy. If all the players on an all-star team are excellent players, it would not logically follow that the team is an excellent team. In other

words, in the fallacy of composition, the name of the characteristic in the predicate is

264

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 23. “Happiness Is the Greatest Good” by Jeremy Bentham

of the interest of the community, without understanding what is the

interest of the individual.”

5. Vince Lombardi, the legendary football coach has said, “Show me a

good loser, and I’ll show you a loser” and “Winning isn’t everything;

it’s the only thing.” Compare these statements to “As a man thinketh

in his heart so is he.”4 What would be Bentham’s reaction to the later

statement? Has Bentham overlooked anything in asserting that mo-

tives are not an exception to his theory?

6. Attempt to do a detailed calculation of the total amount of pleasure

and pain comparing sleeping-in with attending philosophy class. If

you are sleeping, then would it follow that you are experiencing nei-

ther pleasure nor pain because you are not conscious? In your calcu-

lation, be sure to include the extent of the pleasure you bring to the

other members of the class. If you have problems, try assigning plea-

sure as an ordinal relation rather than a cardinal relation, or check the

Internet to see if anyone else has attempted calculating some specific

instances.

used ambiguously.

4.

Proverbs, 23: 7.

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

265

index-284_1.jpg

Chapter 24

“Slave and Master Morality”

by Friedrich Nietzsche

Nietzsche, Thoemmes

About the author. . .

Friedrich Nietzsche’s (1844-1900) intuitive and visceral rejection of the

economics, politics, and science of European civilization in the 19th cen-

tury led him to predict, “There will be wars such as there have never

been on earth before.” His dominant aphoristic style of writing and his

insistence of truth as convenient fiction, or irrefutable error, have puzzled

philosophers who think in traditional ways. Nietzsche seeks to undermine

the traditional quest of philosophy as recounted by Russell and, instead,

seeks to reveal the objects of philosophy (truth, reality, and value) to be

based on the “Will to Power.”

266

Chapter 24. “Slave and Master Morality” by Friedrich Nietzsche

About the work. . .

In Beyond Good and Evil 1 Nietzsche detects two types of morality mixed

not only in higher civilization but also in the psychology of the individ-

ual. Master-morality values power, nobility, and independence: it stands

“beyond good and evil.” Slave-morality values sympathy, kindness, and

humility and is regarded by Nietzsche as “herd-morality.” The history of

society, Nietzsche believes, is the conflict between these two outlooks: the

herd attempts to impose its values universally but the noble master tran-

scends their “mediocrity.”

From the reading. . .

Every elevation of the type man, has hitherto been the work of an

aristocratic society and so. . . requiring slavery in one form or another.”

Ideas of Interest from Beyond Good and Evil

1. How does Nietzsche explain the origins of society? What are the es-

sential characteristics of a healthy society?

2. Nietzsche states that a consequence of the “Will to Power” is the ex-

ploitation of man by man, and this exploitation is the essence of life.

What does he mean by this statement? Is exploitation a basic biologi-

cal function of living things?

3. What does Nietzsche mean when he says that the noble type of man

is “beyond good and evil” and is a creator of values?

4. Explain in some detail the differences among the master-morality and

the slave-morality. Are these concepts useful in the analysis of inter-

personal dynamics?

1.

Friedrich Nietzsche. Beyond Good and Evil. Trans. by Helen Zimmern (1909-

1913), 257-261.

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

267

Chapter 24. “Slave and Master Morality” by Friedrich Nietzsche

5. Explain Nietzsche’s insight into the psychology of vanity. Why is

vanity essential to the slave-morality? How does it relate to the in-

dividual’s need for approval? Is Nietzsche noting that the vanity of

an individual is a direct consequence of the individual’s own sense of

inferiority?

The Reading Selection from Beyond Good

and Evil

[Origin of Aristocracy]

257. Every elevation of the type “man,” has hitherto been the work of an

aristocratic society and so it will always be—a society believing in a long

scale of gradations of rank and differences of worth among human beings,

and requiring slavery in some form or other. Without the pathos of dis-

tance, such as grows out of the incarnated difference of classes, out of the

constant out-looking and down-looking of the ruling caste on subordinates

and instruments, and out of their equally constant practice of obeying and

commanding, of keeping down and keeping at a distance—that other more

mysterious pathos could never have arisen, the longing for an ever new

widening of distance within the soul itself, the formation of ever higher,

rarer, further, more extended, more comprehensive states, in short, just the

elevation of the type “man,” the continued “self-surmounting of man,” to

use a moral formula in a supermoral sense.

To be sure, one must not resign oneself to any humanitarian illusions about

the history of the origin of an aristocratic society (that is to say, of the pre-

liminary condition for the elevation of the type “man”): the truth is hard.

Let us acknowledge unprejudicedly how every higher civilization hitherto

has originated! Men with a still natural nature, barbarians in every terrible

sense of the word, men of prey, still in possession of unbroken strength

of will and desire for power, threw themselves upon weaker, more moral,

more peaceful races (perhaps trading or cattle-rearing communities), or

upon old mellow civilizations in which the final vital force was flickering

out in brilliant fireworks of wit and depravity. At the commencement, the

noble caste was always the barbarian caste: their superiority did not con-

sist first of all in their physical, but in their psychical power—they were

268

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 24. “Slave and Master Morality” by Friedrich Nietzsche

more complete men (which at every point also implies the same as “more

complete beasts”).

[Higher Class of Being]

258. Corruption—as the indication that anarchy threatens to break out

among the instincts, and that the foundation of the emotions, called “life,”

is convulsed—is something radically different according to the organiza-

tion in which it manifests itself. When, for instance, an aristocracy like

that of France at the beginning of the Revolution, flung away its privi-

leges with sublime disgust and sacrificed itself to an excess of its moral

sentiments, it was corruption:—it was really only the closing act of the

corruption which had existed for centuries, by virtue of which that aristoc-

racy had abdicated step by step its lordly prerogatives and lowered itself to

a function of royalty (in the end even to its decoration and parade-dress).

The essential thing, however, in a good and healthy aristocracy is that it

should not regard itself as a function either of the kingship or the common-

wealth, but as the significance highest justification thereof—that it should

therefore accept with a good conscience the sacrifice of a legion of indi-

viduals, who, for its sake, must be suppressed and reduced to imperfect

men, to slaves and instruments. Its fundamental belief must be precisely

that society is not allowed to exist for its own sake, but only as a foun-

dation and scaffolding, by means of which a select class of beings may

be able to elevate themselves to their higher duties, and in general to a

higher existence: like those sun-seeking climbing plants in Java—they are

called Sipo Matador,—which encircle an oak so long and so often with

their arms, until at last, high above it, but supported by it, they can unfold

their tops in the open light, and exhibit their happiness.

[Life Denial]

259. To refrain mutually from injury, from violence, from exploitation,

and put one’s will on a par with that of others: this may result in a cer-

tain rough sense in good conduct among individuals when the necessary

conditions are given (namely, the actual similarity of the individuals in

amount of force and degree of worth, and their co-relation within one or-

ganization). As soon, however, as one wished to take this principle more

generally, and if possible even as the fundamental principle of society, it

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

269

Chapter 24. “Slave and Master Morality” by Friedrich Nietzsche

would immediately disclose what it really is—namely, a Will to the denial

of life, a principle of dissolution and decay.

Here one must think profoundly to the very basis and resist all sentimen-

tal weakness: life itself is essentially appropriation, injury, conquest of

the strange and weak, suppression, severity, obtrusion of peculiar forms,

incorporation, and at the least, putting it mildest, exploitation;—but why

should one for ever use precisely these words on which for ages a dis-

paraging purpose has been stamped?

Even the organization within which, as was previously supposed, the indi-

viduals treat each other as equal—it takes place in every healthy aristoc-

racy—must itself, if it be a living and not a dying organization, do all that

towards other bodies, which the individuals within it refrain from doing to

each other it will have to be the incarnated Will to Power, it will endeav-

our to grow, to gain ground, attract to itself and acquire ascendancy—not

owing to any morality or immorality, but because it lives, and because

life is precisely Will to Power. On no point, however, is the ordinary con-

sciousness of Europeans more unwilling to be corrected than on this mat-

ter, people now rave everywhere, even under the guise of science, about

coming conditions of society in which “the exploiting character” is to be

absent—that sounds to my ears as if they promised to invent a mode of life

which should refrain from all organic functions.

From the reading. . .

“The noble type of man regards himself as a determiner of values; he

does not require to be approved of. . . he is a creator of values.”

“Exploitation” does not belong to a depraved, or imperfect and primitive

society it belongs to the nature of the living being as a primary organic

function, it is a consequence of the intrinsic Will to Power, which is pre-

cisely the Will to Life—Granting that as a theory this is a novelty—as

a reality it is the fundamental fact of all history let us be so far honest

towards ourselves!

270

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 24. “Slave and Master Morality” by Friedrich Nietzsche

[Master Morality]

260. In a tour through the many finer and coarser moralities which have

hitherto prevailed or still prevail on the earth, I found certain traits recur-

ring regularly together, and connected with one another, until finally two

primary types revealed themselves to me, and a radical distinction was

brought to light.

There is master-morality and slave-morality,—I would at once add, how-

ever, that in all higher and mixed civilizations, there are also attempts at the

reconciliation of the two moralities, but one finds still oftener the confu-

sion and mutual misunderstanding of them, indeed sometimes their close

juxtaposition—even in the same man, within one soul. The distinctions of

moral values have either originated in a ruling caste, pleasantly conscious

of being different from the ruled—or among the ruled class, the slaves and

dependents of all sorts.

In the first case, when it is the rulers who determine the conception “good,”

it is the exalted, proud disposition which is regarded as the distinguishing

feature, and that which determines the order of rank. The noble type of

man separates from himself the beings in whom the opposite of this ex-

alted, proud disposition displays itself he despises them. Let it at once be

noted that in this first kind of morality the antithesis “good” and “bad”

means practically the same as “noble” and “despicable”,—the antithesis

“good” and “evil” is of a different origin. The cowardly, the timid, the in-

significant, and those thinking merely of narrow utility are despised; more-

over, also, the distrustful, with their constrained glances, the self-abasing,

the dog-like kind of men who let themselves be abused, the mendicant flat-

terers, and above all the liars:—it is a fundamental belief of all aristocrats

that the common people are untruthful. “We truthful ones”—the nobility

in ancient Greece called themselves.

It is obvious that everywhere the designations of moral value were at first

applied to men; and were only derivatively and at a later period applied

to actions; it is a gross mistake, therefore, when historians of morals start

with questions like, “Why have sympathetic actions been praised?” The

noble type of man regards himself as a determiner of values; he does not

require to be approved of; he passes the judgment: What is injurious to

me is injurious in itself; he knows that it is he himself only who confers

honour on things; he is a creator of values. He honours whatever he recog-

nizes in himself: such morality equals self-glorification. In the foreground

there is the feeling of plenitude, of power, which seeks to overflow, the

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

271

Chapter 24. “Slave and Master Morality” by Friedrich Nietzsche

happiness of high tension, the consciousness of a wealth which would fain

give and bestow:—the noble man also helps the unfortunate, but not—or

scarcely—out of pity, but rather from an impulse generated by the super-

abundance of power. The noble man honours in himself the powerful one,

him also who has power over himself, who knows how to speak and how

to keep silence, who takes pleasure in subjecting himself to severity and

hardness, and has reverence for all that is severe and hard. “Wotan placed a

hard heart in my breast,” says an old Scandinavian Saga: it is thus rightly

expressed from the soul of a proud Viking. Such a type of man is even

proud of not being made for sympathy; the hero of the Saga therefore adds

warningly: “He who has not a hard heart when young, will never have

one.” The noble and brave who think thus are the furthest removed from

the morality which sees precisely in sympathy, or in acting for the good of

others, or in dèintèressement, the characteristic of the moral; faith in one-

self, pride in oneself, a radical enmity and irony towards “selflessness,”

belong as definitely to noble morality, as do a careless scorn and precau-

tion in presence of sympathy and the “warm heart.”

It is the powerful who know how to honour, it is their art, their domain for

invention. The profound reverence for age and for tradition—all law rests

on this double reverence,— the belief and prejudice in favour of ancestors

and unfavourable to newcomers, is typical in the morality of the powerful;

and if, reversely, men of “modern ideas” believe almost instinctively in

“progress” and the “future,” and are more and more lacking in respect

for old age, the ignoble origin of these “ideas” has complacently betrayed

itself thereby.

A morality of the ruling class, however, is more especially foreign and ir-

ritating to present-day taste in the sternness of its principle that one has

duties only to one’s equals; that one may act towards beings of a lower

rank, towards all that is foreign, just as seems good to one, or “as the heart

desires,” and in any case “beyond good and evil”: it is here that sympathy

and similar sentiments can have a place. The ability and obligation to ex-

ercise prolonged gratitude and prolonged revenge—both only within the

circle of equals,—artfulness in retaliation, refinement of the idea in friend-

ship, a certain necessity to have enemies (as outlets for the emotions of

envy, quarrelsomeness, arrogance—in fact, in order to be a good friend):

all these are typical characteristics of the noble morality, which, as has

been pointed out, is not the morality of “modern ideas,” and is therefore at

present difficult to realize, and also to unearth and disclose.

272

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 24. “Slave and Master Morality” by Friedrich Nietzsche

[Slave Morality]

It is otherwise with the second type of morality, slave-morality. Suppos-

ing that the abused, the oppressed, the suffering, the unemancipated, the

weary, and those uncertain of themselves should moralize, what will be

the common element in their moral estimates? Probably a pessimistic sus-

picion with regard to the entire situation of man will find expression, per-

haps a condemnation of man, together with his situation. The slave has an

unfavourable eye for the virtues of the powerful; he has a skepticism and

distrust, a refinement of distrust of everything “good” that is there hon-

oured—he would fain persuade himself that the very happiness there is

not genuine. On the other hand, those qualities which serve to alleviate the

existence of sufferers are brought into prominence and flooded with light;

it is here that sympathy, the kind, helping hand, the warm heart, patience,

diligence, humility, and friendliness attain to honour; for here these are the

most useful qualities, and almost the only means of supporting the burden

of existence. Slave-morality is essentially the morality of utility.

Here is the seat of the origin of the famous antithesis “good” and

“evil”:—power and dangerousness are assumed to reside in the evil, a

certain dreadfulness, subtlety, and strength, which do not admit of being

despised. According to slave-morality, therefore, the “evil” man arouses

fear; according to master-morality, it is precisely the “good” man who

arouses fear and seeks to arouse it, while the bad man is regarded as the

despicable being.

The contrast attains its maximum when, in accordance with the logical

consequences of slave-morality, a shade of depreciation—it may be slight

and well-intentioned—at last attaches itself to the “good” man of this

morality; because, according to the servile mode of thought, the good man

must in any case be the safe man: he is good-natured, easily deceived, per-

haps a little stupid, un bonhomme. Everywhere that slave-morality gains

the ascendancy, language shows a tendency to approximate the significa-

tions of the words “good” and “stupid.”

[Creation of Values]

A l