Reading for Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction to Philosophical Thinking by Lee Archie and John G. Archie - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

choice. If you are a Christian, you will say, Consult a priest; but there are

collaborationists, priests who are resisters and priests who wait for the tide

to turn: which will you choose? Had this young man chosen a priest of the

resistance, or one of the collaboration, he would have decided beforehand

the kind of advice he was to receive. Similarly, in coming to me, he knew

what advice I should give him, and I had but one reply to make. You are

288

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 25. “Man Makes Himself” by Jean-Paul Sartre

free, therefore choose that is to say, invent. No rule of general morality

can show you what you ought to do: no signs are vouchsafed in this world.

The Catholics will reply, “Oh, but they are!” Very well; still, it is I myself,

in every case, who have to interpret the signs. While I was imprisoned, I

made the acquaintance of a somewhat remarkable man, a Jesuit, who had

become a member of that order in the following manner. In his life he had

suffered a succession of rather severe setbacks. His father had died when

he was a child, leaving him in poverty, and he had been awarded a free

scholarship in a religious institution, where he had been made continually

to feel that he was accepted for charity’s sake, and, in consequence, he had

been denied several of those distinctions and honours which gratify chil-

dren. Later, about the age of eighteen, he came to grief in a sentimental af-

fair; and finally, at twenty-two—this was a trifle in itself, but it was the last

drop that overflowed his cup—he failed in his military examination. This

young man, then, could regard himself as a total failure: it was a sign—but

a sign of what? He might have taken refuge in bitterness or despair. But

he took it—very cleverly for him—as a sign that he was not intended for

secular success, and that only the attainments of religion, those of sanctity

and of faith, were accessible to him. He interpreted his record as a message

from God, and became a member of the Order. Who can doubt but that this

decision as to the meaning of the sign was his, and his alone? One could

have drawn quite different conclusions from such a series of reverses—as,

for example, that he had better become a carpenter or a revolutionary. For

the decipherment of the sign, however, ho bears the entire responsibility.

That is what “abandonment” implies, that we ourselves decide our being.

And with this abandonment goes anguish.

[Despair]

As for “despair,” the meaning of this expression is extremely simple. It

merely means that we limit ourselves to a reliance upon that which is

within our wills, or within the sum of the probabilities which render our

action feasible. Whenever one wills anything, there are always these ele-

ments of probability. If I am counting upon a visit from a friend, who may

be coming by train or by tram, I presuppose that the train will arrive at the

appointed time, or that the tram will not be derailed. I remain in the realm

of possibilities; but one does not rely upon any possibilities beyond those

that are strictly concerned in one’s action. Beyond the point at which the

possibilities under consideration cease to affect my action, I ought to dis-

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

289

Chapter 25. “Man Makes Himself” by Jean-Paul Sartre

interest myself. For there is no God and no prevenient design, which can

adapt the world and all its possibilities to my will. When Descartes said,

“Conquer yourself rather than the world,” what he meant was, at bottom,

the same—that we should act without hope.. . .

From the reading. . .

“ The doctrine I am presenting before you is precisely the opposite of

this, since it declares that there is no reality except in action. It goes

further, indeed, and adds, ‘Man is nothing else but what he purposes,

he exists only in so far as he realizes himself, he is therefore nothing

else but the sum of his actions, nothing else but what his life is.’”

[You Are What You Live]

Quietism is the attitude of people who say, “Let others do what I cannot

do.” The doctrine I am presenting before you is precisely the opposite of

this, since it declares that there is no reality except in action. It goes further,

indeed, and adds, “Man is nothing else but what he purposes, he exists only

in so far as he realizes himself, he is therefore nothing else but the sum of

his actions, nothing else but what his life is.” Hence we can well under-

stand why some people are horrified by our teaching. For many have but

one resource to sustain them in their misery, and that is to think, “Circum-

stances have been against me, I was worthy to be something much better

than I have been. I admit I have never had a great love or a great friendship;

but that is because I never met a man or a woman who were worthy of it; if

I have not written any very good books, it is because I had not the leisure

to do so; or, if I have had no children to whom X could devote myself it

is because I did not find the man I could have lived with. So there remains

within me a wide range of abilities, inclinations and potentialities, unused

but perfectly viable, which endow me with a worthiness that could never

be inferred from the mere history of my actions.” But in reality and for the

existentialist, there is no love apart from the deeds of love; no potentiality

of love other than that which is manifested in loving; there is no genius

other than that which is expressed in works of art. The genius of Proust

is the totality of the works of Proust; the genius of Racine is the series of

290

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 25. “Man Makes Himself” by Jean-Paul Sartre

his tragedies, outside of which there is nothing. Why should we attribute

to Racine the capacity to write yet another tragedy when that is precisely

what he—did not write? In life, a man commits himself, draws his own

portrait and there is nothing but that portrait. No doubt this thought may

seem comfortless to one who has not made a success of his life. On the

other hand, it puts everyone in a position to understand that reality alone

is reliable; that dreams, expectations and hopes serve to define a man only

as deceptive dreams abortive hopes, expectations unfulfilled; that is to say,

they define him negatively, not positively. Nevertheless, when one says,

“You are nothing else but what you live,” it does not imply that an artist

is to be judged solely by his works of art, for a thousand other things con-

tribute no less to his definition as a man. What we mean to say is that

a man is no other than a series of undertakings, that he is the sum, the

organization, the set of relations that constitute these undertakings.. . .

We have now, I think, dealt with a certain number of the reproaches against

existentialism. You have seen that it cannot be regarded as a philosophy of

quietism since it defines man by his action; nor as a pessimistic description

of man, for no doctrine is more optimistic, the destiny of man is placed

within himself. Nor is it an attempt to discourage man from action since it

tells him that there is no hope except in his action, and that the one thing

which permits him to have life is the deed. Upon this level therefore, what

we are considering is an ethic of action and self-commitment. However,

we are still reproached, upon these few data, for confining man within his

individual subjectivity. There again people badly misunderstand us.

[Subjectivity]

Our point of departure is, indeed, the subjectivity of the individual, and

that for strictly philosophic reasons. It is not because we are bourgeois,

but because we seek to base our teaching upon the truth, and not upon a

collection of fine theories, full of hope but lacking real foundations. And

at the point of departure there cannot be any other truth than this, I think,

therefore I am, which is the absolute truth of consciousness as it attains

to itself. Every theory which begins with man, outside of this moment of

self-attainment, is a theory which thereby suppresses the truth, for outside

of the Cartesian cogito, all objects are no more than probable, and any

doctrine of probabilities which is not attached to a truth will crumble into

nothing. In order to define the probable one must possess the true. Before

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

291

Chapter 25. “Man Makes Himself” by Jean-Paul Sartre

there can be any truth whatever, then, there must be an absolute truth, and

there is such a truth which is simple, easily attained and within the reach

of everybody; it consists in one’s immediate sense of one’s self.

[Intersubjectivity]

In the second place, this theory alone is compatible with the dignity of

man, it is the only one which does not make man into an object. All kinds

of materialism lead one to treat every man including oneself as an ob-

ject—that is, as a set of pre-determined reactions, in no way different from

the patterns of qualities and phenomena which constitute a table, or a chair

or a stone. Our aim is precisely to establish the human kingdom as a pat-

tern of values in distinction from the material world. But the subjectivity

which we thus postulate as the standard of truth is no narrowly individual

subjectivism, for as we have demonstrated, it is not only one’s own self

that one discovers in the cogito, but those of others too. Contrary to the

philosophy of Descartes, contrary to that of Kant, when we say "I think"

we are attaining to ourselves in the presence of the other, and we are just

as certain of the other as we are of ourselves. Thus the man who discovers

himself directly in the cogito also discovers all the others, and discovers

them as the condition of his own existence. He recognizes that he cannot

be anything (in the sense in which one says one is spiritual, or that one is

wicked or jealous) unless others recognize him as such. I cannot obtain any

truth whatsoever about myself, except through the mediation of another.

The other is indispensable to my existence, and equally so to any knowl-

edge I can have of myself. Under these conditions, the intimate discovery

of myself is at the same time the revelation of the other as a freedom which

confronts mine. and which cannot think or will without doing so either for

or against me. Thus, at once, we find ourselves in a world which is, let us

say, that of “inter-subjectivity” It is in this world that man has to decide

what he is and what others are.

[Human Condition]

Furthermore, although it is impossible to find in each and every man a

universal essence that can be called human nature, there is nevertheless a

human universality of condition. It is not by chance that the thinkers of

today are so much more ready to speak of the condition than of the nature

292

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 25. “Man Makes Himself” by Jean-Paul Sartre

of man. By his condition they understand, with more or less clarity, all

the limitations which à priori define man’s fundamental situation in the

universe. His historical situations are variable: man may be born a slave in

a pagan society or may be a feudal baron, or a proletarian. But what never

vary are the necessities of being in the world, of having to labor and to die

there. These limitations are neither subjective nor objective, or rather there

is both a subjective and an objective aspect of them. Objective, because

we meet with them everywhere and they are everywhere recognizable:

and subjective because they are lived and are nothing if man does not

live them—if, that is to say, he does not freely determine himself and his

existence in relation to them. And, diverse though man’s purpose may be,

at least none of them is wholly foreign to me, since every human purpose

presents itself as an attempt either to surpass these limitations, or to widen

them, or else to deny or to accommodate oneself to them. Consequently

every purpose, however individual it may be, is of universal value. Every

purpose, even that of a Chinese, an Indian or a Negro, can be understood

by a European. To say it can be understood, means that the European of

1945 may be striving out of a certain situation towards the same limitations

in the same way, and that he may reconceive in himself the purpose of the

Chinese, of the Indian or the African. In every purpose there is universality,

in this sense that every purpose is comprehensible to every man. Not that

this or that purpose defines man for ever, but that it may be entertained

again and again. There is always some way of understanding an idiot,

a child, a primitive man or a foreigner if one has sufficient information.

In this sense we may say that there is a human universality, but it is not

something given; it is being perpetually made. I make this universality in

choosing myself; I also make it by understanding the purpose of any other

man, of whatever epoch. This absoluteness of the act of choice does not

alter the relativity of each epoch.

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

293

index-312_1.jpg

Chapter 25. “Man Makes Himself” by Jean-Paul Sartre

Paris, France, Refugee Camp WW II, Library of Congress

What is at the very heart and center of existentialism, is the absolute char-

acter of the free commitment, by which every man realizes himself in re-

alizing a type of humanity—a commitment always understandable, to no

matter whom in no matter what epoch—and its bearing upon the relativity

of the cultural pattern which may result from such absolute commitment.

One must observe equally the relativity of Cartesianism and the absolute

character of the Cartesian commitment. In this sense you may say, if you

like, that every one of us makes the absolute by breathing, by eating, by

sleeping or by behaving in any fashion whatsoever. There is no differ-

ence between free being—being as self-committal, as existence choosing

its essence—and absolute being. And there is no difference whatever be-

tween being as an absolute, temporarily localized that is, localized in his-

tory—and universally intelligible being.

294

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 25. “Man Makes Himself” by Jean-Paul Sartre

From the reading. . .

“What is at the very heart and center of existentialism, is the absolute

character of the free commitment, by which every man realizes himself

in realizing a type of humanity. . . ”

[Moral Choice]

This does not completely refute the charge of subjectivism Indeed that

objection appears in several other forms, of which the first is as follows.

People say to us, “Then it does not matter what you do,” and they say this

in various ways. First they tax us with anarchy; then they say, “You cannot

judge others, for there is no reason for preferring one purpose to another;”

finally, they may say, “Everything being merely voluntary in this choice

of yours, you give away with one hand what you pretend to gain with the

other.” These three are not very serious objections. As to the first, to say

that it does not matter what you choose is not correct. In one sense choice

is possible, but what is not possible is not to choose. I can always choose,

but I must know that if I do not choose, that is still a choice. This, although

it may appear merely formal, is of great importance as a limit to fantasy

and caprice. For, when I confront a real situation—for example, that I am

a sexual being, able to have relations with a being of the other sex and able

to have children—I am obliged to choose my attitude to it, and in every

respect I bear the responsibility of the choice which, in committing myself,

also commits the whole of humanity. Even if my choice is determined by

no à priori value whatever, it can have nothing to do with caprice: and if

anyone thinks that this is only Gide’s theory of the acte gratuit over again,

he has failed to see the enormous difference between this theory and that

of Gide. Gide does not know what a situation is, his “act” is one of pure

caprice. In our view, on the contrary, man finds himself in an organized

situation in which he is himself involved: his choice involves mankind in

its entirety, and he cannot avoid choosing. Either he must remain single,

or he must marry without having children, or he must marry and have

children. In any case, and whichever—he may choose, it is impossible

for him, in respect of this situation, not to take complete responsibility.

Doubtless he chooses without reference to any pre-established value, but

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

295

Chapter 25. “Man Makes Himself” by Jean-Paul Sartre

it is unjust to tax him with caprice. Rather let us say that the moral choice

is comparable to the construction of a work of art.

But here I must at once digress to make it quite clear that we are not

propounding an æsthetic morality, for our adversaries are disingenuous

enough to reproach us even with that. I mention the work of art only by

way of comparison. That being understood, does anyone reproach an artist,

when he paints a picture, for not following rules established à priori? Does

one ever ask what is the picture that he ought to paint? As everyone knows,

there is no pre-defined picture for him to make; the artist applies himself

to the composition of a picture, and the picture that ought to be made is

precisely that which he will have made. As everyone knows, there are no

æsthetic values à priori, but there are values which will appear in due

course in the coherence of the picture, in the relation between the will to

create and the finished work. No one can tell what the painting of tomor-

row will be like; one cannot judge a painting until it is done. What has

that to do with morality? We are in the same creative situation. We never

speak of a work of art as irresponsible; when we are discussing a canvas

by Picasso, we understand very well that the composition became what

it is at the time when he was painting it, and that his works are part and

parcel of his entire life.

It is the same upon the plane of morality. There is this in common between

art and morality, that in both we have to do with creation and invention.

We cannot decide à priori what it is that should be done. I think it was

made sufficiently clear to you in the case of that student who came to

see me, that to whatever ethical system he might appeal, the Kantian or

any other, he could find no sort of guidance whatever; he was obliged

to invent the law for himself. Certainly we cannot say that this man, in

choosing to remain with his mother—that is, in taking sentiment, personal

devotion and concrete charity as his moral foundations—would be making

an irresponsible choice, nor could we do so if he preferred the sacrifice of

going away to England. Man makes himself; he is not found ready-made;

he makes himself by the choice of his morality, and he cannot but choose

a morality, such is the pressure of circumstances upon him. We define man

only in relation to his commitments; it is therefore absurd to reproach us

for irresponsibility in our choice.

In the second place, people say to us, “You are unable to judge others.”

This is true in one sense and false in another. It is true in this sense, that

whenever a man chooses his purpose and his commitment in all clearness

296

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

Chapter 25. “Man Makes Himself” by Jean-Paul Sartre

and in all sincerity, whatever that purpose may be, it is impossible for him

to prefer another. It is true in the sense that we do not believe in progress.

Progress implies amelioration; but man is always the same, facing a situa-

tion which is always changing. and choice remains always a choice in the

situation. The moral problem has not changed since the time when it was

a choice between slavery and anti-slavery. . .

[Authenticity and Self-Deception]

We can judge, nevertheless, for, as I have said, one chooses in view of oth-

ers, and in view of others one chooses himself. One can judge, first—and

perhaps this is not a judgment of value, but it is a logical judgment—that

in certain cases choice is founded upon an error, and in others upon the

truth. One can judge a man by saying that he deceives himself. Since we

have defined the situation of man as one of free choice, without excuse and

without help, any man who takes refuge behind the excuse of his passions,

or by inventing some deterministic doctrine, is a self-deceiver. One may

object: “But why should he not choose to deceive himself?” I reply that

it is not for me to judge him morally, but I define his self-deception as an

error. Here one cannot avoid pronouncing a judgment of truth. The self-

deception is evidently a falsehood, because it is a dissimulation of man’s

complete liberty of commitment. Upon this same level, I say that it is also a

self-deception if I choose to declare that certain values are incumbent upon

me; I am in contradiction with myself if I will these values and at the same

time say that they impose themselves upon me. If anyone says to me, “And

what if I wish to deceive myself?” I answer, “There is no reason why you

should not, but I declare that you are doing so, and that the attitude of strict

consistency alone is that of good faith.” Furthermore, I can pronounce a

moral judgment. For I declare that freedom, in respect of concrete circum-

stances, can have no other end and aim but itself; and when once a man

has seen that values depend upon himself, in that state of forsakenness he

can will only one thing, and that is freedom as the foundation of all val-

ues. That does not mean that he wills it in the abstract: it simply means

that the actions of men of good faith have, as their ultimate significance,

the quest of freedom itself as such. A man who belongs to some commu-

nist or revolutionary society wills certain concrete ends, which imply the

will to freedom, but that freedom is willed in community. We will freedom

for freedom’s sake, in and through particular circumstances. And in thus

willing freedom, we discover that it depends entirely upon the freedom of

Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

297

Chapter 25. “Man Makes Himself” by Jean-Paul Sartre

others and that the freedom of others depends upon our own. Obviously,

freedom as the definition of a man does not depend upon others, but as

soon as there is a commitment, I am obliged to will the liberty of others at

the same time as my own. I cannot make liberty my aim unless I make that

of others equally my aim. Consequently, when I recognize, as entirely au-

thentic, that man is a being whose existence precedes his essence, and that

he is a free being who cannot, in any circumstances, but will his freedom,

at the same time I realize that I cannot not will the freedom of others. Thus,

in the name of that will to freedom which is implied in freedom itself, I can

form judgments upon those who seek to hide from themselves the wholly

voluntary nature of their existence and its complete freedom. Those who

hide from this total freed